메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 90, Issue 4, 2010, Pages 1705-1729

Mill's hedonism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78049298016     PISSN: 00068047     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (8)

References (114)
  • 3
    • 0004247732 scopus 로고
    • ch. II ¶2, ch. IV¶ Liberal Arts Press (1863)
    • See JOHN STUART MILL, UTILITARIANISM ch. II ¶2, ch. IV¶ 2 (Liberal Arts Press 1957) (1863).
    • (1957) Utilitarianism , pp. 2
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 4
    • 78049308007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ch. II¶ 4-7
    • See id. ch. II¶ 4-7.
  • 5
    • 78049262538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ch. IV¶ 4
    • See id. ch. IV¶ 4.
  • 6
    • 1842570477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill's deliberative utilitarianism
    • 149 David Lyons ed., (arguing that Mill is not a hedonist)
    • David O. Brink, Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism, in MILL'S UTILITARIANISM: CRITICAL ESSAYS 149, 149 (David Lyons ed., 1997) (arguing that Mill is not a hedonist);
    • (1997) Mill's Utilitarianism: Critical Essays , pp. 149
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 7
    • 78049251376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also (suggesting that Mill abandons hedonism in Chapter II, and that he vacillates between hedonism and eudaimonism in Chapter IV)
    • see also TERENCE IRWIN, III THE DEVELOPMENT OF ETHICS: A HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL STUDY: FROM KANT TO RAWLS 389-407 (2009) (suggesting that Mill abandons hedonism in Chapter II, and that he vacillates between hedonism and eudaimonism in Chapter IV).
    • (2009) Iii The Development Of Ethics: A Historical And Critical Study: From Kant To Rawls , pp. 389-407
    • Irwin, T.1
  • 8
    • 78049283355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most frequent target for the charge of boneheadedness, of course, is Chapter IV, paragraph three of Utilitarianism, with its alleged proof that the general happiness is a good. See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV¶ 3. I pass by that topic here, because the standard allegation against Mill is not that that passage conflicts with his hedonism but just that it provides a bad argument for it. (In fact, for reasons I mention briefly below, see infra note 15 and accompanying text, I think there is nothing foolish in the view that desire could be (defeasible) evidence of desirability. I also explain below why I think Mill's case for his hedonism does not rest specially on Chapter IV.)
    • The most frequent target for the charge of boneheadedness, of course, is Chapter IV, paragraph three of Utilitarianism, with its alleged proof that the general happiness is a good. See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV¶ 3. I pass by that topic here, because the standard allegation against Mill is not that that passage conflicts with his hedonism but just that it provides a bad argument for it. (In fact, for reasons I mention briefly below, see infra note 15 and accompanying text, I think there is nothing foolish in the view that desire could be (defeasible) evidence of desirability. I also explain below why I think Mill's case for his hedonism does not rest specially on Chapter IV.)
  • 9
    • 78049306131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. I ¶5
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. I ¶5.
  • 10
    • 78049233305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ¶2
    • See id. ¶2.
  • 11
    • 78049294714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 12
    • 78049249433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ¶5
    • See id. ¶5.
  • 13
    • 78049270879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a more specific problem given Mill's account of direct proof about value, which is that whatever can be proved to be good, must be so by being shown to be a means to something admitted to be good without proof. Id. Anyone who thinks that something could be shown to be intrinsically valuable by arguing that it conduces to something else that is good, is unclear on the concept of intrinsic value
    • There is a more specific problem given Mill's account of direct proof about value, which is that "whatever can be proved to be good, must be so by being shown to be a means to something admitted to be good without proof." Id. Anyone who thinks that something could be shown to be intrinsically valuable by arguing that it conduces to something else that is good, is unclear on the concept of intrinsic value.
  • 14
    • 78049245887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. Explaining the larger meaning of the word proof to which we may have recourse, Mill says that [t]he subject is within the cognizance of the rational faculty; and neither does that faculty deal with it solely in the way of intuition. Id. Solely in the way of intuition might seem to leave an opening for intuition to help out, but Mill never suggests this
    • Id. Explaining the "larger meaning of the word proof to which we may have recourse, Mill says that "[t]he subject is within the cognizance of the rational faculty; and neither does that faculty deal with it solely in the way of intuition." Id. "Solely in the way of intuition" might seem to leave an opening for intuition to help out, but Mill never suggests this.
  • 15
    • 78049253063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 16
    • 78049231418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ch. IV
    • See id. ch. IV.
  • 17
    • 78049244485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If we are discussing a moral theory as well as a theory of value, then we can also confront this entire package with more specific judgments of right and wrong in which we have some confidence. I believe that Mill does this, too, in much of Chapters II, III and V
    • If we are discussing a moral theory as well as a theory of value, then we can also confront this entire package with more specific judgments of right and wrong in which we have some confidence. I believe that Mill does this, too, in much of Chapters II, III and V.
  • 18
    • 78049239529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶4
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶4.
  • 19
    • 78049261490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strictly, Mill says that even a purely quantitative hedonist can secure this result. See id. Many readers have doubted that he actually believes this to be so. But, in any case, Mill clearly thinks that he needs to accommodate a stronger thesis, that the life of swine is not fit for a human being, and that this is so for reasons other than the circumstantial advantages of the distinctively human pleasures. See id. For this he needs, on his own view, to abandon a purely quantitative hedonism
    • Strictly, Mill says that even a purely quantitative hedonist can secure this result. See id. Many readers have doubted that he actually believes this to be so. But, in any case, Mill clearly thinks that he needs to accommodate a stronger thesis, that the life of swine is not fit for a human being, and that this is so for reasons other than the "circumstantial advantages" of the distinctively human pleasures. See id. For this he needs, on his own view, to abandon a purely quantitative hedonism.
  • 20
    • 78049290435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 21
    • 0004220926 scopus 로고
    • ch. IV ¶ Clarendon Press 1907 Bentham lists other features that matter to the value of a pleasure - e.g., propinquity or remoteness, fecundity - but these are pretty clearly not the ground of the intrinsic value of the pleasure
    • See id. ch. I ¶2. I have said that Mill is inconsistent on this issue. There are two ways this claim could be construed. In a broad sense, it seems inconsistent to say that one ought never to do something (such as argue in a certain pattern), and then do it. Mill is in this way inconsistent. But it is also reasonable to think that, by arguing in this way in Chapter II, he implicitly affirms that it is appropriate so to argue; and this means that he affirms mutually inconsistent propositions. I have also said that Mill alters the principle of utility in response to the criticism he considers in Chapter II, paragraph three. This is what all his contemporaries and most subsequent commentators have taken him to be doing. Still, someone might suggest that it is not what Mill presents himself as doing. He has said clearly that "[t]o give a clear view of the ... [Greatest Happiness Principle], much more requires to be said; in particular, what things it includes in the ideas of pain and pleasure; and to what extent this is left an open question." Id. ¶ 2. So it might be claimed that although Mill is filling in details in a new way, and so altering the principle to that extent, he does not see himself as contradicting a principle that - in earlier versions - simply said nothing about quality. However, this cannot be right. Mill begins with Bentham's version of the principle in Chapter II paragraph three, and Bentham had explicitly held that only quantity - intensity and duration - mattered to the intrinsic value of a pleasure. JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. IV ¶ I-IV (Clarendon Press 1907) (1780). Bentham lists other features that matter to the value of a pleasure - e.g., propinquity or remoteness, fecundity - but these are pretty clearly not the ground of the intrinsic value of the pleasure.
    • (1780) An Introduction To The Principles Of Morals And Legislation
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 22
    • 78049265878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Mill has to see himself as correcting a mistake in replacing Bentham's version of the principle with his own
    • See ROGER CRISP, MILLON UTILITARIANISM 22 n.1 (1997). Mill has to see himself as correcting a mistake in replacing Bentham's version of the principle with his own.
    • (1997) Millon Utilitarianism , Issue.1 , pp. 22
    • Crisp, R.1
  • 23
    • 78049295182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV¶ 3
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV¶ 3.
  • 24
    • 0010844454 scopus 로고
    • ¶ 42 T.A. Roberts ed., (1726). In the next sentence Butler restricts this claim to natural affections. Id
    • From the distinction above made between self-love, and the several particular principles or affections in our nature, we may see how good ground there was for that assertion, maintained by the several ancient schools of philosophy against the Epicureans, namely, that virtue is to be pursued as an end, eligible in and for itself. For, if there be any principles or affections in the mind of man distinct from self-love, that the things those principles tend towards, or that the objects of those affections are, each of them, in themselves eligible, to be pursued upon its own account, and to be rested in as an end, is implied in the very idea of such principle or affection. JOSEPH BUTLER, Preface to FIFTEEN SERMONS PREACHED AT THE ROLLS CHAPEL AND A DISSERTATION OF THE NATURE OF VIRTUE 15, ¶ 42 (T.A. Roberts ed., 1970) (1726). In the next sentence Butler restricts this claim to "natural" affections. Id.
    • (1970) Preface To Fifteen Sermons Preached At The Rolls Chapel And A Dissertation Of The Nature Of Virtue , pp. 15
    • Butler, J.1
  • 25
    • 78049294217 scopus 로고
    • Brink, supra note 5, at 178 n.l. Brink supplements the list of Mill's contemporaries in
    • Brink, supra note 5, at 178 n.l. Brink supplements the list of Mill's contemporaries in J.B. SCHNEEWIND, SIDGWICK'S ETHICS AND VICTORIAN MORAL PHILOSOPHY 186 n.43 (1977).
    • (1977) Sidgwick's Ethics And Victorian Moral Philosophy , Issue.43 , pp. 186
    • Schneewind, J.B.1
  • 26
    • 78049279346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CRISP, supra note 19, at 32 n.8, adds more names. It would be easy to extend the list. For a few dissenters, see infra note 54
    • CRISP, supra note 19, at 32 n.8, adds more names. It would be easy to extend the list. For a few dissenters, see infra note 54.
  • 27
    • 78049308006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Brink, supra note 5, at 149
    • See Brink, supra note 5, at 149.
  • 28
    • 78049287718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 4
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 4.
  • 29
    • 78049258338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 30
    • 78049272311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 31
    • 78049303570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. ¶ 5
    • Id. ¶ 5.
  • 32
    • 78049269955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. ¶ 6
    • Id. ¶ 6.
  • 33
    • 78049261974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some readers will think very large margin an understatement, for they think that Mill ascribes a lexical priority in value to the higher pleasures. E.g., CRISP, supra note 19, at 24-32; Brink, supra note 5, at 153. I am not convinced. There would be a strong case for this reading if Mill said that the competent judges would prefer any amount of the higher pleasure, no matter how small, to any amount of the lower, no matter how large. But he falls significantly short of saying this. For one thing, the trade-offs that he says competent judges would refuse to make are not of small degrees of higher pleasure, but are much more momentous - an instructed person becoming an ignoramus, for example
    • Some readers will think "very large margin" an understatement, for they think that Mill ascribes a lexical priority in value to the higher pleasures. E.g., CRISP, supra note 19, at 24-32; Brink, supra note 5, at 153. I am not convinced. There would be a strong case for this reading if Mill said that the competent judges would prefer any amount of the higher pleasure, no matter how small, to any amount of the lower, no matter how large. But he falls significantly short of saying this. For one thing, the trade-offs that he says competent judges would refuse to make are not of small degrees of higher pleasure, but are much more momentous - an instructed person becoming an ignoramus, for example.
  • 34
    • 78049305671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 6. For another, the amount of a lower pleasure of which our nature is capable may well be finite; and if so, there may for all Mill says here be an amount of lower pleasure - though one inaccessible to beings of our nature - that would compensate for some loss of a higher one
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 6. For another, the amount of a lower pleasure of which our nature is capable may well be finite; and if so, there may for all Mill says here be an amount of lower pleasure - though one inaccessible to beings of our nature - that would compensate for some loss of a higher one .
  • 35
    • 78049319873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 2
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 2.
  • 37
    • 78049253552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 6
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 6.
  • 38
    • 78049244484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see id
    • But see id.
  • 39
    • 78049276782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. It does not matter to my argument exactly what the distinction is between happiness and content; I appeal simply to the fact that Mill insists that there is one. But, noticing Mill's ascription to the superior being of a vastly greater capacity for happiness, one might - as perhaps only a crude first approximation - take content or satisfaction to consist in a ratio of happiness to capacity for happiness. See id. The superior being's capacity is very great, that of the fool quite limited; the superior being might then have a lower measure of satisfaction (perhaps ten percent), the fool a much higher one (say ninety percent), even though the absolute level of happiness for the superior being is greater, even much greater
    • Id. It does not matter to my argument exactly what the distinction is between happiness and "content"; I appeal simply to the fact that Mill insists that there is one. But, noticing Mill's ascription to the "superior being" of a vastly greater capacity for happiness, one might - as perhaps only a crude first approximation - take content or satisfaction to consist in a ratio of happiness to capacity for happiness. See id. The superior being's capacity is very great, that of the fool quite limited; the superior being might then have a lower measure of satisfaction (perhaps ten percent), the fool a much higher one (say ninety percent), even though the absolute level of happiness for the superior being is greater, even much greater.
  • 40
    • 78049311315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ¶ 5
    • See id. ¶ 5.
  • 41
    • 78049278369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ¶ 6
    • See id. ¶ 6.
  • 42
    • 33846706435 scopus 로고
    • Is mill's hedonism inconsistent?
    • Readers sometimes miss this point, despite Mill's emphasis. Norman O. Dahl, for example, thinks that, for Mill, Socrates's life is less pleasant that the fool's. 39
    • Readers sometimes miss this point, despite Mill's emphasis. Norman O. Dahl, for example, thinks that, for Mill, Socrates's life is less pleasant that the fool's. Norman O. Dahl, Is Mill's Hedonism Inconsistent?, 7 AM. PHIL. Q. 37, 39 (1973). J.J.C. Smart thinks that Mill attributes to Socrates more happiness than the fool, but with less pleasure - and so must be assuming that Mill here without notice abandons his hedonistic account of happiness.
    • (1973) Am. Phil. Q. , vol.7 , pp. 37
    • Dahl, N.O.1
  • 43
    • 0007303707 scopus 로고
    • An outline of a system of utilitarian ethics
    • 15 J.J.C. Smart & Bernard Williams eds
    • J.J.C. Smart, An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics, in UTILITARIANISM: FOR AND AGAINST 1, 15 (J.J.C. Smart & Bernard Williams eds., 1973). Brink writes of "contentment or pleasure (the mental state)," as if these could be the same thing for Mill.
    • (1973) Utilitarianism: For And Against , pp. 1
    • Smart, J.J.C.1
  • 44
    • 78049239987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Brink, supra note 5, at 154-55. He also argues that Mill must regard Socrates's life as deficient in pleasure because he says that Socrates's life is attended with discontent or dissatisfaction
    • See Brink, supra note 5, at 154-55. He also argues that Mill must regard Socrates's life as deficient in pleasure because he says that Socrates's life is attended with discontent or dissatisfaction.
  • 45
    • 78049317741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 180 n.12
    • See id. at 180 n.12.
  • 46
    • 78049242034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A careful reader will notice that what Mill calls a mistake is thinking "that the superior being, [that is, the one pursing higher pleasures,] in anything like equal circumstances, is not happier than the inferior." MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 6. This seems to allow, against the general direction of my reading, that at least in very unequal circumstances, the choice of the higher pleasures could come at a cost in overall happiness. But, a preliminary point, this is clearly not enough to resolve the puzzle. For it allows that a preference for the higher pleasures could come at a cost in happiness in some extreme cases; but Mill's discussion of the gulf between the higher and lower pleasures has surely suggested that, for his competent judges, sacrifice of quantity of pleasure for quality will be routine. And, second, there seems good reason anyway to think that the exception he allows in this passage does not challenge the heart of Mill's "no-cost-in-pleasure" thesis about these choices. His reference to "circumstances" here is plausibly taken to mean, as it certainly does in his talk of the "circumstantial advantages" of the higher pleasures in Chapter II, paragraph four, that his point is about the extrinsic value of the higher (and lower) pleasures involved, due to consequences that may be beyond one's foresight or control. See id. ¶ 4. A choice for the higher pleasures might put someone in the way of an injury that deprived her of the capacity for enjoying the higher pleasures, for example, and in that way led to a net cost in pleasure if compared to an alternative involving some lower pleasures as well as some higher ones. Mill is in any case careful never to say that his competent judges would knowingly make a sacrifice of happiness, though he allows that they might accept a loss of "content."
  • 47
    • 33745392340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill's utilitarianism
    • Smart, supra note 37, at 13. Irwin mentions both readings, but suggests that the weaker one, though making Mill consistent on these issues, is not distinctively utilitarian. IRWIN, supra note 5, at 403. The weaker reading is the one defended by Wendy Donner. 266 John Skorupski ed
    • Smart, supra note 37, at 13. Irwin mentions both readings, but suggests that the weaker one, though making Mill consistent on these issues, is not distinctively utilitarian. IRWIN, supra note 5, at 403. The weaker reading is the one defended by Wendy Donner. Wendy Donner, Mill's Utilitarianism, in THE CAMBRIDGE COMPANION TO MILL 255, 264, 266 (John Skorupski ed., 1998).
    • (1998) The Cambridge Companion To Mill , vol.264 , pp. 255
    • Donner, W.1
  • 48
    • 0004306960 scopus 로고
    • See Enlarged ed. (I know of no commentator who thinks that Mill uses greatest in the manner of P.T. Barnum just to mean best.)
    • See HENRY SIDGWICK, OUTLINES OF THE HISTORY OF ETHICS FOR ENGUSH READERS 247 (Enlarged ed. 1960). (I know of no commentator who thinks that Mill uses "greatest" in the manner of P.T. Barnum just to mean "best.")
    • (1960) Outlines Of The History Of Ethics For Engush Readers , pp. 247
    • Sidgwick, H.1
  • 49
    • 78049244000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g.. CRISP, supra note 19, at 32
    • See, e.g.. CRISP, supra note 19, at 32;
  • 50
    • 78049294712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brink, supra note 5, at 152
    • Brink, supra note 5, at 152;
  • 51
    • 78049253062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Donner, supra note 39, at 263, 268
    • Donner, supra note 39, at 263, 268.
  • 52
    • 78049241071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 8
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 8.
  • 53
    • 78049285833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 54
    • 78049295633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 55
    • 78049281015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 56
    • 78049248968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 19 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 19 and accompanying text.
  • 57
    • 78049314643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill emphasizes in introducing the notion that quality belongs to the nature of the pleasures that have it, so we could add that here if we wish. See MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 4. But it is hard to see how on his view this could be distinctive of quality. At any rate, nothing in his discussion requires that it be distinctive. The problem about intensity, when it comes to the higher pleasures, does not seem to be that they don't have it (to some degree), or that they don't have it intrinsically, but that they don't have enough of it to establish them as everywhere superior, except by appeal to their extrinsic value because of their circumstantial advantages. See id. Quality by contrast is supposed to be something they not only have intrinsically, but have to a sufficient degree that it insures their superiority even without appeal to those other advantages
    • Mill emphasizes in introducing the notion that quality belongs to the nature of the pleasures that have it, so we could add that here if we wish. See MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 4. But it is hard to see how on his view this could be distinctive of quality. At any rate, nothing in his discussion requires that it be distinctive. The problem about intensity, when it comes to the higher pleasures, does not seem to be that they don't have it (to some degree), or that they don't have it intrinsically, but that they don't have enough of it to establish them as everywhere superior, except by appeal to their extrinsic value because of their "circumstantial advantages." See id. Quality by contrast is supposed to be something they not only have intrinsically, but have to a sufficient degree that it insures their superiority even without appeal to those other advantages.
  • 58
    • 78049312751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill writes that quality divides pleasures into kinds, in the plural. See id. He may just mean that there is a division into higher and lower pleasures; or he might mean that there are different ranks of value even within the superior pleasures. But he might have in mind that what he calls quality actually comprises several different factors, which combine with intensity to determine how pleasant, and therefore how valuable, a pleasure is. My reading could accommodate this complication
    • Mill writes that quality divides pleasures into "kinds," in the plural. See id. He may just mean that there is a division into higher and lower pleasures; or he might mean that there are different ranks of value even within the superior pleasures. But he might have in mind that what he calls quality actually comprises several different factors, which combine with intensity to determine how pleasant, and therefore how valuable, a pleasure is. My reading could accommodate this complication.
  • 59
    • 78049271345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This statement may require refinement if one thinks (as I do not) that Mill takes the higher pleasures to be lexically prior to the lower ones in pleasurableness
    • This statement may require refinement if one thinks (as I do not) that Mill takes the higher pleasures to be lexically prior to the lower ones in pleasurableness.
  • 60
    • 78049245886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 8
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 8.
  • 61
    • 78049263935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 62
    • 78049302611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 63
    • 78049317284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (And there needs be the less hesitation to accept this judgment respecting the quality of pleasures, since there is no other tribunal to be referred to even on the question of quantity.)
    • See id. ("And there needs be the less hesitation to accept this judgment respecting the quality of pleasures, since there is no other tribunal to be referred to even on the question of quantity.").
  • 64
    • 78049254924 scopus 로고
    • Mill's utilitarianism
    • Although the historically predominant view of Mill's quantity-quality distinction accuses him of falling into inconsistency, he has had a few defenders. I have already mentioned interpreters who resolve the first problem by attributing to Mill only a weaker form of hedonism; among the problems with this approach is that it does not address the second problem, as my proposal does. See supra note 39 and accompanying text (discussing other authors' findings of Mill's weaker form of hedonism). My reading also differs from other friendly readings of Mill of which I am aware. Ernest Sosa takes pleasures superior in quality to be on that account more pleasant - and takes this to solve the second problem as well as the first - but does so by understanding qualitative differences to be very large quantitative differences; my account keeps quantity and quality distinct. But see 164 James M. Smith & Ernest Sosa eds
    • Although the historically predominant view of Mill's quantity-quality distinction accuses him of falling into inconsistency, he has had a few defenders. I have already mentioned interpreters who resolve the first problem by attributing to Mill only a weaker form of hedonism; among the problems with this approach is that it does not address the second problem, as my proposal does. See supra note 39 and accompanying text (discussing other authors' findings of Mill's weaker form of hedonism). My reading also differs from other "friendly" readings of Mill of which I am aware. Ernest Sosa takes pleasures superior in quality to be on that account more pleasant - and takes this to solve the second problem as well as the first - but does so by understanding qualitative differences to be very large quantitative differences; my account keeps quantity and quality distinct. But see Ernest Sosa, Mill's Utilitarianism, in MILL's UTILITARIANISM: TEXT AND CRITICISM 154, 164 (James M. Smith & Ernest Sosa eds., 1969). Dahl also takes qualitatively superior pleasures to be more pleasant. But he maintains that Mill would be involved in no inconsistency in denying that the greatest pleasure is always the best.
    • (1969) Mill's Utilitarianism: Text And Criticism , pp. 154
    • Sosa, E.1
  • 65
    • 78049268164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dahl, supra note 37, at 40. He also attributes to Mill the view that a pleasure of greater quantity is always the greater pleasure
    • See Dahl, supra note 37, at 40. He also attributes to Mill the view that a pleasure of greater quantity is always the greater pleasure.
  • 66
    • 78049238227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 47. I disagree on both counts. Two discussions that seem closer to mine are by John Skorupski and by Crisp
    • See id. at 47. I disagree on both counts. Two discussions that seem closer to mine are by John Skorupski and by Crisp.
  • 67
    • 78049294711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CRISP, supra note 19, at 30-34
    • See CRISP, supra note 19, at 30-34;
  • 68
    • 0004172972 scopus 로고
    • JOHN SKORUPSKI, JOHN STUART MILL 304-05 (1989). Both see that Mill speaks interchangeably of quantity and intensity (or intensity and duration), and both hold that Mill can say that the higher pleasures are more pleasant (Crisp says that Mill need not "flinch" from saying this).
    • (1989) John Stuart Mill , pp. 304-305
    • Skorupski, J.1
  • 69
    • 78049297027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CRISP, supra note 19, at 33. But Crisp's account is entangled in a way I am not certain I understand with his view (which I doubt, see supra note 29 and accompanying text) that Mill assigns lexical priority in value to the higher pleasures. And, in both discussions, details are missing: for example, neither brings out a point that seems to me crucial, that one pleasure can be lesser in quantity without thereby being less pleasant, or less of a pleasure, than another, and neither mentions what I have called the second problem for Mill's view. It may for all this be that I am elaborating an argument for a conclusion that is in no serious disagreement with theirs
    • See CRISP, supra note 19, at 33. But Crisp's account is entangled in a way I am not certain I understand with his view (which I doubt, see supra note 29 and accompanying text) that Mill assigns lexical priority in value to the higher pleasures. And, in both discussions, details are missing: for example, neither brings out a point that seems to me crucial, that one pleasure can be lesser in quantity without thereby being less pleasant, or less of a pleasure, than another, and neither mentions what I have called the second problem for Mill's view. It may for all this be that I am elaborating an argument for a conclusion that is in no serious disagreement with theirs.
  • 70
    • 78049291863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 9
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. II ¶ 9.
  • 71
    • 78049273287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 72
    • 78049232834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ch. IV
    • See id. ch. IV.
  • 73
    • 78049294710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ¶ 3
    • See id. ¶ 3.
  • 74
    • 78049268163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. ¶ 4
    • Id. ¶ 4.
  • 75
    • 78049266329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ¶ 4-6
    • See id. ¶ 4-6.
  • 76
    • 78049313202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill says that the issue between him and his opponents is whether mankind do desire nothing for itself but that which is a pleasure to them, or of which the absence is a pain. Id. ¶ 10. It seems clear from his discussion, in fact, that all of the goods admitted in Chapter IV, paragraphs five through eight, to be, in some sense, desired for their own sakes, are desired for oneself. This is obvious for money, power, and fame: the miser who desires possession of money as an end is understood to desire that he or she possess it, for example, not that others do so. This pattern is most strikingly continued in the case of virtue, for presumably Mill's associationist account of how we come to desire virtue as an end can be extended to explain why we would desire that others have it as well as ourselves. But Mill's interest appears to be entirely in explaining how we can come to desire, for its own sake, to be virtuous ourselves
    • Mill says that the issue between him and his opponents is "whether mankind do desire nothing for itself but that which is a pleasure to them, or of which the absence is a pain." Id. ¶ 10. It seems clear from his discussion, in fact, that all of the goods admitted in Chapter IV, paragraphs five through eight, to be, in some sense, desired for their own sakes, are desired for oneself. This is obvious for money, power, and fame: the miser who desires possession of money as an end is understood to desire that he or she possess it, for example, not that others do so. This pattern is most strikingly continued in the case of virtue, for presumably Mill's associationist account of how we come to desire virtue as an end can be extended to explain why we would desire that others have it as well as ourselves. But Mill's interest appears to be entirely in explaining how we can come to desire, for its own sake, to be virtuous ourselves.
  • 77
    • 78049308495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ch. II ¶ 15-18. Acting for others' sake would not require any desire for the good of others, thanks to an important complexity in Mill's moral psychology, if it were done solely from a settled habitual will favoring their good. For Mill's view is that motivation by habit, unlike motivation by desire, need not be aimed at one's own happiness. But he thinks that a habitual pursuit of virtue can arise only from one's initially desiring virtue, so presumably would say the corresponding thing about concern for others' good
    • See id. ch. II ¶ 15-18. Acting for others' sake would not require any desire for the good of others, thanks to an important complexity in Mill's moral psychology, if it were done solely from a settled habitual will favoring their good. For Mill's view is that motivation by habit, unlike motivation by desire, need not be aimed at one's own happiness. But he thinks that a habitual pursuit of virtue can arise only from one's initially desiring virtue, so presumably would say the corresponding thing about concern for others' good.
  • 78
    • 78049265373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ch.IV ¶ 11
    • See id. ch.IV ¶ 11.
  • 79
    • 78049284385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I speculate that the happiness of others is not mentioned as an end in Chapter IV of Utilitarianism for dialectical reasons. Mill's opponents want to establish that people care about ends other than happiness. But it would not help them achieve this goal to argue that people care intrinsically about the happiness of others (even if, on their understanding of him, Mill would deny this), because that, after all, would not be an example of people desiring for its own sake anything other than happiness. So Mill anticipates their focusing on a different favorite example, virtue.
  • 81
    • 78049241527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 184. This is the passage not from Utilitarianism that I warned in my Introduction that I would draw on
    • See id. at 184. This is the passage not from Utilitarianism that I warned in my Introduction that I would draw on.
  • 82
    • 78049244483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 5
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 5.
  • 83
    • 78049309454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ¶ 6
    • See id. ¶ 6.
  • 84
    • 78049253550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. ¶ 7
    • Id. ¶ 7.
  • 85
    • 78049254460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 86
    • 78049297028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. ¶ 6
    • Id. ¶ 6.
  • 87
    • 78049253549 scopus 로고
    • These actual coins, which he admits to be desired in and for themselves, are a part either of pleasure or of the absence of pain
    • This point does not require G.E. Moore's surely unfair construal, that Mill would have to mean that
    • This point does not require G.E. Moore's surely unfair construal, that Mill would have to mean that "these actual coins, which he admits to be desired in and for themselves, are a part either of pleasure or of the absence of pain." GEORGE EDWARD MOORE, PRINCIPIA ETHICA 71 (1903). What the miser desires for its own sake is presumably a state, that of possessing money. But it still needs to be explained what would be meant by calling this state part of anyone's pleasure.
    • (1903) Principia Ethica , pp. 71
    • Moore, G.E.1
  • 88
    • 78049261014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 7
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 7.
  • 89
    • 78049253985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. ¶ 6
    • Id. ¶ 6.
  • 90
    • 78049289084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This passage is not an isolated one. A few sentences earlier, describing the process by which something comes to be desired as an end, Mill writes: What was once desired as an instrument for the attainment of happiness has come to be desired for its own sake. In being desired for its own sake it is, however, desired as part of happiness. The person is made, or thinks he would be made, happy by its mere possession; and is made unhappy by failure to obtain it. Id. Of course, part of what is at issue in reading Mill is what "happy" and "unhappy" mean in the last of these sentences. One might think that he cannot be talking about pleasure and the absence of pain, as the previous sentence speaks of happiness as having parts, and it is not clear what it would mean for pleasure and the absence of pain to have parts. But in the first sentence, happiness seems clearly to be pleasure; at least, no commentator I know of has thought that when Mill speaks of money, say, as initially merely instrumental to happiness, he has in mind anything but a hedonistic account of what it is instrumental to. But that suggests that happiness in the third sentence is, after all, pleasure and the absence of pain. Or, again, consider these two sentences together: Whatever is desired otherwise than as a means to some end beyond itself, and ultimately to happiness, is desired as itself a part of happiness, and is not desired for itself until it has become so. Those who desire virtue for its own sake desire it either because the consciousness of it is a pleasure, or because the consciousness of being without it is a pain, or for both reasons united ....
  • 91
    • 78049317283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. ¶ 8
    • Id. ¶ 8.
  • 92
    • 78049236533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here again, Mill seems to be providing an entirely hedonistic account of what is involved in desiring virtue as part of happiness. Finally, there are passages that say nothing about happiness having parts, but which summarize this entire discussion as having argued that no desire can possibly be directed to anything ultimately except pleasure and exemption from pain. Id. ¶ 11
    • Here again, Mill seems to be providing an entirely hedonistic account of what is involved in desiring virtue as part of happiness. Finally, there are passages that say nothing about happiness having parts, but which summarize this entire discussion as having argued that no "desire can possibly be directed to anything ultimately except pleasure and exemption from pain." Id. ¶ 11.
  • 93
    • 78049264865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Irwin sees Mill as vacillating between a eudaimonist and a hedonist view from sentence to sentence in the passage I have just quoted. See IRWIN, supra note 5, at 406-07 n.29. Part of his reason for seeing a strong eudaimonist strain in Chapter IV of Mill's Utilitarianism derives from his conviction that Mill had already abandoned hedonism in Chapter II; so the argument of my previous section is also relevant here
    • Irwin sees Mill as vacillating between a eudaimonist and a hedonist view from sentence to sentence in the passage I have just quoted. See IRWIN, supra note 5, at 406-07 n.29. Part of his reason for seeing a strong eudaimonist strain in Chapter IV of Mill's Utilitarianism derives from his conviction that Mill had already abandoned hedonism in Chapter II; so the argument of my previous section is also relevant here.
  • 94
    • 78049295180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SIDGWICK, supra note 31, at 93 n.l. Crisp offers a similar account. See CRISP, supra note 19, at 86-88
    • SIDGWICK, supra note 31, at 93 n.l. Crisp offers a similar account. See CRISP, supra note 19, at 86-88.
  • 95
    • 78049281936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 6
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 6.
  • 96
    • 78049253059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • mote
    • Id. ¶ 6-7. In his first statement of his utility principle in Chapter II, Mill has it saying that "pleasure and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends; and that all desirable things ... are desirable either for the pleasure inherent in themselves or as means to the promotion of pleasure and the prevention of pain." Id. ch. II ¶ 2. His wording does not make absolutely clear whether he is distinguishing two or three categories of desirable things. (The answer would clearly be three if he had written "all other desirable things.") I am inclined, however, to read this as a three-way distinction: putting the absence of pain to one side, there are (1) pleasure itself, (2) things with pleasure inherent in them, and (3) things that are means to pleasure. (Irwin also appears to see a three-way distinction here. See IRWIN, supra note 5, at 399.) If we assume that three categories are meant, my view is that is that the distinction Mill wants in Chapter IV, paragraphs five through eight, is between desiring something for being in category (3) above, and desiring it for being in category (2), where being in category (2) - having pleasure inherent in it - is being the sort of thing whose possession is a source of immediate pleasure, rather merely being, as with category (3), an instrumental means to pleasure.
  • 97
    • 78049236067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV¶ 6
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV¶ 6.
  • 98
    • 78049317267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are not the only ways in which money, say, can give rise to pleasure. What about the disproportionate pleasure some take in spending money on items from which they expect little benefit? The idea, I think, would be that just as it is possible to desire money for the pleasure of having it, apart from the benefit from anything it will buy, so it is possible to value spending it - to love shopping -just for the pleasure inherent in doing so, apart from any benefit from what one is buying
    • These are not the only ways in which money, say, can give rise to pleasure. What about the disproportionate pleasure some take in spending money on items from which they expect little benefit? The idea, I think, would be that just as it is possible to desire money for the pleasure of having it, apart from the benefit from anything it will buy, so it is possible to value spending it - to love shopping -just for the pleasure inherent in doing so, apart from any benefit from what one is buying.
  • 99
    • 78049314143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 64, at 184
    • MILL, supra note 64, at 184.
  • 100
    • 78049248019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 101
    • 78049294708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 102
    • 78049271854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 103
    • 78049237008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 104
    • 78049292802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That Mill views this sense as respectable and important is indicated by his use of it in correcting Whewell: In Dr. Whewell's view of morality, he writes, disinterestedness has no place. Id. at 184 n.*. He clearly intends that, in his own theory, disinterested desire does have a place
    • That Mill views this sense as respectable and important is indicated by his use of it in correcting Whewell: "In Dr. Whewell's view of morality," he writes, "disinterestedness has no place." Id. at 184 n.*. He clearly intends that, in his own theory, disinterested desire does have a place.
  • 105
    • 78049248965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 5-8
    • MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 5-8.
  • 106
    • 78049268160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CRISP, supra note 19, at 86
    • CRISP, supra note 19, at 86.
  • 107
    • 78049303090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IRWIN, supra note 5, at 399
    • IRWIN, supra note 5, at 399.
  • 108
    • 78049250881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SlDGWICK, supra note 31, at 93 n.l
    • SlDGWICK, supra note 31, at 93 n.l.
  • 109
    • 78049232347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BUTLER, Preface, supra note 21, at 12-15, ¶ 35-41; BUTLER, Sermon 11, supra note 21, at 99-110, ¶ 1-11
    • BUTLER, Preface, supra note 21, at 12-15, ¶ 35-41; BUTLER, Sermon 11, supra note 21, at 99-110, ¶ 1-11.
  • 110
    • 78049308485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill writes in Chapter IV of Utilitarianism of pleasure in the mere possession of virtue or money. See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV. But we need a different term for what immediately pleases, in a quite similar way, about another's good. (And possession will hardly do, anyway, for music, one of the examples in Chapter IV.)
    • Mill writes in Chapter IV of Utilitarianism of pleasure in the "mere possession" of virtue or money. See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV. But we need a different term for what immediately pleases, in a quite similar way, about another's good. (And "possession" will hardly do, anyway, for music, one of the examples in Chapter IV.)
  • 111
    • 78049269494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham, too, allows that there are [p]leasures of benevolence or goodwill, appearing to have a similar phenomenon in mind. See BENTHAM, supra note 19, at 36. A complete account would need to discuss what it is to take pleasure in some state of affairs. Here I leave this at an intuitive level, taking it as obvious that the immediate pleasures that Mill speaks of as arising through association are pleasures in virtue, in the good of others, in possessing money, and so on
    • Bentham, too, allows that there are "[p]leasures of benevolence or goodwill," appearing to have a similar phenomenon in mind. See BENTHAM, supra note 19, at 36. A complete account would need to discuss what it is to take pleasure in some state of affairs. Here I leave this at an intuitive level, taking it as obvious that the immediate pleasures that Mill speaks of as arising through association are pleasures in virtue, in the good of others, in possessing money, and so on.
  • 112
    • 78049291403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am influenced here by a point common to many philosophical discussions of linguistic reference, that when we discover that the world contains nothing that quite fits some definition we had thought attached to one of our terms, we do not always conclude that our term refers to nothing; sometimes we decide that we need a better definition, shaped in part by what the world has to offer. I think that Mill has made a plausible case that if we lived in what we might call a Mill-world rather than a Butler-world - that is, in a world in which all desires had at bottom to be for one's own pleasure - we should not conclude that our term, "disinterested benevolence," refers to nothing; that we should decide instead, on balance, that he has provided a reasonable account of that very phenomenon.
  • 113
    • 78049316818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 5. I think that this case can be made even taking account of the point from above, that Mill discusses the desire for virtue that he thinks some acquire as if it were solely a desire for virtue in oneself. See supra note 61 and accompanying text. This would mean that the immediate pleasure that someone with this desire takes in virtue would be limited to pleasure in his or her own virtue. But, first, Mill may not really be limited to this rather narcissistic picture of the lover of virtue. He may well think (and plausibly) that a lover of virtue will take pleasure in it no matter who displays it; the focus on a desire for virtue in oneself may be an artifact brought about by his opponent's focus on that sort of example. And, second, even immediate pleasure just in one's own virtue (and immediate distress at its absence), even if it is focused on oneself, is not in the mature person based on, or derived from, any perception of the advantage of being virtuous. So the term "disinterested" would still seem to apply.
  • 114
    • 78049305215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 8
    • See MILL, supra note 2, ch. IV ¶ 8.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.