메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 110, Issue 4, 2010, Pages 1172-1192

Power rules

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77954478709     PISSN: 00101958     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (20)

References (110)
  • 2
    • 77954461431 scopus 로고
    • Edwin Curley ed., Hackett Publ'g Co. 1994
    • Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan 144 (Edwin Curley ed., Hackett Publ'g Co. 1994) (1668);
    • (1668) Leviathan , pp. 144
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 5
    • 70249119792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The vulnerable subject: Anchoring equality in the human condition
    • 8-15
    • Martha Albertson Fineman, The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition, 20 Yale J.L. & Feminism 1, 8-15 (2008).
    • (2008) Yale J.L. & Feminism , vol.20 , pp. 1
    • Fineman, M.A.1
  • 6
    • 77954505916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This Essay focuses on the U.S. legal system, but seemingly every legal system contains rules designed to protect vulnerable persons
    • This Essay focuses on the U.S. legal system, but seemingly every legal system contains rules designed to protect vulnerable persons.
  • 7
    • 0346155183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights essentialism and remedial equilibration
    • One analogue in current legal literature is "prophylactic rules," or rules meant to avoid risk, usually the risk that a government actor will violate the Constitution (e.g., the Miranda requirement). See generally, 899-904 (1999)
    • One analogue in current legal literature is "prophylactic rules," or rules meant to avoid risk, usually the risk that a government actor will violate the Constitution (e.g., the Miranda requirement). See generally Daryl J. Levinson, Rights Essentialism and Remedial Equilibration, 99 Colum. L. Rev. 857, 899-904 (1999);
    • Colum. L. Rev. , vol.99 , pp. 857
    • Levinson, D.J.1
  • 8
    • 0038923957 scopus 로고
    • The supreme court, 1974 term - Foreword: Constitutional common law
    • 21
    • Henry P. Monaghan, The Supreme Court, 1974 Term - Foreword: Constitutional Common Law, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 21 (1975);
    • (1975) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1
    • Monaghan, H.P.1
  • 9
    • 0039382286 scopus 로고
    • The ubiquity of prophylactic rules
    • 190. Dominating the literature on prophylactic rules is the question of constitutional legitimacy. The desirability of prophylactic rules has been occasionally considered, but only for particular rules or contexts
    • David A. Strauss, The Ubiquity of Prophylactic Rules, 55 U. Chi. L. Rev. 190, 190 (1988). Dominating the literature on prophylactic rules is the question of constitutional legitimacy. The desirability of prophylactic rules has been occasionally considered, but only for particular rules or contexts.
    • (1988) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.55 , pp. 190
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 10
    • 85055307075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The nature and function of fiduciary loyalty
    • See, e.g., 468-71
    • See, e.g., Matthew Conaglen, The Nature and Function of Fiduciary Loyalty, 121 L.Q. Rev. 452, 468-71 (2005);
    • (2005) L.Q. Rev. , vol.121 , pp. 452
    • Conaglen, M.1
  • 11
    • 77954519640 scopus 로고
    • Deconstructing the prophylactic ban on lawyer solicitation
    • 897. No theory for the general desirability of prophylactic rules has been offered. Another analogue to power rules is "nonconsummate offenses," especially "[s]imple nonconsummate offenses"
    • Drake D. Hill, Deconstructing the Prophylactic Ban on Lawyer Solicitation, 62 Temp. L. Rev. 875, 897 (1989). No theory for the general desirability of prophylactic rules has been offered. Another analogue to power rules is "nonconsummate offenses," especially "[s]imple nonconsummate offenses."
    • (1989) Temp. L. Rev. , vol.62 , pp. 875
    • Hill, D.D.1
  • 12
    • 4143152965 scopus 로고
    • The nature and justifiability of nonconsummate offenses
    • 169. Yet another analogue, also in the criminal law, is risk-creation offenses
    • Douglas N. Husak, The Nature and Justifiability of Nonconsummate Offenses, 37 Ariz. L. Rev. 151, 169 (1995). Yet another analogue, also in the criminal law, is risk-creation offenses.
    • (1995) Ariz. L. Rev. , vol.37 , pp. 151
    • Husak, D.N.1
  • 13
    • 44449147629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prohibited risks and culpable disregard or inattentiveness: Challenge and confusion in the formulation of risk-creation offenses
    • See, e.g. The concept of power rules can be seen as a different way of thinking about rules that, for the most part, fall under one or more of these headings. For such rules, this concept emphasizes not the risk of harm but rather the allocation of power and vulnerability between human actors. This shift generates a vocabulary for describing rules more precisely and observing patterns that would be missed with a more general concept like prophylactic rules. There also are differences in scope. The three analogous concepts are both broader and narrower than the concept of power rules: broader, because they include accidents and impersonal risks, see infra text accompanying note 13; and narrower, because they largely miss the category of rules described below as "power-increasing"
    • See, e.g., Paul H. Robinson, Prohibited Risks and Culpable Disregard or Inattentiveness: Challenge and Confusion in the Formulation of Risk-Creation Offenses, 4 Theoretical Inquiries L. 367 (2003). The concept of power rules can be seen as a different way of thinking about rules that, for the most part, fall under one or more of these headings. For such rules, this concept emphasizes not the risk of harm but rather the allocation of power and vulnerability between human actors. This shift generates a vocabulary for describing rules more precisely and observing patterns that would be missed with a more general concept like prophylactic rules. There also are differences in scope. The three analogous concepts are both broader and narrower than the concept of power rules: broader, because they include accidents and impersonal risks, see infra text accompanying note 13; and narrower, because they largely miss the category of rules described below as "power-increasing."
    • (2003) Theoretical Inquiries L. , vol.4 , pp. 367
    • Robinson, P.H.1
  • 14
    • 77954512497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an example, see infra note 70 and accompanying text (describing corporate law scholarship on how a certain kind of power rule is self-enforcing)
    • For an example, see infra note 70 and accompanying text (describing corporate law scholarship on how a certain kind of power rule is self-enforcing).
  • 15
    • 0001609162 scopus 로고
    • Property rules, liability rules, and inalienability: One view of the cathedral
    • Cf., 1089
    • Cf. Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 1089, 1089 (1972).
    • (1972) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.85 , pp. 1089
    • Calabresi, G.1    Melamed, A.D.2
  • 16
    • 77954502412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Grimes
    • U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 3A1.1 (b)(1) (2009); see also, 637-38 (7th Cir.) (affirming enhancement of defendant's sentence based on victims' vulnerability)
    • U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 3A1.1 (b)(1) (2009); see also United States v. Grimes, 173 F.3d 634, 637-38 (7th Cir. 1999) (affirming enhancement of defendant's sentence based on victims' vulnerability).
    • (1999) F.3d , vol.173 , pp. 634
  • 17
    • 77954476262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, revamping the phantom protections for the vulnerable elderly: Section 3Al.l(b), new hope for old victims
    • See generally, 50-51 ("The vulnerable victim sentence enhancement seeks to punish more severely criminals who victimize 'unusually vulnerable' persons such as the elderly.")
    • See generally Trent M. Murch, Note, Revamping the Phantom Protections for the Vulnerable Elderly: Section 3Al.l(b), New Hope for Old Victims, 6 Elder L.J. 49, 50-51 (1998) ("The vulnerable victim sentence enhancement seeks to punish more severely criminals who victimize 'unusually vulnerable' persons such as the elderly.").
    • (1998) Elder L.J. , vol.6 , pp. 49
    • Murch, T.M.1
  • 18
    • 0004152506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Words with a rich intellectual past, such as "power" and "vulnerability," may be best defined genealogically rather than analytically. For present purposes, however, a brief analytical definition is helpful: Power and vulnerability are correlative - power is the ability to harm another person; vulnerability is the susceptibility to being harmed by another person. These definitions abbreviate and abstract the definition of "power as domination" offered by Steven Lukes: "the ability to constrain the choices of others, coercing them or securing their compliance, by impeding them from living as their own nature and judgment dictate." (2d ed.) (reviewing half a century of debate in political theory over concept of power). As used here, power may involve resources and opportunities of almost any imaginable kind, including commodities (e.g., money, weapons) or methods of influence (e.g., advertising, threats)
    • Words with a rich intellectual past, such as "power" and "vulnerability," may be best defined genealogically rather than analytically. For present purposes, however, a brief analytical definition is helpful: Power and vulnerability are correlative - power is the ability to harm another person; vulnerability is the susceptibility to being harmed by another person. These definitions abbreviate and abstract the definition of "power as domination" offered by Steven Lukes: "the ability to constrain the choices of others, coercing them or securing their compliance, by impeding them from living as their own nature and judgment dictate." Steven Lukes, Power: A Radical View 85 (2d ed. 2005) (reviewing half a century of debate in political theory over concept of power). As used here, power may involve resources and opportunities of almost any imaginable kind, including commodities (e.g., money, weapons) or methods of influence (e.g., advertising, threats).
    • (2005) Power: A Radical View , pp. 85
    • Lukes, S.1
  • 19
    • 0002953848 scopus 로고
    • Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning
    • Contra 44 (treating power as only legal power and making it correlative to liability). Power may be granted by law, or permitted by law, or accumulated in spite of law. This conception of power and vulnerability is by no means the only one compatible with the analysis in this Essay
    • Contra Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 Yale L.J. 16, 44 (1913) (treating power as only legal power and making it correlative to liability). Power may be granted by law, or permitted by law, or accumulated in spite of law. This conception of power and vulnerability is by no means the only one compatible with the analysis in this Essay.
    • (1913) Yale L.J. , vol.23 , pp. 16
    • Hohfeld, W.N.1
  • 20
    • 33751350877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See (proposing giving every citizen "Patriot dollars" to be used for political campaign contributions)
    • See Bruce Ackerman & Ian Ayres, Voting with Dollars: A New Paradigm for Campaign Finance 4 (2002) (proposing giving every citizen "Patriot dollars" to be used for political campaign contributions).
    • (2002) Voting with Dollars: A New Paradigm for Campaign Finance , pp. 4
    • Ackerman, B.1    Ayres, I.2
  • 21
    • 36349022392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Agency problems, legal strategies and enforcement
    • The concept of power-increasing rules is analogous to "governance strategies" or "principal-empowering strategies" in corporate law. See (Reinier Kraakman et al., eds, 2d ed.)
    • The concept of power-increasing rules is analogous to "governance strategies" or "principal-empowering strategies" in corporate law. See John Armour, Henry Hansmann & Reinier Kraakman, Agency Problems, Legal Strategies and Enforcement, in The Anatomy of Corporate Law: A Comparative and Functional Approach § 2.2 (Reinier Kraakman et al., eds, 2d ed. 2009).
    • (2009) The Anatomy of Corporate Law: A Comparative and Functional Approach § 2.2
    • Armour, J.1    Hansmann, H.2    Kraakman, R.3
  • 22
    • 0003506796 scopus 로고
    • To be clear: The distinction is not in effect, because both kinds of rules can prevent harm and can alter power and vulnerability; nor is the distinction in public justification, because both are supported, at least in contemporary liberal democracies, with appeals to the ultimate prevention of harm. Rather, the distinction lies in whether the act (or condition) being regulated is perceived to be per se harmful (examples of harm rules include prohibitions on assault, rape, securities fraud, race discrimination, intentional infliction of emotional distress). One reason the distinction is not absolute is the nebulousness of what constitutes harm. See 1 ("The word 'harm' is both vague and ambiguous ....")
    • To be clear: The distinction is not in effect, because both kinds of rules can prevent harm and can alter power and vulnerability; nor is the distinction in public justification, because both are supported, at least in contemporary liberal democracies, with appeals to the ultimate prevention of harm. Rather, the distinction lies in whether the act (or condition) being regulated is perceived to be per se harmful (examples of harm rules include prohibitions on assault, rape, securities fraud, race discrimination, intentional infliction of emotional distress). One reason the distinction is not absolute is the nebulousness of what constitutes harm. See 1 Joel Feinberg, Harm to Others: The Moral Limits of Criminal Law 31-36 (1987) ("The word 'harm' is both vague and ambiguous ....");
    • (1987) Harm to Others: The Moral Limits of Criminal Law , pp. 31-36
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 23
    • 0345910646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The collapse of the harm principle
    • see also, 113 ("Claims of harm have become so pervasive that the harm principle has become meaningless . . . ."). This Essay relies on ordinary usage of the term in lieu of technical definition
    • see also Bernard E. Harcourt, The Collapse of the Harm Principle, 90 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 109, 113 (1999) ("Claims of harm have become so pervasive that the harm principle has become meaningless . . . ."). This Essay relies on ordinary usage of the term in lieu of technical definition.
    • (1999) J. Crim. L. & Criminology , vol.90 , pp. 109
    • Harcourt, B.E.1
  • 24
    • 70349427756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf.(considering why intentional trespass is a strict liability tort). Another example is a rule that an elected judge must be recused in a case involving a major contributor
    • Cf. Thomas W. Merrill & Henry E. Smith, Property: Principles and Policies 7-8 (2007) (considering why intentional trespass is a strict liability tort). Another example is a rule that an elected judge must be recused in a case involving a major contributor.
    • (2007) Property: Principles and Policies , pp. 7-8
    • Merrill, T.W.1    Smith, H.E.2
  • 25
    • 77954485897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Caperton v. A.T. Massey Coal Co.
    • See, 2256-57 (2009). Such a rule might be a harm rule, if the harm is perceived to be the appearance of impropriety, or a power rule, if the harm is perceived to be actual bias
    • See Caperton v. A.T. Massey Coal Co., 129 S. Ct. 2252, 2256-57 (2009). Such a rule might be a harm rule, if the harm is perceived to be the appearance of impropriety, or a power rule, if the harm is perceived to be actual bias.
    • S. Ct. , vol.129 , pp. 2252
  • 26
    • 77954504716 scopus 로고
    • Insults and epithets: Are they protected speech?
    • For a discussion of the various harms prevented by the regulation of fighting words, see generally 294-307. I am indebted to Kent Greenawalt for suggesting these intermediate cases
    • In addition to instances where the power/harm rule distinction turns on the characterization of the harm, there are four kinds of cases that might be considered intermediate: (1) The law regulates conduct that is not per se harmful and yet the probability of subsequent harm approaches 100% (e.g., a person purchases large quantities of a date rape drug); (2) the law regulates conduct that is not per se harmful and yet no further steps must be taken by the actor to inflict harm (e.g., a person writes a slanderous post on a blog that no one reads); (3) the law regulates conduct that is sometimes per se harmful and sometimes not and yet we cannot be sure which one is the case (e.g., a judge votes in a major contributor's case, if the harm is perceived as actual bias); and (4) the law regulates conduct that is per se harmful but does not do so primarily to prevent the coincident harm but rather to prevent a subsequent harm (e.g., a person's use of fighting words). For a discussion of the various harms prevented by the regulation of fighting words, see generally Kent Greenawalt, Insults and Epithets: Are They Protected Speech?, 42 Rutgers L. Rev. 287, 294-307 (1990). I am indebted to Kent Greenawalt for suggesting these intermediate cases.
    • (1990) Rutgers L. Rev. , vol.42 , pp. 287
    • Greenawalt, K.1
  • 27
    • 77954530908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 3 (noting that this is one of ways that concept of power rules differs from concept of prophylactic rules)
    • See supra note 3 (noting that this is one of ways that concept of power rules differs from concept of prophylactic rules).
  • 28
    • 77955394420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., 285 (2004) (statement of Rep. Osborne, previously a highly successful college football coach) ("[T]he use of steroids and precursors threatens the integrity of athletic competition.")
    • See, e.g., 150 Cong. Rec. 11,285 (2004) (statement of Rep. Osborne, previously a highly successful college football coach) ("[T]he use of steroids and precursors threatens the integrity of athletic competition.");
    • Cong. Rec. , vol.150 , pp. 11
  • 29
    • 77954471624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Drug testing of athletes - An internal, not external, matter
    • cf., 801 ("Pharmacological performance-enhancing substances are banned because of their adverse effects on both athletes' health and competitive integrity." (emphasis omitted))
    • cf. Matthew J. Mitten, Drug Testing of Athletes - An Internal, Not External, Matter, 40 New Eng. L. Rev. 797, 801 (2006) ("Pharmacological performance-enhancing substances are banned because of their adverse effects on both athletes' health and competitive integrity." (emphasis omitted)).
    • (2006) New Eng. L. Rev. , vol.40 , pp. 797
    • Mitten, M.J.1
  • 30
    • 77954511155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steroids and drug enhancements in sports: The real problem and the real solution
    • On federal criminal law and steroids, see generally, 196-97 (describing federal regulation of enhancements by Congress, DEA, and FDA)
    • On federal criminal law and steroids, see generally Colin Latiner, Steroids and Drug Enhancements in Sports: The Real Problem and the Real Solution, 3 DePaul J. Sports L. & Contemp. Probs. 192, 196-97 (2006) (describing federal regulation of enhancements by Congress, DEA, and FDA);
    • (2006) DePaul J. Sports L. & Contemp. Probs. , vol.3 , pp. 192
    • Latiner, C.1
  • 31
    • 33845751866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comment, faster, higher, stronger? Federal efforts to criminalize anabolic steroids and steroid precursors
    • 387-92 (detailing history of congressional regulation of anabolic steroids)
    • Adrian Wilairat, Comment, Faster, Higher, Stronger? Federal Efforts to Criminalize Anabolic Steroids and Steroid Precursors, 8 J. Health Care L. & Pol'y 377, 387-92 (2005) (detailing history of congressional regulation of anabolic steroids).
    • (2005) J. Health Care L. & Pol'y , vol.8 , pp. 377
    • Wilairat, A.1
  • 32
    • 77954461429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a few cases we might achieve a measure of certainty, as when a steroid-using player hits a home run that barely clears the fence
    • In a few cases we might achieve a measure of certainty, as when a steroid-using player hits a home run that barely clears the fence.
  • 33
    • 10644296780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally(offering account of legal indeterminacy, including vague expressions with borderline cases)
    • See generally Timothy A.O. Endicott, Vagueness in Law (2000) (offering account of legal indeterminacy, including vague expressions with borderline cases);
    • (2000) Vagueness in Law
    • Endicott, T.A.O.1
  • 34
    • 77954525875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preventive adjudication
    • see also (forthcoming) (distinguishing two kinds of legal indeterminacy, one of which characteristically involves borderline cases)
    • see also Samuel L. Bray, Preventive Adjudication, 77 U. Chi. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2010) (distinguishing two kinds of legal indeterminacy, one of which characteristically involves borderline cases).
    • (2010) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.77
    • Bray, S.L.1
  • 35
    • 77954509405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Randall v. Sorrell
    • 248-49 ("[C]ontribution limits that are too low can . . . harm the electoral process by preventing challengers from mounting effective campaigns against incumbent officeholders . . . .")
    • Randall v. Sorrell, 548 U.S. 230, 248-49 (2006) ("[C]ontribution limits that are too low can . . . harm the electoral process by preventing challengers from mounting effective campaigns against incumbent officeholders . . . .").
    • (2006) U.S. , vol.548 , pp. 230
  • 36
    • 84937306618 scopus 로고
    • Free speech and the widening gyre of fund-raising: Why campaign spending limits may not violate the first amendment after all
    • See, 1282-83 (arguing that candidates should be protected from having to "rais[e] money round-the-clock")
    • See Vincent Blasi, Free Speech and the Widening Gyre of Fund-Raising: Why Campaign Spending Limits May Not Violate the First Amendment After All, 94 Colum. L. Rev. 1281, 1282-83 (1994) (arguing that candidates should be protected from having to "rais[e] money round-the-clock").
    • (1994) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 1281
    • Blasi, V.1
  • 37
    • 53349134041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Promoting political equality: Spending limits in british electoral law
    • See, e.g., 499 ("[S]pending limits . . . help[ ] to create a level playing field on which campaigns can be fought without either side having an unfair advantage based on financial resources alone.")
    • See, e.g., Keith D. Ewing, Promoting Political Equality: Spending Limits in British Electoral Law, 2 Election L.J. 499, 499 (2003) ("[S]pending limits . . . help[ ] to create a level playing field on which campaigns can be fought without either side having an unfair advantage based on financial resources alone.");
    • (2003) Election L.J. , vol.2 , pp. 499
    • Ewing, K.D.1
  • 38
    • 77954524793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The newer incoherence: Competition, social science, and balancing in campaign finance law after Randall v. Sorrell
    • see also, 887 (suggesting equality as goal of some campaign finance limits). But see Citizens United v. FEC, No. 08-205, 2010 WL 183856, at *25-30 (U.S.Jan. 21, 2010) (rejecting equality rationale on First Amendment grounds)
    • see also Richard L. Hasen, The Newer Incoherence: Competition, Social Science, and Balancing in Campaign Finance Law After Randall v. Sorrell, 68 Ohio St. L.J. 849, 887 (2007) (suggesting equality as goal of some campaign finance limits). But see Citizens United v. FEC, No. 08-205, 2010 WL 183856, at *25-30 (U.S.Jan. 21, 2010) (rejecting equality rationale on First Amendment grounds).
    • (2007) Ohio St. L.J. , vol.68 , pp. 849
    • Hasen, R.L.1
  • 39
    • 77954511913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Blasi, supra note 18, at 1282 (noting that the " [disproportionate influence" of a campaign contributor on an officeholder "is hard to measure")
    • Cf. Blasi, supra note 18, at 1282 (noting that the " [disproportionate influence" of a campaign contributor on an officeholder "is hard to measure").
  • 40
    • 77954477310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Davis v. FEC
    • A power-increasing rule in election law was the Millionaires' Amendment passed as part of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act; it allowed a candidate with a wealthy rival to receive larger campaign donations and coordinated party expenditures. See (holding Millionaires' Amendment unconstitutional on First Amendment grounds). Other power-increasing rules might include a constitutional requirement to have majority-minority districts, or Bruce Ackerman and Ian Ayres's notion of Patriot dollars. On the latter, see generally Ackerman & Ayres, supra note 8
    • A power-increasing rule in election law was the Millionaires' Amendment passed as part of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act; it allowed a candidate with a wealthy rival to receive larger campaign donations and coordinated party expenditures. See Davis v. FEC, 128 S. Ct. 2759 (2008) (holding Millionaires' Amendment unconstitutional on First Amendment grounds). Other power-increasing rules might include a constitutional requirement to have majority-minority districts, or Bruce Ackerman and Ian Ayres's notion of Patriot dollars. On the latter, see generally Ackerman & Ayres, supra note 8.
    • (2008) S. Ct. , vol.128 , pp. 2759
  • 41
    • 77954481094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aggressive parental leave incentivizing: A statutory proposal toward gender equalization in the workplace
    • For discussion of such a proposal, see, 301 & n.34
    • For discussion of such a proposal, see Ariel Meysam Ayanna, Aggressive Parental Leave Incentivizing: A Statutory Proposal Toward Gender Equalization in the Workplace, 9 U. Pa. J. Lab. & Emp. L. 293, 301 & n.34 (2007);
    • (2007) U. Pa. J. Lab. & Emp. L. , vol.9 , pp. 293
    • Ayanna, A.M.1
  • 42
    • 0039291411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Family leave and the gender wage gap
    • 773-75
    • Michael Selmi, Family Leave and the Gender Wage Gap, 78 N.C. L. Rev. 707, 773-75 (2000);
    • (2000) N.C. L. Rev. , vol.78 , pp. 707
    • Selmi, M.1
  • 43
    • 0347710451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human behavior and the law of work
    • cf., 261-64 (analyzing nonwaivable rights in context of norm and preference change)
    • cf. Cass R. Sunstein, Human Behavior and the Law of Work, 87 Va. L. Rev. 205, 261-64 (2001) (analyzing nonwaivable rights in context of norm and preference change).
    • (2001) Va. L. Rev. , vol.87 , pp. 205
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 44
    • 77954470303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Parts II.B, III, and IV
    • See infra Parts II.B, III, and IV.
  • 45
    • 77954517401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the central case involving human actors, the law might be unable to reach the agent because the agent is impersonal. For example, to protect persons whose homes are vulnerable to earthquakes, the law relies on building codes that regulate structural materials, because an earthquake cannot be held liable for the injuries it causes
    • Beyond the central case involving human actors, the law might be unable to reach the agent because the agent is impersonal. For example, to protect persons whose homes are vulnerable to earthquakes, the law relies on building codes that regulate structural materials, because an earthquake cannot be held liable for the injuries it causes.
  • 46
    • 77954505915 scopus 로고
    • NLRB v. Gissel Packing Co.
    • 616-20 (upholding NLRB's finding of unfair labor practice where employer threatened economic retaliation if employees voted for union recognition)
    • NLRB v. Gissel Packing Co., 395 U.S. 575, 616-20 (1969) (upholding NLRB's finding of unfair labor practice where employer threatened economic retaliation if employees voted for union recognition).
    • (1969) U.S. , vol.395 , pp. 575
  • 47
    • 77954494969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 42 U.S.C. § 1395ss(x)(2) (2006) (prohibiting collection of genetic information by medical insurers "prior to . . . enrollment" and "for underwriting purposes")
    • See 42 U.S.C. § 1395ss(x)(2) (2006) (prohibiting collection of genetic information by medical insurers "prior to . . . enrollment" and "for underwriting purposes").
  • 48
    • 77954525490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For discussion of power-decreasing rules, see supra Part I
    • For discussion of power-decreasing rules, see supra Part I.
  • 49
    • 77954501529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are exceptions. Sometimes the people a power rule is meant to protect - such as economically disadvantaged political candidates, who benefit from some campaign finance power rules - will have an incentive to find violations. And sometimes the people a harm rule is meant to protect will have reasons to avoid speaking out, such as fear of social retaliation for filing a complaint. But as a general matter, when someone violates a power rule it is less likely that there will be an identifiable victim to spur enforcement
    • There are exceptions. Sometimes the people a power rule is meant to protect - such as economically disadvantaged political candidates, who benefit from some campaign finance power rules - will have an incentive to find violations. And sometimes the people a harm rule is meant to protect will have reasons to avoid speaking out, such as fear of social retaliation for filing a complaint. But as a general matter, when someone violates a power rule it is less likely that there will be an identifiable victim to spur enforcement.
  • 52
    • 36248979073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Changing name changing: Framing rules and the future of marital names
    • see also, 842 (concluding that even when law plays "a marginal role," it can give a "small push ... to help individuals overcome the collective action problem involved in changing social meaning")
    • see also Elizabeth F. Emens, Changing Name Changing: Framing Rules and the Future of Marital Names, 74 U. Chi. L. Rev. 761, 842 (2007) (concluding that even when law plays "a marginal role," it can give a "small push ... to help individuals overcome the collective action problem involved in changing social meaning").
    • (2007) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.74 , pp. 761
    • Emens, E.F.1
  • 53
    • 62549087027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the prisoners' dilemma: Coordination, game theory, and law
    • See, 233-35
    • See Richard H. McAdams, Beyond the Prisoners' Dilemma: Coordination, Game Theory, and Law, 82 S. Cal. L. Rev. 209, 233-35 (2009).
    • (2009) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.82 , pp. 209
    • McAdams, R.H.1
  • 54
    • 33645775188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Menus matter
    • On the regulation of choice and the regulation of social meaning, see generally
    • On the regulation of choice and the regulation of social meaning, see generally Ian Ayres, Menus Matter, 73 U. Chi. L. Rev. 3 (2006);
    • (2006) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 3
    • Ayres, I.1
  • 55
    • 33750159669 scopus 로고
    • The regulation of social meaning
    • see also supra note 30
    • Lawrence Lessig, The Regulation of Social Meaning, 62 U. Chi. L. Rev. 943 (1995); see also supra note 30.
    • (1995) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.62 , pp. 943
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 56
    • 77954514763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the function of a prophylactic rule. See supra note 3
    • This is the function of a prophylactic rule. See supra note 3.
  • 57
    • 77954505075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Given the efficient market hypothesis, a prohibition on false disclosures could be considered a harm rule
    • Given the efficient market hypothesis, a prohibition on false disclosures could be considered a harm rule.
  • 58
    • 70349467716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Manufacturing crime: Process, pretext, and criminal justice
    • A similar shift in focus can be observed in the enforcement of "process crimes." See
    • A similar shift in focus can be observed in the enforcement of "process crimes." See Erin Murphy, Manufacturing Crime: Process, Pretext, and Criminal Justice, 97 Geo. L.J. 1435 (2009).
    • (2009) Geo. L.J. , vol.97 , pp. 1435
    • Murphy, E.1
  • 59
    • 77954473951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Me. Rev. Stat. Ann. tit. 17-A, § 403 (2006) (criminalizing possession of "burglar's tools," i.e., "any tool, implement, instrument or other article that is adapted, designed or commonly used for . . . forcible breaking of safes or other containers or depositories of property")
    • See, e.g., Me. Rev. Stat. Ann. tit. 17-A, § 403 (2006) (criminalizing possession of "burglar's tools," i.e., "any tool, implement, instrument or other article that is adapted, designed or commonly used for . . . forcible breaking of safes or other containers or depositories of property").
  • 60
    • 77954493328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An exception is cases where the violation of a power rule merges with the violation of a harm rule. In a jurisdiction where conspiracy merges with the completed crime, a power rule prohibiting conspiracy would lack this cumulative effect
    • An exception is cases where the violation of a power rule merges with the violation of a harm rule. In a jurisdiction where conspiracy merges with the completed crime, a power rule prohibiting conspiracy would lack this cumulative effect.
  • 61
    • 0345807564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The pathological politics of criminal law
    • This bent of legislators in the United States has been critiqued for decades by the academy, to no apparent effect. See, e.g., 508 [hereinafter Stuntz, Pathological Politics] (noting legislators' imperviousness to "normative arguments" and decrying how "American criminal law's historical development has borne no relation to any plausible normative theory - unless 'more' counts as a normative theory"). On power rules and enforcement discretion, see infra Parts III.C and IV
    • This bent of legislators in the United States has been critiqued for decades by the academy, to no apparent effect. See, e.g., William J. Stuntz, The Pathological Politics of Criminal Law, 100 Mich. L. Rev. 505, 508 (2001) [hereinafter Stuntz, Pathological Politics] (noting legislators' imperviousness to "normative arguments" and decrying how "American criminal law's historical development has borne no relation to any plausible normative theory - unless 'more' counts as a normative theory"). On power rules and enforcement discretion, see infra Parts III.C and IV.
    • (2001) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.100 , pp. 505
    • Stuntz, W.J.1
  • 62
    • 77954464805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Militia Act of 1792, ch. 33, 1 Stat. 271; Statute of Winchester, 1285, 13 Edw. 1, cc. 1, 4 (Eng.); Assize of Arms, 1181, 27 Hen. 2 (Eng.); see also (discussing laws in twelfth and thirteenth centuries that required English subjects to bear arms)
    • See, e.g., Militia Act of 1792, ch. 33, 1 Stat. 271; Statute of Winchester, 1285, 13 Edw. 1, cc. 1, 4 (Eng.); Assize of Arms, 1181, 27 Hen. 2 (Eng.); see also Frederick Wilkinson, Those Entrusted with Arms: The Police, Post, Prison, Customs and Private Use of Weapons in Britain 9-13 (2002) (discussing laws in twelfth and thirteenth centuries that required English subjects to bear arms).
    • (2002) Those Entrusted with Arms: The Police, Post, Prison, Customs and Private Use of Weapons in Britain , pp. 9-13
    • Wilkinson, F.1
  • 63
    • 34547485336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strict judicial scrutiny
    • This point is widely recognized for prophylactic rules. See, e.g., 1272 (using "overbroad" and "prophylactic" as effectively synonymous)
    • This point is widely recognized for prophylactic rules. See, e.g., Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Strict Judicial Scrutiny, 54 UCLA L. Rev. 1267, 1272 (2007) (using "overbroad" and "prophylactic" as effectively synonymous).
    • (2007) UCLA L. Rev. , vol.54 , pp. 1267
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 64
    • 77954464197 scopus 로고
    • Comment, the anabolic steroids control act of 1990: A need for change
    • Thus each of the regulations of competition described above raises overbreadth concerns. See, e.g., Blasi, supra note 18, at 1314-16 (noting overbreadth issue for campaign spending limits), 132 (criticizing steroids law as overbroad). Power-increasing rules also suffer from a kind of overbreadth: If a vulnerable person is required to maintain a certain power - such as firearms for convenience store clerks - that power could be misused with terrible consequences
    • Thus each of the regulations of competition described above raises overbreadth concerns. See, e.g., Blasi, supra note 18, at 1314-16 (noting overbreadth issue for campaign spending limits); Jeffrey A. Black, Comment, The Anabolic Steroids Control Act of 1990: A Need for Change, 97 Dick. L. Rev. 131, 132 (1992) (criticizing steroids law as overbroad). Power-increasing rules also suffer from a kind of overbreadth: If a vulnerable person is required to maintain a certain power - such as firearms for convenience store clerks - that power could be misused with terrible consequences.
    • (1992) Dick. L. Rev. , vol.97 , pp. 131
    • Black, J.A.1
  • 65
    • 77954518055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Offenses against public order and safety: Make wearing bulletproof vests during commission or attempted commission of certain offenses unlawful
    • S.C. § 931 (2006) (making it a federal crime for anyone convicted of a violent felony to "purchase, own, or possess body armor"); see also U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 2K2.6 (2009) (increasing federal sentence of anyone who used body armor in connection with another felony offense); (detailing Georgia statute that "makes it unlawful to wear a bulletproof vest during the commission or attempted commission of certain offenses")
    • S.C. § 931 (2006) (making it a federal crime for anyone convicted of a violent felony to "purchase, own, or possess body armor"); see also U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 2K2.6 (2009) (increasing federal sentence of anyone who used body armor in connection with another felony offense); Joseph Larkin, Offenses Against Public Order and Safety: Make Wearing Bulletproof Vests During Commission or Attempted Commission of Certain Offenses Unlawful, 20 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 95 (2003) (detailing Georgia statute that "makes it unlawful to wear a bulletproof vest during the commission or attempted commission of certain offenses").
    • (2003) Ga. St. U. L. Rev. , vol.20 , pp. 95
    • Larkin, J.1
  • 66
    • 77954471836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Patton
    • These facts are drawn from, 618-20 (10th Cir.)
    • These facts are drawn from United States v. Patton, 451 F.3d 615, 618-20 (10th Cir. 2006).
    • (2006) F.3d , vol.451 , pp. 615
  • 67
    • 77954482610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If, however, the rationale is considered to be the protection of the state itself, the restriction would not be overbroad, though it might well be unnecessary or excessive. On power rules and the state, see infra note 53
    • If, however, the rationale is considered to be the protection of the state itself, the restriction would not be overbroad, though it might well be unnecessary or excessive. On power rules and the state, see infra note 53.
  • 68
    • 54749141221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., 1 ("The major problem with possession offenses ... is overbreadth."). In administrative law attention has been paid to overbreadth as a problem of the optimal specification of rules
    • One could imagine harm rules that are overbroad: an example would be the rule that "no one may draw blood in the streets of Bologna" if applied to doctors engaged in the competent practice of medicine. And one could imagine power rules that are not overbroad, such as the ban on private possession of nuclear weapons noted below. So it is not necessary that power rules be overbroad relative to harm rules. But in actual use the tendency of power rules toward overbreadth is pervasive; it is also unsurprising, given power rules' less direct approach to preventing harm, see supra Part I. Overbreadth is an important topic in multiple areas of legal scholarship, and only selective examples can be noted here. In criminal law scholars have emphasized overbreadth concerns in discussion of the overlapping categories of anticipatory, inchoate, strict4iability, and possessory offenses. See, e.g., 1 George P. Fletcher, The Grammar of Criminal Law 295 (2007) ("The major problem with possession offenses ... is overbreadth."). In administrative law attention has been paid to overbreadth as a problem of the optimal specification of rules.
    • (2007) The Grammar of Criminal Law , pp. 295
    • Fletcher, G.P.1
  • 69
    • 84926274214 scopus 로고
    • The optimal precision of administrative rules
    • See, e.g., 75. In various contexts scholars and courts have considered the conditions in which law should be defeasible, allowing individuals to show that a generally applicable legal rule should not apply in their cases. See, e.g., United States v. Engstrum, No. 2:08-CR-430 TS, 2009 WL 1683285, at *1 (D. Utah June 15, 2009) (Second Amendment), rev'd sub nom
    • See, e.g., Colin S. Diver, The Optimal Precision of Administrative Rules, 93 Yale L.J. 65, 75 (1983). In various contexts scholars and courts have considered the conditions in which law should be defeasible, allowing individuals to show that a generally applicable legal rule should not apply in their cases. See, e.g., United States v. Engstrum, No. 2:08-CR-430 TS, 2009 WL 1683285, at *1 (D. Utah June 15, 2009) (Second Amendment), rev'd sub nom.
    • (1983) Yale L.J. , vol.93 , pp. 65
    • Diver, C.S.1
  • 70
    • 77954500489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In re United States
    • 1197 (10th Cir.)
    • In re United States, 578 F.3d 1195, 1197 (10th Cir. 2009);
    • (2009) F.3d , vol.578 , pp. 1195
  • 72
    • 29044443515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Criminalizing endangerment
    • 961-62 (criminal law)
    • R.A. Duff, Criminalizing Endangerment, 65 La. L. Rev. 941, 961-62 (2005) (criminal law);
    • (2005) La. L. Rev. , vol.65 , pp. 941
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 73
    • 41249089558 scopus 로고
    • Free exercise revisionism and the smith decision
    • 1110-11 (Free Exercise Clause)
    • Michael W. McConnell, Free Exercise Revisionism and the Smith Decision, 57 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1109, 1110-11 (1990) (Free Exercise Clause).
    • (1990) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.57 , pp. 1109
    • McConnell, M.W.1
  • 74
    • 84928439700 scopus 로고
    • Making sense of overbreadth
    • Overbreadth is of course a distinct doctrine in constitutional law, see, e.g., and questions of overbreadth and optimal specificity feature prominently in the massive literature on rules and standards, see generally Frederick Schauer, Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in Life (1991)
    • Overbreadth is of course a distinct doctrine in constitutional law, see, e.g., Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Making Sense of Overbreadth, 100 Yale L.J. 853 (1991), and questions of overbreadth and optimal specificity feature prominently in the massive literature on rules and standards, see generally Frederick Schauer, Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in Life (1991).
    • (1991) Yale L.J. , vol.100 , pp. 853
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 75
    • 77954477296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S.C. § 831; see also id. § 175 (prohibiting possession of biological weapons); id. § 229 (prohibiting possession of chemical weapons); 42 U.S.C. § 2181(a) (2006) (restricting patents "useful solely ... in an atomic weapon")
    • S.C. § 831; see also id. § 175 (prohibiting possession of biological weapons); id. § 229 (prohibiting possession of chemical weapons); 42 U.S.C. § 2181(a) (2006) (restricting patents "useful solely ... in an atomic weapon").
  • 76
    • 66449129697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The gun control debate: A culture-theory manifesto
    • See generally (arguing that "cultural world views" inform "[b]eliefs about the causes and effective responses to societal risks")
    • See generally Dan M. Kahan, The Gun Control Debate: A Culture-Theory Manifesto, 60 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 3 (2003) (arguing that "cultural world views" inform "[b]eliefs about the causes and effective responses to societal risks").
    • (2003) Wash. & Lee L. Rev. , vol.60 , pp. 3
    • Kahan, D.M.1
  • 78
    • 25844494304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why roll calls? A model of position-taking in legislative voting and elections
    • developing "rationale for roll call voting and position-taking in legislatures"
    • James M. Snyder, Jr. & Michael M. Ting, Why Roll Calls? A Model of Position-Taking in Legislative Voting and Elections, 21 J.L. Econ. & Org. 153 (2005) (developing "rationale for roll call voting and position-taking in legislatures");
    • (2005) J.L. Econ. & Org. , vol.21 , pp. 153
    • Snyder Jr., J.M.1    Ting, M.M.2
  • 79
    • 2442528211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Congress as culprit: How lawmakers spurred on the court's anti-congress crusade
    • see also, 461-62 (arguing Congress has increasingly favored symbolic messages over effective legislation)
    • see also Neal Devins, Congress as Culprit: How Lawmakers Spurred on the Court's Anti-Congress Crusade, 51 Duke L.J. 435, 461-62 (2001) (arguing Congress has increasingly favored symbolic messages over effective legislation).
    • (2001) Duke L.J. , vol.51 , pp. 435
    • Devins, N.1
  • 80
    • 77954511156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Shortt
    • Cf. Black, supra note 41, at 132 (noting only one indictment under Anabolic Steroids Control Act of 1990 in year or two following its passage). But see, 244 (4th Cir.) (upholding one-year sentence for doctor prescribing anabolic steroids and human growth hormone to bodybuilders and professional football players)
    • Cf. Black, supra note 41, at 132 (noting only one indictment under Anabolic Steroids Control Act of 1990 in year or two following its passage). But see United States v. Shortt, 485 F.3d 243, 244 (4th Cir. 2007) (upholding one-year sentence for doctor prescribing anabolic steroids and human growth hormone to bodybuilders and professional football players).
    • (2007) F.3d , vol.485 , pp. 243
  • 81
    • 0002099638 scopus 로고
    • The technology of personal violence
    • See, 61 (describing ordinance in Atlanta, Georgia suburb "requiring every household in the city to keep a firearm in their home"); cf. supra note 39 and accompanying text (noting historical statutes requiring private persons to carry weapons to help secure the peace)
    • See Philip J. Cook, The Technology of Personal Violence, 14 Crime & Just. 1, 61 (1991) (describing ordinance in Atlanta, Georgia suburb "requiring every household in the city to keep a firearm in their home"); cf. supra note 39 and accompanying text (noting historical statutes requiring private persons to carry weapons to help secure the peace).
    • (1991) Crime & Just. , vol.14 , pp. 1
    • Cook, P.J.1
  • 82
    • 78149446644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Badawi, supra note 30 (suggesting that purely expressive laws allow governments to realize "efficiency gains . . . with little or no enforcement costs"). For entry points to the substantial literature on law and social norms, see generally
    • See generally Badawi, supra note 30 (suggesting that purely expressive laws allow governments to realize "efficiency gains . . . with little or no enforcement costs"). For entry points to the substantial literature on law and social norms, see generally Eric A. Posner, Law and Social Norms (2000);
    • (2000) Law and Social Norms
    • Posner, E.A.1
  • 83
    • 0001695934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The origin, development and regulation of norms
    • Richard H. McAdams, The Origin, Development and Regulation of Norms, 96 Mich. L. Rev. 338 (1997).
    • (1997) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.96 , pp. 338
    • McAdams, R.H.1
  • 84
    • 4043172793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Righting victim wrongs: Responding to philosophical criticisms of the nonspecific victim liability defense
    • See, e.g., 492 ("Many courts and legislatures have defined the mens rea element in possession crimes as something like negligence.")
    • See, e.g., Aya Gruber, Righting Victim Wrongs: Responding to Philosophical Criticisms of the Nonspecific Victim Liability Defense, 52 Buff. L. Rev. 433, 492 (2004) ("Many courts and legislatures have defined the mens rea element in possession crimes as something like negligence.").
    • (2004) Buff. L. Rev. , vol.52 , pp. 433
    • Gruber, A.1
  • 85
    • 0347710366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Policing possession: The war on crime and the end of criminal law
    • For a broadside against possession offenses in the criminal law, see, 855-934
    • For a broadside against possession offenses in the criminal law, see Markus Dirk Dubber, Policing Possession: The War on Crime and the End of Criminal Law, 91 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 829, 855-934 (2001).
    • (2001) J. Crim. L. & Criminology , vol.91 , pp. 829
    • Dubber, M.D.1
  • 86
    • 38349147111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy and decriminalization
    • On the distinction between overbreadth and redundancy in criminal law, see, 230-31
    • On the distinction between overbreadth and redundancy in criminal law, see Darryl K. Brown, Democracy and Decriminalization, 86 Tex. L. Rev. 223, 230-31 (2007).
    • (2007) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.86 , pp. 223
    • Brown, D.K.1
  • 87
    • 66249084258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutional design and the policing of prosecutors: Lessons from administrative law
    • The desirability of overbroad power rules in the criminal law will of course depend on many other facts, including the institutional characteristics of prosecutors' offices, see
    • The desirability of overbroad power rules in the criminal law will of course depend on many other facts, including the institutional characteristics of prosecutors' offices, see Rachel E. Barkow, Institutional Design and the Policing of Prosecutors: Lessons from Administrative Law, 61 Stan. L. Rev. 869 (2009);
    • (2009) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.61 , pp. 869
    • Barkow, R.E.1
  • 88
    • 66049101723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prosecutorial regulation versus prosecutorial accountability
    • and the constraints on official conduct that may be imposed by constitutional rights and the legal rules that give them practical force (e.g., the exclusionary rule, 42 U.S.C. § 1983 (2006)). Although this Essay focuses on power rules that protect one private person from another, the concept might be applied to the interactions of branches of government (e.g., separation of powers prevents the concentration of power by any one branch). The concept might also be applied to the interactions of citizens and the state. Some legal rules limit the power of the state vis-à-vis citizens (e.g., the Fourth Amendment), and others make the state vulnerable to its citizens (e.g., the Freedom of Information Act, or exceptions to sovereign immunity). This is not to suggest that states seek an equality of vulnerability with their citizens - exceptions to sovereign immunity are exceptions to the general rule
    • Stephanos Bibas, Prosecutorial Regulation Versus Prosecutorial Accountability, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 959 (2009), and the constraints on official conduct that may be imposed by constitutional rights and the legal rules that give them practical force (e.g., the exclusionary rule, 42 U.S.C. § 1983 (2006)). Although this Essay focuses on power rules that protect one private person from another, the concept might be applied to the interactions of branches of government (e.g., separation of powers prevents the concentration of power by any one branch). The concept might also be applied to the interactions of citizens and the state. Some legal rules limit the power of the state vis-à-vis citizens (e.g., the Fourth Amendment), and others make the state vulnerable to its citizens (e.g., the Freedom of Information Act, or exceptions to sovereign immunity). This is not to suggest that states seek an equality of vulnerability with their citizens - exceptions to sovereign immunity are exceptions to the general rule.
    • (2009) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.157 , pp. 959
    • Bibas, S.1
  • 89
    • 38949184007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Optimal discretion in the application of rules
    • See Diver, supra note 45, at 67-71 (discussing congruence as one aspect of the optimal precision of rules). On discretion and rule enforcement, see generally
    • See Diver, supra note 45, at 67-71 (discussing congruence as one aspect of the optimal precision of rules). On discretion and rule enforcement, see generally Steven Shavell, Optimal Discretion in the Application of Rules, 9 Am. L. & Econ. Rev. 175 (2007).
    • (2007) Am. L. & Econ. Rev. , vol.9 , pp. 175
    • Shavell, S.1
  • 90
    • 3042773697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plea bargaining and criminal law's disappearing shadow
    • 2548; see also Stuntz, Pathological Politics, supra note 38, at 519-20 (describing consequences of prosecutors having a greater number of charging options). Another way of making this point is to say that power rules tend to increase the amount of delegated criminal lawmaking
    • William J. Stuntz, Plea Bargaining and Criminal Law's Disappearing Shadow, 117 Harv. L. Rev. 2548, 2548 (2004); see also Stuntz, Pathological Politics, supra note 38, at 519-20 (describing consequences of prosecutors having a greater number of charging options). Another way of making this point is to say that power rules tend to increase the amount of delegated criminal lawmaking.
    • (2004) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.117 , pp. 2548
    • Stuntz, W.J.1
  • 91
    • 0347790360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lenity and federal common law crimes
    • See generally (arguing "historic underenforcement of lenity" reflects a "rule of criminal law: that Congress may delegate criminal lawmaking power to courts" (emphasis omitted))
    • See generally Dan M. Kahan, Lenity and Federal Common Law Crimes, 1994 Sup. Ct. Rev. 345 (arguing "historic underenforcement of lenity" reflects a "rule of criminal law: that Congress may delegate criminal lawmaking power to courts" (emphasis omitted)).
    • 1994 Sup. Ct. Rev. , pp. 345
    • Kahan, D.M.1
  • 92
    • 77954501530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For qualification, see supra note 37 (noting exception where violation of a power rule merges with violation of a harm rule). The complementary use of power rules also increases the options available to juries. When a prosecutor does charge a defendant with multiple offenses, and the case goes to trial, jurors could convict on charge one but not charges two and three, and so on
    • For qualification, see supra note 37 (noting exception where violation of a power rule merges with violation of a harm rule). The complementary use of power rules also increases the options available to juries. When a prosecutor does charge a defendant with multiple offenses, and the case goes to trial, jurors could convict on charge one but not charges two and three, and so on.
  • 93
    • 0345999272 scopus 로고
    • Plea bargaining and its history
    • See generally, 16-26 (describing rise of plea bargaining)
    • See generally Albert W. Alschuler, Plea Bargaining and Its History, 79 Colum. L. Rev. 1, 16-26 (1979) (describing rise of plea bargaining);
    • (1979) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.79 , pp. 1
    • Alschuler, A.W.1
  • 94
    • 3042853798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plea bargaining outside the shadow of trial
    • 2469-96 (describing structural influences on plea bargaining, such as the Federal Sentencing Guidelines)
    • Stephanos Bibas, Plea Bargaining Outside the Shadow of Trial, 117 Harv. L. Rev. 2463, 2469-96 (2004) (describing structural influences on plea bargaining, such as the Federal Sentencing Guidelines).
    • (2004) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.117 , pp. 2463
    • Bibas, S.1
  • 95
    • 0039580144 scopus 로고
    • Unconscionability: A critical reappraisal
    • 304 (noting that in some cases, "[p]roof of fraud is apt to be difficult . . . even if the fraud itself is likely")
    • Richard A. Epstein, Unconscionability: A Critical Reappraisal, 18 J.L. & Econ. 293, 304 (1975) (noting that in some cases, "[p]roof of fraud is apt to be difficult . . . even if the fraud itself is likely").
    • (1975) J.L. & Econ. , vol.18 , pp. 293
    • Epstein, R.A.1
  • 96
    • 77954477653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 97
    • 77954480949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. Epstein distinguishes the situation in which the returning prisoner of war sought out the municipal bond seller - there unconscionability should not be applied to make the transaction voidable. Id
    • Id. Epstein distinguishes the situation in which the returning prisoner of war sought out the municipal bond seller - there unconscionability should not be applied to make the transaction voidable. Id.
  • 98
    • 77954467584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intriguingly, the degree of overbreadth might not be correlated with a power rule's ability to make law enforcement more efficient through prevention, proof, and punitive flexibility
    • Intriguingly, the degree of overbreadth might not be correlated with a power rule's ability to make law enforcement more efficient through prevention, proof, and punitive flexibility.
  • 99
    • 1542718582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See (7th ed.) (describing development of law on transactions with interested directors). Such a rule does obtain in the United Kingdom, but it operates as a penalty default rule: A transaction with a director is voidable if the director fails to make disclosures required by Companies Act, 2006, c. 2, § 177
    • See Jesse H. Choper, John C. Coffee, Jr. & Ronald J. Gilson, Cases and Materials on Corporations 111-12 (7th ed. 2008) (describing development of law on transactions with interested directors). Such a rule does obtain in the United Kingdom, but it operates as a penalty default rule: A transaction with a director is voidable if the director fails to make disclosures required by Companies Act, 2006, c. 2, § 177.
    • (2008) Cases and Materials on Corporations , pp. 111-112
    • Choper, J.H.1    Coffee Jr., J.C.2    Gilson, R.J.3
  • 100
    • 85007996160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Controlling fiduciary power
    • For a systematic analysis of how law can constrain fiduciary power, with special attention paid to the powers of trustees and corporate directors, see generally
    • For a systematic analysis of how law can constrain fiduciary power, with special attention paid to the powers of trustees and corporate directors, see generally R.C. Nolan, Controlling Fiduciary Power, 68 Cambridge L.J. 293 (2009).
    • (2009) Cambridge L.J. , vol.68 , pp. 293
    • Nolan, R.C.1
  • 101
    • 0347514460 scopus 로고
    • Abuse of rights: A pervasive legal concept
    • See id. at 297-304 (discussing "improper purposes doctrine"). On the tacit condition that legal rights may not be used for purely malicious reasons, see, 37
    • See id. at 297-304 (discussing "improper purposes doctrine"). On the tacit condition that legal rights may not be used for purely malicious reasons, see Joseph M. Perillo, Abuse of Rights: A Pervasive Legal Concept, 27 Pac. L.J. 37, 37 (1995);
    • (1995) Pac. L.J. , vol.27 , pp. 37
    • Perillo, J.M.1
  • 102
    • 77954478144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also (2d ed.) (detailing equitable methods of regulating abuse of power by decisionmakers). Any conditions that accompany power-increasing rules should be intuitive and straightforward; otherwise they would prevent vulnerable people from being confident that they could exercise the power
    • see also Sarah Worthington, Equity 142-47 (2d ed. 2006) (detailing equitable methods of regulating abuse of power by decisionmakers). Any conditions that accompany power-increasing rules should be intuitive and straightforward; otherwise they would prevent vulnerable people from being confident that they could exercise the power.
    • (2006) Sarah Worthington, Equity , pp. 142-147
  • 103
    • 34547574288 scopus 로고
    • Decision rules and conduct rules: On acoustic separation in criminal law
    • Cf., 651, 668-73 (concluding that clarity and accessibility matter more for conduct rules than for decision rules); Diver, supra note 45, at 76-77 (concluding that transparency is more important for external rules than for internal rules)
    • Cf. Meir Dan-Cohen, Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law, 97 Harv. L. Rev. 625, 651, 668-73 (1984) (concluding that clarity and accessibility matter more for conduct rules than for decision rules); Diver, supra note 45, at 76-77 (concluding that transparency is more important for external rules than for internal rules);
    • (1984) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.97 , pp. 625
    • Dan-Cohen, M.1
  • 104
    • 84930557482 scopus 로고
    • Rules of conduct and principles of adjudication
    • 732 ("[E]ffective . . . rules of conduct must be simple, based on objective criteria with easily communicable and comprehensible standards.")
    • Paul H. Robinson, Rules of Conduct and Principles of Adjudication, 57 U. Chi. L. Rev. 729, 732 (1990) ("[E]ffective . . . rules of conduct must be simple, based on objective criteria with easily communicable and comprehensible standards.").
    • (1990) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.57 , pp. 729
    • Robinson, P.H.1
  • 105
    • 42949148140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justifications, powers, and authority
    • See, 1072-74 (discussing "division of labor between those who have the legal power to decide what conduct is . . . legally justified in the circumstances and those who carry out that conduct"). Note that Thorburn uses "power" in the Hohfeldian sense of legal power rather than the sense in which it is used in this Essay. Compare id. at 1073 n.1, with supra note 7
    • See Malcolm Thorburn, Justifications, Powers, and Authority, 117 Yale L.J. 1070, 1072-74 (2008) (discussing "division of labor between those who have the legal power to decide what conduct is . . . legally justified in the circumstances and those who carry out that conduct"). Note that Thorburn uses "power" in the Hohfeldian sense of legal power rather than the sense in which it is used in this Essay. Compare id. at 1073 n.1, with supra note 7.
    • (2008) Yale L.J. , vol.117 , pp. 1070
    • Thorburn, M.1
  • 106
    • 77954512110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diver, supra note 45, at 98. See generally id. at 97-106 (offering standard explanations for gap between public interest and decisions of administrative officials)
    • Diver, supra note 45, at 98. See generally id. at 97-106 (offering standard explanations for gap between public interest and decisions of administrative officials).
  • 107
    • 33846645025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Auditing executive discretion
    • For suggestions about how this judgment can rest on systematic evaluation of enforcing officials, see
    • For suggestions about how this judgment can rest on systematic evaluation of enforcing officials, see Mariano-Florentino Cuéllar, Auditing Executive Discretion, 82 Notre Dame L. Rev. 227 (2006).
    • (2006) Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.82 , pp. 227
    • Cuéllar, M.-F.1
  • 108
    • 77954489614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a description of this comparative advantage in baseball, see Doug Glanville, Seeing Is Disbelieving, Opinionator, Jan. 21, 2010, at (on file with the Columbia Law Review)
    • For a description of this comparative advantage in baseball, see Doug Glanville, Seeing Is Disbelieving, Opinionator, Jan. 21, 2010, at http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes. com/2010/01/21/seeing-is-disbelieving/ (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
  • 109
    • 77954527515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 30-31 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 30-31 and accompanying text.
  • 110
    • 77954481093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Armour, Hansmann & Kraakman, supra note 9, at § 2.3.1 (noting enforcement institution in corporate law is "only of second-order importance" for "principal-empowering strategies" in corporate law). Because power-increasing rules can decentralize enforcement, they raise a number of questions. Who is better positioned to avoid the harm: the state or the newly empowered vulnerable person? And would a power-increasing rule foster individual responsibility and elevate vulnerable persons? Or would it signal a lack of protection from the state and encourage a culture of blaming those who suffer injury?
    • See Armour, Hansmann & Kraakman, supra note 9, at § 2.3.1 (noting enforcement institution in corporate law is "only of second-order importance" for "principal-empowering strategies" in corporate law). Because power-increasing rules can decentralize enforcement, they raise a number of questions. Who is better positioned to avoid the harm: the state or the newly empowered vulnerable person? And would a power-increasing rule foster individual responsibility and elevate vulnerable persons? Or would it signal a lack of protection from the state and encourage a culture of blaming those who suffer injury?


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.