메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 90, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 551-578

The unity of interpretation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77954340224     PISSN: 00068047     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (27)

References (73)
  • 2
    • 77954342788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming (Apr. 17, 2009 manuscript, on file with the Boston University Law Review).
    • RONALD DWORHN, JUSTICE FOR HEDGEHOGS (forthcoming 2010) (Apr. 17, 2009 manuscript, on file with the Boston University Law Review).
    • (2010) Justice For Hedgehogs
    • Dworhn, R.1
  • 3
    • 84896306930 scopus 로고
    • Hard cases
    • Ronald Dworkin, Hard Cases, 88 HARV. L. REV. 1057 (1975).
    • (1975) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 1057
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 5
    • 85081494736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In oral remarks at the Boston University conference, Dworkin seemed to express general assent to the account offered in the oral remarks that formed the basis for this Essay
    • In oral remarks at the Boston University conference, Dworkin seemed to express general assent to the account offered in the oral remarks that formed the basis for this Essay.
  • 7
    • 84921544036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 3, at
    • Dworkin, Hard Cases, supra note 3, at 1058-60.
    • Hard Cases , pp. 1058-1060
    • Dworkin1
  • 8
    • 85081525583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1059 (discussing "arguments of policy")
    • Id. at 1059 (discussing "arguments of policy").
  • 9
    • 85081507561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (discussing "arguments of principle").
    • Id. (discussing "arguments of principle").
  • 10
    • 85081519639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1060.
    • Id. at 1060.
  • 11
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the separation of law and morals
    • 593
    • H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593, 607 (1958).
    • (1958) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 607
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 12
    • 85081514522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 13
    • 12744266420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Method and principle in legal theory
    • 1757
    • See Stephen R. Perry, Method and Principle in Legal Theory, 111 YALE L.J. 1757, 1807 (2002)
    • (2002) Yale L.J. , vol.111 , pp. 1807
    • Perry, S.R.1
  • 15
    • 84930981279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 4, at 354 ("Hercules does not need one method for hard cases and another for easy ones."); see also id. at 266 ("[E]asy cases are, for law as integrity, only special cases of hard ones....").
    • See DWORHN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 4, at 354 ("Hercules does not need one method for hard cases and another for easy ones."); see also id. at 266 ("[E]asy cases are, for law as integrity, only special cases of hard ones....").
    • Law's Empire
    • Dworhn1
  • 16
    • 85081515289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My view of this relationship has been greatly influenced by the work of Mark Greenberg.
    • My view of this relationship has been greatly influenced by the work of Mark Greenberg.
  • 17
    • 80055030062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UCLA Sch. of Law Research Paper No. 0807, available at
    • See Mark Greenberg, The Standard Picture and Its Discontents (UCLA Sch. of Law Research Paper No. 08-07,2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract= 1103569.
    • (2008) The Standard Picture and Its Discontents
    • Greenberg, M.1
  • 18
    • 85081507709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Dworkin does, however, describe the theory of Law's Empire as involving two steps: First, there must be a "preinterpretive" stage in which the rules and standards taken to provide the tentative content of the practice are identified.... Second, there must be an interpretive stage at which the interpreter settles on some general justification for the main elements of the practice identified at the preinterpretive stage. DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 4, at 65-66. But this is not a two-step theory of interpretation; interpretation is stage two. If the same schema were applied to the theory in Hard Cases, there would be a three-step theory: (1) identify the object of interpretation; (2) identify the settled core (the easy issues); and (3) apply the method of fit and justification to the penumbra (the hard issues).
  • 19
    • 85081494542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is explicit in the passage quoted supra note 15. 17 By otherwise, I mean "in the absence of controlling legal rules" or "if the case were a hard case rather than an easy case" or "if the case were in the penumbra rather than the core of the relevant legal rule."
    • This is explicit in the passage quoted supra note 15. 17 By otherwise, I mean "in the absence of controlling legal rules" or "if the case were a hard case rather than an easy case" or "if the case were in the penumbra rather than the core of the relevant legal rule."
  • 20
    • 84930981279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 4, at
    • See, e.g., DWORHN, LAW'S EMPIRE, supra note 4, at 186-90.
    • Law's Empire , pp. 186-190
    • Dworhn1
  • 21
    • 85081496796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These remarks and questions about Dworkin's view in Law's Empire are not intended as objections; this assessment of the viability of the normative legal theory offered in Law's Empire is far outside the scope of this Essay. Rather, I aim to present a picture of the way in which Law's Empire was received in order to provide the context for the emergence of Dworkin's new view in Justice for Hedgehogs.
  • 23
    • 85081498962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORHN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 79).
    • DWORHN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 79).
  • 24
    • 85081498802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 25
    • 85081501065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 26
    • 85081525385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 79-80).
    • Id. (manuscript at 79-80).
  • 27
    • 85081496984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 83).
    • Id. (manuscript at 83).
  • 28
    • 85081524536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 84).
    • Id. (manuscript at 84).
  • 29
    • 85081516855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. 28 Id. (manuscript at 85).
    • Id. 28 Id. (manuscript at 85).
  • 30
    • 85081495380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 86).
    • Id. (manuscript at 86).
  • 32
    • 85081507942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 87).
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 87).
  • 33
    • 85081518801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 34
    • 85081525001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 35
    • 85081500262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 255).
    • Id. (manuscript at 255).
  • 36
    • 85081505186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 84).
    • See id. (manuscript at 84).
  • 37
    • 85081522657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 98).
    • Id. (manuscript at 98).
  • 38
    • 84968850937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at 4.
    • See Dworkin, Response, supra note 5, at 4.
    • Response
    • Dworkin1
  • 39
    • 85081503199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying note 27.
    • See supra text accompanying note 27.
  • 40
    • 85081492954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 84).
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 84).
  • 41
    • 85081510156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 42
  • 43
    • 85081494748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 85) (emphasis added).
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 85) (emphasis added).
  • 44
    • 85081521705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I searched the Journals and Law Reviews database, using search term "semantically available."
    • I searched the Journals and Law Reviews database, using search term "semantically available."
  • 45
    • 85081509939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fall (unpublished manuscript), available at I performed this Google search on January 24,2010.43
    • Ronald Dworkin, Interpretation, Morality, and Truth (Fall 2002) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://wwwl.Iaw.nyu.edu/clppt/ program2002/readings/dworkin/dworkin.rtf. I performed this Google search on January 24,2010.43
    • (2002) Interpretation, Morality, and Truth
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 46
    • 77954332042 scopus 로고
    • "Meaning" in the law of contracts
    • 939
    • See E. Allan Farnsworth, "Meaning" in the Law of Contracts, 76 YALE L.J. 939, 939 (1967).
    • (1967) Yale L.J. , vol.76 , pp. 939
    • Allan Farnsworth, E.1
  • 47
    • 85081517105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although this article by Farnsworth is the first theoretically sophisticated discussion in a contemporary law review, the distinction goes back at least as far as the nineteenth century.
    • Although this article by Farnsworth is the first theoretically sophisticated discussion in a contemporary law review, the distinction goes back at least as far as the nineteenth century.
  • 51
    • 77954326263 scopus 로고
    • Conditions in the law of contract
    • 739
    • Arthur L. Corbin, Conditions in the Law of Contract, 28 YALE L.J. 739, 740-41 (1919);
    • (1919) Yale L.J. , vol.28 , pp. 740-741
    • Corbin, A.L.1
  • 52
    • 0346286462 scopus 로고
    • The interpretation and construction of contracts
    • 833
    • Edwin W. Patterson, The Interpretation and Construction of Contracts, 64 COLUM. L. REV. 833, 833 (1964).
    • (1964) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.64 , pp. 833
    • Patterson, E.W.1
  • 53
    • 85081517530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To be absolutely clear, the words "interpretation" and "construction" are not always used this way. There is a long history of this usage in American common-law jurisprudence that embraces this distinction, but the distinction between interpretation and construction is a technical, legal and theoretical distinction. The senses that are stipulated in the definitions specified above are technical senses. In other contexts, these words are used as synonyms that refer to whole activity (both the discovery of linguistic meaning and the construction of legal doctrines). And both words have other senses as well - already identified for "interpretation," and obvious in the case of "construction" (that is, " construction" has a sense that refers to building).
  • 54
    • 85081496287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying note 42.
    • See supra text accompanying note 42.
  • 55
    • 84860461714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mar. 4, (unpublished manuscript on file with the Boston University Law Review).
    • See Lawrence B. Solum, The Interpretation-Construction Distinction 14 (Mar. 4,2010) (unpublished manuscript on file with the Boston University Law Review).
    • (2010) The Interpretation-Construction Distinction , pp. 14
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 56
    • 85081509182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.A.
    • See supra Part I.A.
  • 58
    • 0005161517 scopus 로고
    • The ambiguity rule and insurance law: Why insurance contracts should not be construed against the drafter
    • 171
    • Michael B. Rappaport, The Ambiguity Rule and Insurance Law: Why Insurance Contracts Should Not Be Construed Against the Drafter, 30 GA. L. REV. 171, 173 (1995);
    • (1995) Ga. L. Rev. , vol.30 , pp. 173
    • Rappaport, M.B.1
  • 59
    • 26844569795 scopus 로고
    • Confused notions and constitutional theory
    • 567
    • John T. Valauri, Confused Notions and Constitutional Theory, 12 N. KY. L. REV. 567,570-71 (1985).
    • (1985) N. Ky. L. Rev. , vol.12 , pp. 570-571
    • Valauri, J.T.1
  • 61
    • 85081507152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Endicott identifies two marks of vagueness: (1) borderline cases; and (2) a tolerance principle, which states that "a tiny change in an object in a respect relevant to the application of the expression cannot make the difference between the expression's applying and not applying." Id. at 33.
    • Endicott identifies two marks of vagueness: (1) borderline cases; and (2) a tolerance principle, which states that "a tiny change in an object in a respect relevant to the application of the expression cannot make the difference between the expression's applying and not applying." Id. at 33.
  • 62
    • 85081504048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By "intended or public meaning," I mean to elide the question whether the meaning of a legal text is a function of the author's intentions or the conventional semantic meanings of the words and phrases and the patterns of usage that constitute the rules of grammar and syntax for a given linguistic community. 34 In this Essay, I will not investigate the possibility that a Dworkinian theory of construction might authorize legal content that is inconsistent with semantic content. This is an important question, but its resolution is not required for the purposes of investigating the main implications of the interpretation-construction distinction for Dworkin's view.
  • 63
    • 85081508121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.A.
    • See supra Part I.A.
  • 64
    • 85081500929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For the purposes of this simplified version of alternative Dworkin's theory, I am eliding a number of complexities. For example, the object of "fit" might be broader than the semantic content of the authoritative legal texts; it might include the actions and practices of legal actors and institutions. These complications are simply set aside for the purposes of this Essay. 37 DWORHN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 252).
  • 65
    • 85081505743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 253).
    • Id. (manuscript at 253).
  • 66
    • 85081497646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 17,97-100).
    • Id. (manuscript at 17,97-100).
  • 67
    • 85081516543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 67-68).
    • Id. (manuscript at 67-68).
  • 68
    • 85081502560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is only one reference to "constructivism" in Justice for Hedgehogs, see DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 171), and in oral remarks at the conference, Dworkin disavowed understanding of "constructivism" as a theory. See Dworkin, Response, supra note 5, at 2. On constructivism
    • There is only one reference to "constructivism" in Justice for Hedgehogs, see DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 171), and in oral remarks at the conference, Dworkin disavowed understanding of "constructivism" as a theory. See Dworkin, Response, supra note 5, at 2. On constructivism,
  • 69
    • 24144478785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constructivism in rawls and kant
    • Samuel Freeman ed.
    • see generally Onora O'Neill, Constructivism in Rawls and Kant, in THE CAMBRIDGE COMPANION TO RAWLS 347 (Samuel Freeman ed., 2003).
    • (2003) The Cambridge Companion To Rawls , pp. 347
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 70
    • 85081505314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • O'Neill, supra note 61, at 348.
    • O'Neill, supra note 61, at 348.
  • 71
    • 85081499964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. 64 DWORHN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 17).
    • Id. 64 DWORHN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 17).
  • 72
    • 85081503151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 75).
    • Id. (manuscript at 75).
  • 73
    • 85081520937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 10).
    • Id. (manuscript at 10).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.