메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 119, Issue 8, 2010, Pages 1948-1991

Integrity and the incongruities of justice: A review of Daniel Markovits's a modern legal ethics: Adversary advocacy in a democratic age

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77954514140     PISSN: 00440094     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (6)

References (80)
  • 1
    • 77954502890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • DANIEL MARKOVITS, A MODERN LEGAL ETHICS: ADVERSARY ADVOCACY IN A DEMOCRATIC AGE (2008).
  • 2
    • 77954522080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 1.
  • 3
    • 77954479541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 17.
  • 4
    • 77954493046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 13-16.
  • 5
    • 77954527549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., ARTHUR ISAK APPLBAUM, ETHICS FOR ADVERSARIES (1999); DAVID LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE (1988); WILLIAM H. SIMON, THE PRACTICE OF JUSTICE: A THEORY OF LAWYERS' ETHICS (1998).
  • 6
    • 77954510592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 104-05.
  • 7
    • 77954529416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 107-08, 115-17.
  • 8
    • 77954478181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 93-96.
  • 9
    • 77954465567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 211.
  • 10
    • 77954523257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 171-211.
  • 11
    • 77954530057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 163.
  • 12
    • 77954531845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 212-46.
  • 13
    • 77954498789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 1.
  • 14
    • 77954465836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Charles Fried, The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer-Client Relation, 85 YALE L.J. 1060 (1976).
  • 15
    • 77954503278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • SIMON, supra note 5.
  • 16
    • 77954513555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, THE LOST LAWYER: FAILING IDEALS OF THE LEGAL PROFESSION (1993).
  • 17
    • 77954495404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at xi.
  • 18
    • 77954517056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE (1971).
  • 19
    • 77954472218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Bernard Williams, A Critique of Utilitarianism, in J.J.C. SMART & BERNARD WILLIAMS, UTILITARIANISM: FOR AND AGAINST 77 (1973).
  • 20
    • 77954530942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 98-99.
  • 21
    • 77954526646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 121-33.
  • 22
    • 77954493045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., CHRISTINE M. KORSGAARD, CREATING THE KINGDOM OF ENDS (1996).
  • 23
    • 77954484792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Markovits's attraction to the ancients' phrasing of ethical questions appears to have been influenced by Williams. MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 109 (describing the "venerable Aristotelean tradition" in ethics and citing Williams in support of this tradition). See generally BERNARD WILLIAMS, ETHICS AND THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHY (1985) (arguing that the tradition of the ancients is superior to the modern, impartialist tradition).
  • 24
    • 77954468676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Williams, supra note 19, at 99-100; see also Bernard Williams, Persons, Character and Morality, in MORAL LUCK: PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS 1973-1980, at 1 (1981) (criticizing Kantian moral theory for failing to specify the connection between a person's actions and what gives a person character and identity).
  • 25
    • 77954510201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • KRONMAN, supra note 16, at 53-108.
  • 26
    • 77954487646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Cf. id. at 146-54 (discussing advocacy, but explaining why lawyer-statesman capacities play some role in litigation, not explaining the legitimacy of the advocate's partisanship).
  • 27
    • 77954506794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 3.
  • 28
    • 77954465205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 4.
  • 29
    • 77954501565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 4.
  • 30
    • 77954471660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 4-5.
  • 31
    • 77954489285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 35.
  • 32
    • 77954497827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Cheating would seem to be intentionally violating the rules that govern a rule-governed activity in order to gain an advantage. Breaking of the rules-even if implicit-is essential and deservingness inessential. A stellar baseball team undeservingly robbed of a genuine double play that should have ended a game because of a bad call by the umpire would nonetheless be cheating if it altered the next batter's bat to ensure its deserved win. Conversely, the other team's assertion that the umpire's decision cannot be revisited by television replay would not be cheating, even if this amounted to advocating for an undeserved benefit. Similarly, in adversarial litigation if there is an entitlement to assert a claim or a defense that one believes is sufficiently strong to be successful, and one complies with the rules, one is not cheating. But, to replace a date stamp on a document in order to comply with a statute of limitations-even if the underlying claim is deserving-would be cheating (as well as lying). Cf. Ted Schneyer, The Promise and Problematics of Legal Ethics from the Lawyer's Point of View, 16 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 45, 63 (2004) (criticizing Markovits's argument, as presented in an earlier article, on the ground that calling something "cheating" entails that rules or expectations governing an activity have been violated to obtain an advantage).
  • 33
    • 77954500808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 44.
  • 34
    • 77954467248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 77.
  • 35
    • 77954520062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 34.
  • 36
    • 77954521023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 34 (emphasis added).
  • 37
    • 77954472217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 35 (emphasis added).
  • 38
    • 77954512144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MODEL RULES OF PROF'L CONDUCT R. 3.3(a) (2007).
  • 39
    • 77954462245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. R. 3.3(a)(3). As the Comments to the Rules indicate, there are numerous reasons-including those sounding in the Sixth Amendment-to suppose that the criminal defendant's right to counsel should be read to entail a broad obligation of the criminal defense counsel to give her client the benefit of the doubt in deciding whether to offer evidence of his innocence. See id. R. 3.3 cmt.
  • 40
    • 77954528878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 40.
  • 41
    • 77954531599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Williams, supra note 19, at 99 ("[Utilitarianism ignores] that each of us is specially responsible for what he does, rather than for what other people do. This is an idea closely connected with the value of integrity.").
  • 42
    • 77954482252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • And, indeed, the argument that lawyers are lying about the law is, I believe, much weaker to begin with. It rests on the claim that lawyers are lying when they take positions before judges that they would not take outside of the particular representation. As to the judicial context, where there are adversaries, this falls far short of an argument that lawyers are lying. Although the "actor" argument is not quite correct, the addressees of lawyers making legal arguments are judges and other lawyers, who perfectly understand that the context of speech is intrinsically framed by mutual understanding that each lawyer is taking an adversarial stance. In this sense, it is no more like lying than bluffing in an expert game of poker.
  • 43
    • 77954526645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 211.
  • 44
    • 77954483122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 10.
  • 45
    • 77954474338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 173.
  • 46
    • 77954489983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 219-21 (describing as part of the change in the legal profession that more lawyers are shifting to jobs in which their interests are more closely aligned with their clients' interests).
  • 47
    • 77954482251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • David B. Wilkins, Team of Rivals? Toward a New Model of the Corporate Attorney/Client Relationship, in 62 CURRENT LEGAL PROBLEMS 478 (Colm O'Cinneide ed., 2009).
  • 48
    • 77954505109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 220 n.†.
  • 49
    • 77954464839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Markovits anticipates this objection and responds to it. He writes: [T]he suggestion that a division of labor might save lawyers' integrity misconstrues the nature of the threat against their integrity that lawyers face, specifically by locating that threat, incorrectly, in lawyers' discomfort with their clients' ultimate purposes rather than, as I have been arguing, in tensions between more general first-personal ethical ideals of truth-telling and fair play and the methods that lawyers must employ in serving their clients' purposes, whatever they are. Id. at 221 n.†.
  • 50
    • 77954529487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See sources cited supra note 5.
  • 51
    • 77954500807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 184-211.
  • 52
    • 77954530056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See MARKOVITS, supra note 1. at 185.
  • 53
    • 77954489284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 173-84, 314 n.16 (citing RAYMOND GEUSS, THE IDEA OF A CRITICAL THEORY: HABERMAS AND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL (1981)).
  • 54
    • 77954515546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 173-84, 314 n.16 (citing RAYMOND GEUSS, THE IDEA OF A CRITICAL THEORY: HABERMAS AND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL (1981)). at 176.
  • 55
    • 77954477692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. at 184-87.
  • 56
    • 77954469561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. at 187 ("[T]his practical account places lawyerly fidelity and negative capability at the center of the transformative power of the legal process and therefore at the foundation of its legitimacy.").\
  • 57
    • 77954532223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. at 189.
  • 58
    • 77954509050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 210-11.
  • 59
    • 77954528466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • But see id. at 90-98.
  • 60
    • 77954524820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Lon L. Fuller, Positivism & Fidelity to Law-A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630 (1958).
  • 61
    • 77954531213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Two caveats are needed on this point-one large and one small. The large caveat is that while there appears to be consensus that John Keats introduced the term "negative capability," one of the most prominent jurisprudential articles of the past several decades actually makes extensive use of this term. See Roberto Mangabeira Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement, 96 HARV. L. REV. 561, 650 (1983). Moreover, negative capability is one of the large overarching themes of Unger's book, ROBERTO MANGABEIRA UNGER, FALSE NECESSITY: ANTI-NECESSITARIAN SOCIAL THEORY IN THE SERVICE OF RADICAL DEMOCRACY (1987). Unger mentions that the phrase "negative capability" comes from Keats, Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement, supra, at 624, and indicates that his usage of it differs from Keats's, notwithstanding some connections, id. Markovits indicates in a note that his usage of "negative capability" bears "some similarity" to Unger's. MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 297 n.71. The smaller caveat is that the body of legal scholarship prior to Markovits-including legal scholarship about the nature of legal thought-includes some discussion of Keats's "negative capability." See, e.g., Peter Read Teachout, The Soul of the Fugue: An Essay on Reading Fuller, 70 MINN. L. REV. 1073, 1107 (1986) (articulating negative capability themes-although not by that name-in the thought of Lon Fuller). These observations do not take away from the originality of Markovits's use of the Keats idea in thinking about legal ethics, for the prior uses do not pertain to the legal thought of practicing private lawyers advocating for clients.
  • 62
    • 77954495403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Letter from John Keats to George and Thomas Keats (Dec. 21, 1817), reprinted in THE SELECTED LETTERS OF JOHN KEATS 102, 103 (Lionel Trilling ed., 1951).
  • 63
    • 77954476294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 93 (quoting Letter from John Keats to Richard Woodhouse (Oct. 27, 1818), in THE SELECTED LETTERS OF JOHN KEATS, supra note 62, at 165, 166.
  • 64
    • 77954489208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. at 201.
  • 65
    • 77954520061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Robert Cover, The Supreme Court 1982 Term-Foreword: Nomos and Narrative, 97 HARV. L. REV. 4 (1983).
  • 66
    • 85025011756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 318 n.60 (citing TOM R. TYLER, WHY PEOPLE OBEY THE LAW 105 (1990); Tom R. Tyler, The Psychology of Disputant Concerns in Mediation, 3 NEGOTIATION J. 367 (1987)).
  • 67
    • 77954473594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Fried, supra note 14, at 1075.
  • 68
    • 77954495002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Stephen L. Pepper, The Lawyer's Amoral Ethical Role: A Defense, A Problem, and Some Possibilities, 1986 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 613. As Andrew Kaufman points out in his response to Pepper, Pepper's structural account does not entail that it is always impermissible for a lawyer to diverge from what Pepper refers to as the lawyer's amoral role, or that some extraordinarily high standard must be met to justify such a divergence. Andrew L. Kaufman, Commentary on Pepper's The Lawyer's Amoral Ethical Role, A Symposium on The Lawyer's Amoral Ethical Role, 1986 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 651, 653-54.
  • 69
    • 77954490576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See David Luban, Lawyers as Upholders of Human Dignity (When They Aren't Busy Assaulting It), in LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY 65 (2007).
  • 70
    • 77954472974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Pepper, supra note 68, at 615-19. Markovits's account differs from Pepper's in innumerable ways. Critically, while Pepper states that law is "intended to be a public good which increases autonomy," id. at 617, Markovits's justification looks to the role of law in dispute resolution in a democracy. Moreover, Markovits would reject both the public good conceptualization, as such, and the autonomy consequentialism Pepper seems to accept.
  • 71
    • 77954530055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Robert W. Gordon, The Legal Profession, in LOOKING BACK AT LAW'S CENTURY 287 (Austin Sarat, Bryant Garth & Robert A. Kagan eds., 2002).
  • 72
    • 77954508070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Russell G. Pearce, The Professionalism Paradigm Shift: Why Discarding Professional Ideology Will Improve the Conduct and Reputation of the Bar, 70 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1229 (1995).
  • 73
    • 77954478179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • DEBORAH L. RHODE, IN THE INTERESTS OF JUSTICE: REFORMING THE LEGAL PROFESSION (2000).
  • 74
    • 0347173920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Tanina Rostain, Ethics Lost: Limitations of Current Approaches to Lawyer Regulation, 71 S. CAL. L. REV. 1273 (1998).
  • 75
    • 77954463250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Wilkins, supra note 47.
  • 76
    • 77954468291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 245.
  • 77
    • 77954501708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 246.
  • 78
    • 77954465835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See generally Luban, supra note 69, at 19-63; Gerald J. Postema, Moral Responsibility in Professional Ethics, 55 N.Y.U. L. REV. 63 (1980); Richard Wasserstrom, Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues, 5 HUM. RTS. 1 (1975).
  • 79
    • 77954491451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The psychological costs of personal change are, interestingly, one of the central themes of Chapter 6, and play a very large role in Markovits's philosophical defense of Williams. MARKOVITS, supra note 1, at 143-50. Indeed, Markovits's defense of Jim's decision not to kill is oddly based on a kind of cost-of-change argument. The question is why it might be rational for a person to have ethical commitments-such as the commitment not, through one's acts, to bring about another person's death-that are so deeply entrenched that one would be unwilling to violate those commitments even if one saw what appeared to be a strong impartialist justification for doing so. Markovits's answer is that leading lives that amount to something and being a person who has some goals and substance would not be possible unless at least certain commitments are so deeply entrenched that we are incapable of revisiting them; it would be simply too psychologically costly to rethink commitments every time there would appear to be reasons to rethink them. Hence, a rational person makes such commitments. Given that it is rational to make commitments of this form, given that the commitment not to take other lives is a commitment that it is entirely justifiable for a person to have, and given that Jim has made such a commitment, it is not true that Jim is ethically required to take the life of another. The point would not be that one was asking Jim to betray his basic commitments (although one would be), but that one would be asking Jim not to have this basic commitment, or, perhaps, any basic commitments of this strength, and those would be unjustifiable demands.
  • 80
    • 32944471147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Fred C. Zacharias & Bruce A. Green, Reconceptualizing Advocacy Ethics, 74 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 1 (2005).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.