메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn , Issue , 2008, Pages 246-285

Exploitation and placebo controls

(1)  Hawkins, Jennifer S a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78649363530     PISSN: None     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book    
DOI: None     Document Type: Chapter
Times cited : (11)

References (36)
  • 1
    • 84890592968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AZT is the brand name for the antiretroviral drug zidovudine. A more detailed description of the case appears in the introduction to this volume
    • AZT is the brand name for the antiretroviral drug zidovudine. A more detailed description of the case appears in the introduction to this volume.
  • 2
    • 17144448291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AIDS Research in Africa: Juggling Risks and Hopes
    • October 9
    • H. French, "AIDS Research in Africa: Juggling Risks and Hopes," New York Times, October 9, 1997.
    • (1997) New York Times
    • French, H.1
  • 3
    • 0030775618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ethics of Clinical Research in the Third World
    • Marcia Angell, "The Ethics of Clinical Research in the Third World," New England Journal of Medicine 337 (1997): 847-49;
    • (1997) New England Journal of Medicine , vol.337 , pp. 847-849
    • Angell, M.1
  • 4
    • 0030767808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unethical Trials of Interventions to Reduce Perinatal Transmission of the Human Immunodeficiency Virus in Developing Countries
    • These two pieces sparked the debate over the AZT trials.While many other articles have been critical of these trials, they are too numerous to list here.
    • Peter Lurie and Sidney Wolfe, "Unethical Trials of Interventions to Reduce Perinatal Transmission of the Human Immunodeficiency Virus in Developing Countries," New England Journal of Medicine 337 (1997): 853-55. These two pieces sparked the debate over the AZT trials.While many other articles have been critical of these trials, they are too numerous to list here.
    • (1997) New England Journal of Medicine , vol.337 , pp. 853-855
    • Lurie, P.1    Wolfe, S.2
  • 5
    • 84890683496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The asterisk is there to remind the reader that "placebo case," as I am using it, only refers to a subset of trials that employ placebo controls. There is a huge general literature on the ethics of placebo-controlled trials, but I am not aiming to engage that entire debate
    • The asterisk is there to remind the reader that "placebo case," as I am using it, only refers to a subset of trials that employ placebo controls. There is a huge general literature on the ethics of placebo-controlled trials, but I am not aiming to engage that entire debate.
  • 6
    • 84890658525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For detailed descriptions of AZT and Surfaxin, see chapter 2 of this volume
    • For detailed descriptions of AZT and Surfaxin, see chapter 2 of this volume.
  • 7
    • 84890725205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See chapter 1 of this volume for a more in-depth explanation of these trial designs and their typical uses
    • See chapter 1 of this volume for a more in-depth explanation of these trial designs and their typical uses.
  • 8
    • 84890603245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is important to emphasize that the first question-whether PCTs are really necessary in a given case-is not a simple one. The question opens up a bitter, on-going methodological dispute that has an important normative component, since in clinical research the degree of methodological rigor we insist upon has real human effects. In real life, many people find it difficult to separate the two questions I outline here.Nonetheless, it is conceptually possible to separate them and morally beneficial to do so.
    • It is important to emphasize that the first question-whether PCTs are really necessary in a given case-is not a simple one. The question opens up a bitter, on-going methodological dispute that has an important normative component, since in clinical research the degree of methodological rigor we insist upon has real human effects. In real life, many people find it difficult to separate the two questions I outline here.Nonetheless, it is conceptually possible to separate them and morally beneficial to do so.
  • 9
    • 84890638746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the discussion of the case by Lurie and Wolfe in Ethical Issues in International Biomedical Research: A Casebook, ed., New York:Oxford University Press
    • See the discussion of the case by Lurie and Wolfe in Ethical Issues in International Biomedical Research: A Casebook, ed. James V. Lavery, Christine Grady,Elizabeth R.Wahl, and Ezekiel J. Emanuel (New York:Oxford University Press, 2007), 159-70.
    • (2007) , pp. 159-170
    • Lavery, J.V.1    Christine Grady, E.R.W.2    Emanuel, E.J.3
  • 10
    • 0004118270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exploitation
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Alan Wertheimer, Exploitation (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 10.
    • (1996) , pp. 10
    • Wertheimer, A.1
  • 11
    • 27544477607 scopus 로고
    • Exploitation
    • All further references to Wertheimer are to this book unless stated otherwise. See also, in The Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. L. C. Becker (New York: Garland Press
    • All further references to Wertheimer are to this book unless stated otherwise. See also Richard Arneson, "Exploitation," in The Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. L. C. Becker (New York: Garland Press, 1992), 350.
    • (1992) , pp. 350
    • Arneson, R.1
  • 12
    • 84972057828 scopus 로고
    • Exploitation
    • For a theorist who does not accept even this rather general account of exploitation, see
    • For a theorist who does not accept even this rather general account of exploitation, see Allen Wood, "Exploitation," Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995): 135-58.
    • (1995) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.12 , pp. 135-158
    • Wood, A.1
  • 13
    • 84890633800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, some of the subjects in Nicole's trial very likely did not give fully informed consent (revealing that fact appears to have been the primary journalistic motive for the article in note 1). However, I shall set aside those concerns here
    • For example, some of the subjects in Nicole's trial very likely did not give fully informed consent (revealing that fact appears to have been the primary journalistic motive for the article in note 1). However, I shall set aside those concerns here.
  • 14
    • 84890781717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though see note 29 below about coercion
    • Though see note 29 below about coercion.
  • 15
    • 84890700773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wertheimer has also used this case as an example of coercion where the baseline against which threats are distinguished from offers is moralized. Exploitation, at 53. On the relationship between my analysis and coercion, see note 29
    • Wertheimer has also used this case as an example of coercion where the baseline against which threats are distinguished from offers is moralized. Exploitation, at 53. On the relationship between my analysis and coercion, see note 29.
  • 16
    • 4644265447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Standards for Research in Developing Countries: From 'Reasonable Availability' to 'Fair Benefits
    • See, e.g., Participants in the 2001 Conference on Ethical Aspects of Research in Developing Countries
    • See, e.g., Participants in the 2001 Conference on Ethical Aspects of Research in Developing Countries, "Moral Standards for Research in Developing Countries: From 'Reasonable Availability' to 'Fair Benefits,'" Hastings Center Report 34, no. 3 (2004): 17-27.
    • (2004) Hastings Center Report , vol.34 , Issue.3 , pp. 17-27
  • 17
    • 84890736842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The relationship need not always be formed by explicit agreement, or by some prior personal engagement between doctor and patient, as long as there are institutional norms that make it clear when one person becomes another's patient
    • The relationship need not always be formed by explicit agreement, or by some prior personal engagement between doctor and patient, as long as there are institutional norms that make it clear when one person becomes another's patient.
  • 18
    • 85015592230 scopus 로고
    • Guilty Bystanders? On the Legitimacy of Duty to Rescue Statutes
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., Alison McIntyre, "Guilty Bystanders? On the Legitimacy of Duty to Rescue Statutes," Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (1994): 157-91;
    • (1994) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.23 , pp. 157-191
    • McIntyre, A.1
  • 19
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What We Owe to Each Other
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), 224 -28;
    • (1998)
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 20
    • 0003439620 scopus 로고
    • Harm to Others
    • Oxford:Oxford University Press
    • and Joel Feinberg, Harm to Others (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 1984), 126-86.
    • (1984) , pp. 126-186
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 21
    • 84890662522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feinberg notes that although many European countries have instituted laws that penalize people who fail to carry out easy rescues, Anglo-American law has generally not done so. But Anglo-American law does penalize someone in a fiduciary relationship who allows the other party to suffer an easily preventable injury. Hence, Anglo-American law reflects the same distinction I make in the text between two types of positive obligations to help
    • Feinberg notes that although many European countries have instituted laws that penalize people who fail to carry out easy rescues, Anglo-American law has generally not done so. But Anglo-American law does penalize someone in a fiduciary relationship who allows the other party to suffer an easily preventable injury. Hence, Anglo-American law reflects the same distinction I make in the text between two types of positive obligations to help.
  • 22
    • 84890642398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this chapter I use "obligation" in the wide sense that carries no implication that if A is morally obligated to do X for B, B has a right against A that A do X
    • In this chapter I use "obligation" in the wide sense that carries no implication that if A is morally obligated to do X for B, B has a right against A that A do X.
  • 23
    • 84890700321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As I use it here, "role overlap" does not refer to the general idea of one person occupying both roles (which remains common), but the more specific idea of occupying both roles in relation to the same person. This is certainly less common than it used to be
    • As I use it here, "role overlap" does not refer to the general idea of one person occupying both roles (which remains common), but the more specific idea of occupying both roles in relation to the same person. This is certainly less common than it used to be.
  • 24
    • 0000164463 scopus 로고
    • Role Obligations
    • I follow Hardimon and Daniels in seeing the role obligations of physicians as contractual: the obligated individual consents to adopt the entire role, even though the specific obligations she acquires form a cluster or group among which she is not free to pick and choose. See
    • I follow Hardimon and Daniels in seeing the role obligations of physicians as contractual: the obligated individual consents to adopt the entire role, even though the specific obligations she acquires form a cluster or group among which she is not free to pick and choose. See M. Hardimon, "Role Obligations," Journal of Philosophy 91 (1994): 333-63;
    • (1994) Journal of Philosophy , vol.91 , pp. 333-363
    • Hardimon, M.1
  • 25
    • 0026133955 scopus 로고
    • Duty to Treat or Right to Refuse?
    • Norman Daniels, "Duty to Treat or Right to Refuse?" Hastings Center Report 21, no. 2 (1991): 36-47.
    • (1991) Hastings Center Report , vol.21 , Issue.2 , pp. 36-47
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 26
    • 84890609902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This ought to be qualified a bit.There is room to disagree about whether, even in resource-rich environments, a researcher's obligations are the same as a physician's or simply similar to them (and constrained by them). But I will not pursue the point here
    • This ought to be qualified a bit.There is room to disagree about whether, even in resource-rich environments, a researcher's obligations are the same as a physician's or simply similar to them (and constrained by them). But I will not pursue the point here.
  • 27
    • 85052248588 scopus 로고
    • Famine,Affluence, and Morality
    • There is much disagreement about when appeals to personal sacrifice can defeat Good Samaritan obligations. A much stronger view than the one I advocate for here is
    • There is much disagreement about when appeals to personal sacrifice can defeat Good Samaritan obligations. A much stronger view than the one I advocate for here is Peter Singer, "Famine,Affluence, and Morality," Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1972): 229-43, at 231.
    • (1972) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.1
    • Singer, P.1
  • 28
    • 84890586666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • duties to rescue
    • also defend the idea that researchers have Good Samaritan obligations-what they call
    • Henry Richardson and Leah Belsky also defend the idea that researchers have Good Samaritan obligations-what they call "duties to rescue."
    • Richardson, H.1    Belsky, L.2
  • 29
    • 3042525453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ancillary Care Responsibilities of Medical Researchers: An Ethical Framework for Thinking about the Clinical Care That Researchers Owe Their Subjects
    • However, their primary concern is to defend additional positive duties over and above duties to rescue. They neither elaborate on Good Samaritan obligations nor relate them explicitly to placebo-controlled trials
    • H. Richardson and L. Belsky, "The Ancillary Care Responsibilities of Medical Researchers: An Ethical Framework for Thinking about the Clinical Care That Researchers Owe Their Subjects,"Hastings Center Report 34, no. 1 (2004): 25-33. However, their primary concern is to defend additional positive duties over and above duties to rescue. They neither elaborate on Good Samaritan obligations nor relate them explicitly to placebo-controlled trials.
    • (2004) Hastings Center Report , vol.34 , Issue.1 , pp. 25-33
    • Richardson, H.1    Belsky, L.2
  • 30
    • 84890653576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank Dan Brock and Dan Wikler for pressing me on this
    • I thank Dan Brock and Dan Wikler for pressing me on this.
  • 32
    • 0033119953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zelen Randomization:Attitudes of Parents Participating in a Neonatal Clinical Trial
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., C. Snowden, D. Elbourne, and J. Garcia, "Zelen Randomization:Attitudes of Parents Participating in a Neonatal Clinical Trial," Controlled Clinical Trials 20 (1998): 149-71.
    • (1998) Controlled Clinical Trials , vol.20 , pp. 149-171
    • Snowden, C.1    Elbourne, D.2    Garcia, J.3
  • 33
    • 84890679472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ancillary Care Responsibilities
    • For more on ancillary care, see, 44. Though see note 38 for a possible second requirement
    • For more on ancillary care, see Richardson and Belsky, "Ancillary Care Responsibilities." 44. Though see note 38 for a possible second requirement.
    • Richardson, B.1
  • 34
    • 84890751604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is precisely what happened in Surfaxin. After receiving negative publicity about its plans from Ralph Nader's Public Citizen's Health Research Group, the manufacturer abandoned the project and conducted active controlled trials in the United States and Europe instead
    • This is precisely what happened in Surfaxin. After receiving negative publicity about its plans from Ralph Nader's Public Citizen's Health Research Group, the manufacturer abandoned the project and conducted active controlled trials in the United States and Europe instead.
  • 35
    • 84890770010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not mere speculation. Robert Temple of the Food and Drug Administration was quoted as saying, "If they did the trial, half of the people would get surfactant and better perinatal care, and the other half would get better perinatal care. It seems to me that all the people in the trial would have been better off." S. Shah, "Globalizing Clinical Research," Nation, July 1
    • This is not mere speculation. Robert Temple of the Food and Drug Administration was quoted as saying, "If they did the trial, half of the people would get surfactant and better perinatal care, and the other half would get better perinatal care. It seems to me that all the people in the trial would have been better off." S. Shah, "Globalizing Clinical Research," Nation, July 1, 2002, 28.
    • (2002) , pp. 28
  • 36
    • 84890690337 scopus 로고
    • 'Bizarre as it may seem to most people,' declared the lead editorial in the New York Times on May 6, 1992, 'many black Americans believe that AIDS and the health measures used against it are part of a conspiracy to wipe out the black race.' . . .The consequences of mistrust were nothing short of tragic. As the Times explained, 'At its most destructive, the paranoia causes many blacks to avoid medical treatment.'" J. Jones, Bad Blood: The Tuskeegee Syphilis Experiment, new and expanded edition (New York: Free Press
    • "'Bizarre as it may seem to most people,' declared the lead editorial in the New York Times on May 6, 1992, 'many black Americans believe that AIDS and the health measures used against it are part of a conspiracy to wipe out the black race.' . . .The consequences of mistrust were nothing short of tragic. As the Times explained, 'At its most destructive, the paranoia causes many blacks to avoid medical treatment.'" J. Jones, Bad Blood: The Tuskeegee Syphilis Experiment, new and expanded edition (New York: Free Press, 1993), 221.
    • (1993) , pp. 221


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.