-
1
-
-
28744443738
-
Is virtue possible?
-
Michael Slote, "Is Virtue Possible?" Analysis 42, no. 2 (1982): 72;
-
(1982)
Analysis
, vol.42
, Issue.2
, pp. 72
-
-
Slote, M.1
-
2
-
-
0004141126
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
Bernard Williams, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), 124.
-
(1993)
Shame and Necessity
, pp. 124
-
-
Williams, B.1
-
3
-
-
33846797464
-
Sanity and the metaphysics of responsibility
-
ed. J. Christman Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Susan Wolf, "Sanity and the Metaphysics of Responsibility," in The Inner Citadel: Essays on Autonomy, ed. J. Christman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 146.
-
(1989)
The Inner Citadel: Essays on Autonomy
, pp. 146
-
-
Wolf, S.1
-
6
-
-
84937310048
-
Culture, responsibility, and affected ignorance
-
(hereinafter referred to in main text and notes as "AI")
-
Michele Moody-Adams, "Culture, Responsibility, and Affected Ignorance," Ethics 104, no. 2 (1994): 291-309 (hereinafter referred to in main text and notes as "AI");
-
(1994)
Ethics
, vol.104
, Issue.2
, pp. 291-309
-
-
Moody-Adams, M.1
-
8
-
-
42149143582
-
The idea of moral progress
-
Michele Moody-Adams, "The Idea of Moral Progress," Metaphilosophy 30, no. 3 (1999): 168-83.
-
(1999)
Metaphilosophy
, vol.30
, Issue.3
, pp. 168-183
-
-
Moody-Adams, M.1
-
9
-
-
0000114587
-
Social structures and their threats to moral agency
-
A similar stance is taken by Alasdair MacIntyre in "Social Structures and Their Threats to Moral Agency," Philosophy 74, no. 289 (1999): 311-29.
-
(1999)
Philosophy
, vol.74
, Issue.289
, pp. 311-329
-
-
MacIntyre, A.1
-
11
-
-
84856929184
-
-
MacIntyre argues that there are societies "whose structures to some large degree inhibit the exercise of the powers of moral agency." But he also maintains that the diminished responsibility defense fails even for institutional wrongdoers in such societies, because they "are not passive victims," and therefore "share in responsibility for having made themselves into the kind of diminished agent that they are." See MacIntyre, "Social Structures," 327.
-
Social Structures
, pp. 327
-
-
MacIntyre1
-
12
-
-
0003465228
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press n. 21 and n. 28
-
G. A. Cohen, If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), 211-12, n. 21 and n. 28.
-
(2000)
If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich?
, pp. 211-212
-
-
Cohen, G.A.1
-
13
-
-
79959980440
-
Culture and responsibility: A reply to moody-adams
-
Paul Benson, "Culture and Responsibility: A Reply to Moody-Adams," Journal of Social Philosophy 32, no. 4 (2001): 610.
-
(2001)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.32
, Issue.4
, pp. 610
-
-
Benson, P.1
-
15
-
-
84945761953
-
Aristotle and the anonymous opponents of slavery
-
ed. M. Finley London: Cass
-
Giuseppe Cambiano, "Aristotle and the Anonymous Opponents of Slavery," in Classical Slavery, ed. M. Finley (London: Cass, 1987), 23.
-
(1987)
Classical Slavery
, pp. 23
-
-
Cambiano, G.1
-
17
-
-
0004290807
-
-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
Jürgen Habermas's notion of opening oneself to persuasion by "the unforced force of the better argument" nicely captures the ideal form of autonomous judgment. See Jürgen Habermas, Justification and Application (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993), 163.
-
(1993)
Justification and Application
, pp. 163
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
18
-
-
84888627960
-
Responsibility, convention, and the role of ideas in history
-
Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press
-
Thomas Haskell, "Responsibility, Convention, and the Role of Ideas in History," in Objectivity Is Not Neutrality (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1998), 302.
-
(1998)
Objectivity Is Not Neutrality
, pp. 302
-
-
Haskell, T.1
-
19
-
-
9744281136
-
Convention and hegemonic interest in the debate over antislavery
-
Thomas Haskell, "Convention and Hegemonic Interest in the Debate over Antislavery," The Ameri - can Historical Review 92, no. 4 (1987): 848.
-
(1987)
The Ameri - Can Historical Review
, vol.92
, Issue.4
, pp. 848
-
-
Haskell, T.1
-
20
-
-
0004150971
-
-
(New York: Vintage)
-
According to Ronald Dworkin, the "paradigm liberal position on abortion" holds that abortion "means the extinction of a human life that has already begun, and for that reason alone involves a serious moral cost," but one which is "nevertheless morally justified for a variety of serious reasons" (32-33). Ronald Dworkin, Life's Dominion (New York: Vintage).
-
Life's Dominion
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
22
-
-
0004224658
-
-
Oxford: Blackwell
-
Wittgenstein, On Certainty (Oxford: Blackwell, 1975), makes a similar point against Cartesian doubt: One does not doubt that something is the case merely by avowing, contemplating, or entertaining propositions of the form "I doubt that X," however intensely one concentrates on the proposition.
-
(1975)
On Certainty
-
-
Wittgenstein1
-
23
-
-
0038075132
-
-
London: Routledge
-
See, for example, Raimond Gaita, A Common Humanity (London: Routledge, 2000), 181-83, who chastises Singer not so much for his (tentative) conclusions, but for being prepared even to broach what he (Gaita) regards as "the morally unthinkable."
-
(2000)
A Common Humanity
, pp. 181-183
-
-
Gaita, R.1
-
24
-
-
5844331558
-
Animal rights and feminist theory
-
ed. G. Gaard Philadelphia: Temple University Press
-
As an antidote to the perceived coldness and emotional detachment of conventional consequentialist and deontological arguments for animal liberation, Josephine Donovan voices the decidedly non-reflective exhortation: "We should not kill, eat, torture, and exploit animals because they do not want to be so treated, and we know that. If we listen, we can hear them." Josephine Donovan, "Animal Rights and Feminist Theory," in Ecofeminism, ed. G. Gaard (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1993), 185.
-
(1993)
Ecofeminism
, pp. 185
-
-
Donovan, J.1
-
25
-
-
84873383565
-
-
See Wittgenstein's extended discussion of the concepts, Philosophical Investigations, 193-208.
-
Philosophical Investigations
, pp. 193-208
-
-
-
26
-
-
0004150971
-
-
Dworkin, Life's Dominion, argues that practically all "liberals" and antiabortionists share the same core values and moral principles (the "sacredness" of human life), but apply them in different ways.
-
Life's Dominion
-
-
Dworkin1
-
28
-
-
0026180513
-
Virtue theory and abortion
-
In her article "Virtue Theory and Abortion," Philosophy and Public Affairs 20, no. 3 (1991): 223-46, Rosalind Hursthouse rejects traditional approaches to the morality of abortion that argue over its permissibility as such, advocating instead a contextually sensitive approach that attends to the conditions under which abortion in particular cases manifests vice or virtue.
-
(1991)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.20
, Issue.3
, pp. 223-246
-
-
-
29
-
-
0004313047
-
-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
See John Searle, Rationality in Action (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001), 68.
-
(2001)
Rationality in Action
, pp. 68
-
-
Searle, J.1
-
30
-
-
0010110035
-
Deciding to believe
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See Bernard Williams, "Deciding to Believe," in Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973).
-
(1973)
Problems of the Self
-
-
Williams, B.1
|