메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 39, Issue 1, 2008, Pages 96-115

Institutional wrongdoing and moral perception

(1)  Pleasants, Nigel a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78650322228     PISSN: 00472786     EISSN: 14679833     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9833.2007.00413.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (21)

References (31)
  • 1
    • 28744443738 scopus 로고
    • Is virtue possible?
    • Michael Slote, "Is Virtue Possible?" Analysis 42, no. 2 (1982): 72;
    • (1982) Analysis , vol.42 , Issue.2 , pp. 72
    • Slote, M.1
  • 2
    • 0004141126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Bernard Williams, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), 124.
    • (1993) Shame and Necessity , pp. 124
    • Williams, B.1
  • 3
    • 33846797464 scopus 로고
    • Sanity and the metaphysics of responsibility
    • ed. J. Christman Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Susan Wolf, "Sanity and the Metaphysics of Responsibility," in The Inner Citadel: Essays on Autonomy, ed. J. Christman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 146.
    • (1989) The Inner Citadel: Essays on Autonomy , pp. 146
    • Wolf, S.1
  • 6
    • 84937310048 scopus 로고
    • Culture, responsibility, and affected ignorance
    • (hereinafter referred to in main text and notes as "AI")
    • Michele Moody-Adams, "Culture, Responsibility, and Affected Ignorance," Ethics 104, no. 2 (1994): 291-309 (hereinafter referred to in main text and notes as "AI");
    • (1994) Ethics , vol.104 , Issue.2 , pp. 291-309
    • Moody-Adams, M.1
  • 8
    • 42149143582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea of moral progress
    • Michele Moody-Adams, "The Idea of Moral Progress," Metaphilosophy 30, no. 3 (1999): 168-83.
    • (1999) Metaphilosophy , vol.30 , Issue.3 , pp. 168-183
    • Moody-Adams, M.1
  • 9
    • 0000114587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social structures and their threats to moral agency
    • A similar stance is taken by Alasdair MacIntyre in "Social Structures and Their Threats to Moral Agency," Philosophy 74, no. 289 (1999): 311-29.
    • (1999) Philosophy , vol.74 , Issue.289 , pp. 311-329
    • MacIntyre, A.1
  • 11
    • 84856929184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MacIntyre argues that there are societies "whose structures to some large degree inhibit the exercise of the powers of moral agency." But he also maintains that the diminished responsibility defense fails even for institutional wrongdoers in such societies, because they "are not passive victims," and therefore "share in responsibility for having made themselves into the kind of diminished agent that they are." See MacIntyre, "Social Structures," 327.
    • Social Structures , pp. 327
    • MacIntyre1
  • 13
    • 79959980440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Culture and responsibility: A reply to moody-adams
    • Paul Benson, "Culture and Responsibility: A Reply to Moody-Adams," Journal of Social Philosophy 32, no. 4 (2001): 610.
    • (2001) Journal of Social Philosophy , vol.32 , Issue.4 , pp. 610
    • Benson, P.1
  • 15
    • 84945761953 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle and the anonymous opponents of slavery
    • ed. M. Finley London: Cass
    • Giuseppe Cambiano, "Aristotle and the Anonymous Opponents of Slavery," in Classical Slavery, ed. M. Finley (London: Cass, 1987), 23.
    • (1987) Classical Slavery , pp. 23
    • Cambiano, G.1
  • 17
    • 0004290807 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Jürgen Habermas's notion of opening oneself to persuasion by "the unforced force of the better argument" nicely captures the ideal form of autonomous judgment. See Jürgen Habermas, Justification and Application (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993), 163.
    • (1993) Justification and Application , pp. 163
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 18
    • 84888627960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Responsibility, convention, and the role of ideas in history
    • Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press
    • Thomas Haskell, "Responsibility, Convention, and the Role of Ideas in History," in Objectivity Is Not Neutrality (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1998), 302.
    • (1998) Objectivity Is Not Neutrality , pp. 302
    • Haskell, T.1
  • 19
    • 9744281136 scopus 로고
    • Convention and hegemonic interest in the debate over antislavery
    • Thomas Haskell, "Convention and Hegemonic Interest in the Debate over Antislavery," The Ameri - can Historical Review 92, no. 4 (1987): 848.
    • (1987) The Ameri - Can Historical Review , vol.92 , Issue.4 , pp. 848
    • Haskell, T.1
  • 20
    • 0004150971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (New York: Vintage)
    • According to Ronald Dworkin, the "paradigm liberal position on abortion" holds that abortion "means the extinction of a human life that has already begun, and for that reason alone involves a serious moral cost," but one which is "nevertheless morally justified for a variety of serious reasons" (32-33). Ronald Dworkin, Life's Dominion (New York: Vintage).
    • Life's Dominion
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 22
    • 0004224658 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Wittgenstein, On Certainty (Oxford: Blackwell, 1975), makes a similar point against Cartesian doubt: One does not doubt that something is the case merely by avowing, contemplating, or entertaining propositions of the form "I doubt that X," however intensely one concentrates on the proposition.
    • (1975) On Certainty
    • Wittgenstein1
  • 23
    • 0038075132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • See, for example, Raimond Gaita, A Common Humanity (London: Routledge, 2000), 181-83, who chastises Singer not so much for his (tentative) conclusions, but for being prepared even to broach what he (Gaita) regards as "the morally unthinkable."
    • (2000) A Common Humanity , pp. 181-183
    • Gaita, R.1
  • 24
    • 5844331558 scopus 로고
    • Animal rights and feminist theory
    • ed. G. Gaard Philadelphia: Temple University Press
    • As an antidote to the perceived coldness and emotional detachment of conventional consequentialist and deontological arguments for animal liberation, Josephine Donovan voices the decidedly non-reflective exhortation: "We should not kill, eat, torture, and exploit animals because they do not want to be so treated, and we know that. If we listen, we can hear them." Josephine Donovan, "Animal Rights and Feminist Theory," in Ecofeminism, ed. G. Gaard (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1993), 185.
    • (1993) Ecofeminism , pp. 185
    • Donovan, J.1
  • 25
    • 84873383565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Wittgenstein's extended discussion of the concepts, Philosophical Investigations, 193-208.
    • Philosophical Investigations , pp. 193-208
  • 26
    • 0004150971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, Life's Dominion, argues that practically all "liberals" and antiabortionists share the same core values and moral principles (the "sacredness" of human life), but apply them in different ways.
    • Life's Dominion
    • Dworkin1
  • 28
    • 0026180513 scopus 로고
    • Virtue theory and abortion
    • In her article "Virtue Theory and Abortion," Philosophy and Public Affairs 20, no. 3 (1991): 223-46, Rosalind Hursthouse rejects traditional approaches to the morality of abortion that argue over its permissibility as such, advocating instead a contextually sensitive approach that attends to the conditions under which abortion in particular cases manifests vice or virtue.
    • (1991) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.20 , Issue.3 , pp. 223-246
  • 29
    • 0004313047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See John Searle, Rationality in Action (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001), 68.
    • (2001) Rationality in Action , pp. 68
    • Searle, J.1
  • 30
    • 0010110035 scopus 로고
    • Deciding to believe
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Bernard Williams, "Deciding to Believe," in Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973).
    • (1973) Problems of the Self
    • Williams, B.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.