-
3
-
-
77954345756
-
-
("'Without the Sunni parties there will be no consensus goverament[,] ... without consensus government there will be no unity, there will be no peace.'" (quoting Iraqi President Jalai Talabani)).
-
("'Without the Sunni parties there will be no consensus goverament[,] ... without consensus government there will be no unity, there will be no peace.'" (quoting Iraqi President Jalai Talabani)).
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
77954332456
-
Promising troops where they aren't really wanted
-
Jan. 11
-
Sabrina Tavernise & John F. Bums, Promising Troops Where They Aren't Really Wanted, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 11,2007, at A20.
-
(2007)
N.Y. Times
-
-
Tavernise, S.1
Bums, J.F.2
-
5
-
-
77954346792
-
-
Apr. 17, manuscript at on file with the Boston University Law Review.
-
RONALD DWORHN, JUSTICE FOR HEDGEHOGS (forthcoming 2010) (Apr. 17, 2009 manuscript at 218-19, on file with the Boston University Law Review).
-
(2009)
Justice For Hedgehogs (Forthcoming 2010)
, pp. 218-219
-
-
Dworhn, R.1
-
6
-
-
77954335377
-
-
See id. (manuscript at 242).
-
See id. (manuscript at 242).
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
77954325123
-
-
See id. at x-xi.
-
See id. at x-xi.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
77954342452
-
-
See id. at 138-40 ("[T]here is no general reason to reject a system of representation simply because it does not adhere to the proportionality principle.").
-
See id. at 138-40 ("[T]here is no general reason to reject a system of representation simply because it does not adhere to the proportionality principle.").
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
77954337157
-
-
note
-
Professor Dworkin rejects indeterminacy as the default position and would require a positive justification for a claim of indeterminacy rather than uncertainty, see DWORHN, supra note 3 (manuscript at 58-63), but, in some cases, abstract questions of democratic institutional design may be objectively indeterminate. This is not to say that one cannot make a sound case for particular reforms when one combines these principles with greater information about particular contexts and historical patterns and pathologies.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
0004015503
-
-
Democracy is founded on the premise of political equality: individuals equally hold rights, including an equal right to participate in making majority decisions. This right to participate, Waldron maintains, is the "right of rights." Id. at 232.
-
JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT 299 (1999). Democracy is founded on the premise of political equality: individuals equally hold rights, including an equal right to participate in making majority decisions. This right to participate, Waldron maintains, is the "right of rights." Id. at 232.
-
(1999)
Law And Disagreement
, pp. 299
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
12
-
-
77954339578
-
-
These paragraphs draw on a draft paper I coauthored with Christopher L. Karpowitz and Evan Oxman.
-
These paragraphs draw on a draft paper I coauthored with Christopher L. Karpowitz and Evan Oxman.
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
77954336183
-
-
Mar. 7, (unpublished manuscript, on file with the Boston University Law Review).
-
See generally Stephen Macedo, Christopher L. Karpowitz & Evan Oxman, Two Conceptions of Democracy (Mar. 7, 2006) (unpublished manuscript, on file with the Boston University Law Review).
-
(2006)
Two Conceptions of Democracy
-
-
Macedo, S.1
Karpowitz, C.L.2
Oxman, E.3
-
14
-
-
77954339185
-
-
DWORKIN, supra note 3 (manuscript at 242-43).
-
DWORKIN, supra note 3 (manuscript at 242-43).
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
77954326418
-
-
WALDRON, supra note 9, at 283.
-
WALDRON, supra note 9, at 283.
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
77954332785
-
-
Id. at 298.
-
Id. at 298.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
77954325531
-
-
Id. at 295.
-
Id. at 295.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
77954378776
-
-
(Harvard Law Sch. Pub. Law & Legal Theory Working Paper Series, Paper No. 09-20, 2009), available at
-
See id. at 289-312; Mark Tushnet, Against Judicial Review 2-3 (Harvard Law Sch. Pub. Law & Legal Theory Working Paper Series, Paper No. 09-20, 2009), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract-1368857
-
Against Judicial Review
, pp. 2-3
-
-
Tushnet, M.1
-
19
-
-
77954334663
-
-
(arguing that "mechanisms of displacement must be relatively easy" so that the people can "replac[e] the legislators who made choices of which [they] disapprove)
-
(arguing that "mechanisms of displacement must be relatively easy" so that the people can "replac[e] the legislators who made choices of which [they] disapprove);
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0003753338
-
-
(discussing the importance of ensuring non permanent majority factions, especially in a system without judicial review).
-
see also MARK TUSHNET, TAKING THE CONSTITUTION AWAY FROM THE COURTS 96-100 (2000) (discussing the importance of ensuring non permanent majority factions, especially in a system without judicial review).
-
(2000)
Taking The Constitution Away From The Courts
, pp. 96-100
-
-
Tushnet, M.1
-
21
-
-
77954334115
-
-
WALDRON, supra note 9, at 299.
-
WALDRON, supra note 9, at 299.
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
77954329640
-
-
Id. As with utilitarianism, there is another aggregative standard for decision: everyone counts for one, nobody counts for more than one. BEITZ, supra note 5, at 55-67.
-
Id. As with utilitarianism, there is another aggregative standard for decision: everyone counts for one, nobody counts for more than one. BEITZ, supra note 5, at 55-67.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
77954327587
-
-
WALDRON, supra note 9, at 286-87.
-
WALDRON, supra note 9, at 286-87.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
0002101302
-
Accountability and authority: Toward a theory of political accountability
-
131, Adam Przeworski et al. eds., (arguing that "[e]lectoral punishment... is a fairly blunt instrument," and that accountability through greater transparency can be much more effective).
-
See John Ferejohn, Accountability and Authority: Toward a Theory of Political Accountability, in DEMOCRACY, ACCOUNTABILITY, AND REPRESENTATION 131, 131-53 (Adam Przeworski et al. eds., 1999) (arguing that "[e]lectoral punishment... is a fairly blunt instrument," and that accountability through greater transparency can be much more effective).
-
(1999)
Democracy, Accountability, And Representation
, pp. 131-153
-
-
Ferejohn, J.1
-
26
-
-
77954326751
-
-
For example, Congress can enact legislation that limits the decision's impact and lower courts can narrowly interpret the holding or call the Supreme Court's reasoning dicta.
-
For example, Congress can enact legislation that limits the decision's impact and lower courts can narrowly interpret the holding or call the Supreme Court's reasoning dicta.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
77954318836
-
-
note
-
See discussion infra notes 45, 46 and accompanying text (discussing how limited judicial review in countries such as the United Kingdom and New Zealand has resulted in a higher caliber of debate and discussion within the political branches). Similarly, Dworkin does not argue that the United States's institutional design is optimal.
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
77954335872
-
-
See supra notes 7-8 and accompanying text.
-
See supra notes 7-8 and accompanying text.
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
33645815488
-
77ie core of the case against judicial review
-
1346, (citing both abortion and affirmative action as examples of rights-based disagreements that "define major choices that any modern society must face").
-
Jeremy Waldron, 77ie Core of the Case Against Judicial Review, 115 YALE LJ. 1346, 1366-67 (2006) (citing both abortion and affirmative action as examples of rights-based disagreements that "define major choices that any modern society must face").
-
(2006)
Yale Lj.
, vol.115
, pp. 1366-1367
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
30
-
-
77954325530
-
-
note
-
See id. at 1361-62 ("I assume that the [democratic] institutions, procedures, and practices of legislation are kept under constant review from this perspective, so that if there are perceived inequities of representation that derogate seriously from the ideal of political equality, it is understood among all the members of the society that this is an appropriate criticism to make and that, if need be, the legislature and the electoral system should be changed to remedy it").
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
77954317101
-
-
Id. at 1361 & n.47.
-
Id. at 1361 & n.47.
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
77954322106
-
-
Id. at 1369-95 (arguing that because neither majoritarian nor non-majoritarian processes clearly produce better outcomes, majoritarian processes should be preferred because they are procedurally superior)
-
Id. at 1369-95 (arguing that because neither majoritarian nor non-majoritarian processes clearly produce better outcomes, majoritarian processes should be preferred because they are procedurally superior);
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
77955241228
-
Compared to what? Judicial activism and the New Zealand parliament
-
441
-
Jeremy Waldron, Compared to What? Judicial Activism and the New Zealand Parliament, 2005 N.Z. L.J. 441,442-45.
-
(2005)
N.Z. L.J.
, pp. 442-445
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
34
-
-
77954325875
-
-
Add a third alternative and the possibility of intransitive preferences and the familiar Arrow-type cycling problems (varying the order in which several pair-wise alternatives come up for a vote) make it impossible to say that any particular results are preferred by a majority.
-
Add a third alternative and the possibility of intransitive preferences and the familiar Arrow-type cycling problems (varying the order in which several pair-wise alternatives come up for a vote) make it impossible to say that any particular results are preferred by a majority.
-
-
-
-
35
-
-
0003578882
-
-
("The people are a sovereign whose vocabulary is limited to two words, 'Yes' and 'No.'")
-
See E.E. SCHATTSCHNEIDER, PARTY GOVERNMENT 52 (1942) ("The people are a sovereign whose vocabulary is limited to two words, 'Yes' and 'No.'");
-
(1942)
Party Government
, pp. 52
-
-
Schattschneider, E.E.1
-
37
-
-
77954332195
-
-
[hereinafter SCHATTSCHNEIDER, SEMISOVEREIGN] (describing how the two-party system "organizefs the electorate by reducing their alternatives to the extreme limit of simplification").
-
[hereinafter SCHATTSCHNEIDER, SEMISOVEREIGN] (describing how the two-party system "organizefs] the electorate by reducing their alternatives to the extreme limit of simplification").
-
-
-
-
39
-
-
77954321773
-
-
see also SCHATTSCHNEIDER, SEMISOVEREIGN, supra note 29, at 135-36.
-
see also SCHATTSCHNEIDER, SEMISOVEREIGN, supra note 29, at 135-36.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
77954338494
-
-
For example, administrative agencies are subject to robust due process requirements codified in administrative law including publication of proposed rales, opportunities for public comment, and judicial review of agency decisions.
-
For example, administrative agencies are subject to robust due process requirements codified in administrative law including publication of proposed rales, opportunities for public comment, and judicial review of agency decisions.
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
1342327354
-
Arguing for majority rule
-
41,43-48
-
See Mathias Risse, Arguing for Majority Rule, 12 J. POL. PHIL. 41,43-48,57-62 (2004)
-
(2004)
J. Pol. Phil.
, vol.12
, pp. 57-62
-
-
Risse, M.1
-
44
-
-
77954322878
-
-
(critiquing arguments for majority rule and describing various alternate voting procedures); see also BEITZ, supra note 5, at 58-67 (arguing that simple majority rule does not completely satisfy social choice theory).
-
(critiquing arguments for majority rule and describing various alternate voting procedures); see also BEITZ, supra note 5, at 58-67 (arguing that simple majority rule does not completely satisfy social choice theory).
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
77954327032
-
-
note
-
See BEITZ, supra note 5, at 90 ("[F]air procedures ought not to allow the more or less permanent exclusion of an entrenched minority from effective participation in politics."). As Douglas Rae has argued, if our collective choice about decision rules is guided by the aim of assuring each person that the system maximizes the chances of getting what he wants and not getting what he does not want, majority rule wins out only under extremely restrictive conditions - strictly pair-wise alternatives, strictly individualistic preferences (no factions or coalitions), no linkages across decisions, no accounting for intensity of preferences, no asymmetry of gains and losses (no preference for avoiding bads over achieving goods).
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
84971116267
-
Decision-rules and individual values in constitutional choice
-
40
-
See Douglas W. Rae, Decision-Rules and Individual Values in Constitutional Choice, 63 AM. POL. Sei. REV. 40, 40-63 (1969)
-
(1969)
Am. Pol. Sei. Rev.
, vol.63
, pp. 40-63
-
-
Rae, D.W.1
-
47
-
-
77954320272
-
-
(discussing the difficulties that permanent minority factions pose to majority rale). If we depart from these conditions (by allowing for the existence of factions, by including non-individualistic preferences, etc.), majority rale loses its appeal. See id.
-
(discussing the difficulties that permanent minority factions pose to majority rale). If we depart from these conditions (by allowing for the existence of factions, by including non-individualistic preferences, etc.), majority rale loses its appeal. See id.
-
-
-
-
50
-
-
77954347237
-
-
(arguing that the real issue is not that the minorities are "discrete and insular," rather that status is the result of an underlying prejudice that is harmful to a democratic system). Note here that the objection to a simple aggregation approach refers to the underlying strategy of justification.
-
(arguing that the real issue is not that the minorities are "discrete and insular," rather that status is the result of an underlying prejudice that is harmful to a democratic system). Note here that the objection to a simple aggregation approach refers to the underlying strategy of justification.
-
-
-
-
51
-
-
77954324069
-
The plight of the poor in the midst of plenty
-
July 15
-
Waldron argues this point in his terrific review of John Rawls's Collected Papers. See generally Jeremy Waldron, The Plight of the Poor in the Midst of Plenty, LONDON REV. BOOKS, July 15,1999, at 3-6
-
(1999)
London Rev. Books
, pp. 3-6
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
52
-
-
0003946754
-
-
Samuel Freeman ed.
-
(reviewing JOHN RAWLS, COLLECTED PAPERS (Samuel Freeman ed., 1999)).
-
(1999)
Collected Papers
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
53
-
-
77954347405
-
-
For another account see, for example, BEITZ, supra note 5, at 23 ("[T]he terms of democratic participation are fair when they are reasonably acceptable from each citizen's point of view.").
-
For another account see, for example, BEITZ, supra note 5, at 23 ("[T]he terms of democratic participation are fair when they are reasonably acceptable from each citizen's point of view.").
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
77954341462
-
-
DWORKIN, supra note 3 (manuscript at 246).
-
DWORKIN, supra note 3 (manuscript at 246).
-
-
-
-
55
-
-
77954317242
-
-
Id. (manuscript at 250).
-
Id. (manuscript at 250).
-
-
-
-
56
-
-
77954327389
-
-
Id. (manuscript at 249-51).
-
Id. (manuscript at 249-51).
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
77954331557
-
-
See id. at 415-19 ("Tjhose who rely on the courts absent significant public and political support will fail to achieve meaningful social change, and may set their cause back.")
-
See id. at 415-19 ("[Tjhose who rely on the courts absent significant public and political support will fail to achieve meaningful social change, and may set their cause back.");
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
21344481606
-
Racial change, and the civil rights movement
-
7,71
-
Michael J. Klarman, Brown, Racial Change, and the Civil Rights Movement, 80 VA. L. REV. 7,71, 85 (1994)
-
(1994)
Va. L. Rev.
, vol.80
, pp. 85
-
-
Klarman Brown, M.J.1
-
60
-
-
77954324958
-
-
arguing that "a transformation in American race relations was ... a virtual inevitability" and that judicial action through Brown
-
(arguing that "a transformation in American race relations was ... a virtual inevitability" and that judicial action through Brown "catalyz[ed] southern resistance to racial change").
-
Catalyz[ed] southern resistance to racial change
-
-
-
61
-
-
34548620028
-
Roe Rage: Democratic constitutionalism and backlash
-
(arguing that backlash is a normal part of "democratic constitutionalism" because it permits the people to have an interpretive voice in constitutional law).
-
See generally Robert Post & Reva Siegel, Roe Rage: Democratic Constitutionalism and Backlash, 42 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 373 (2007) (arguing that backlash is a normal part of "democratic constitutionalism" because it permits the people to have an interpretive voice in constitutional law).
-
(2007)
Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev.
, vol.42
, pp. 373
-
-
Post, R.1
Siegel, R.2
-
63
-
-
62649129083
-
Beyond backlash: Assessing the impact of judicial decisions on LGBT rights
-
passim
-
Thomas M. Keck, Beyond Backlash: Assessing the Impact of Judicial Decisions on LGBT Rights, 43 LAW & Soc'Y REV. 151 passim (2009)
-
(2009)
Law & Soc'y Rev.
, vol.43
, pp. 151
-
-
Keck, T.M.1
-
64
-
-
77954337935
-
-
[hereinafter Keck, Beyond Backlash] (observing how same-sex marriage law suits resulted in a backlash against gay rights, but also laid the groundwork for future successful litigation)
-
[hereinafter Keck, Beyond Backlash] (observing how same-sex marriage law suits resulted in a backlash against gay rights, but also laid the groundwork for future successful litigation);
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
35348867602
-
Party, policy, or duty: Why does the supreme court invalidate federal statutes?
-
321
-
cf. Thomas M. Keck, Party, Policy, or Duty: Why Does the Supreme Court Invalidate Federal Statutes?, 101 AM. POL. Sci. REV. 321, 322-23 (2007)
-
(2007)
Am. Pol. Sci. Rev.
, vol.101
, pp. 322-323
-
-
Keck, T.M.1
-
66
-
-
77954339727
-
-
(examining how often and under what circumstances "partisan elites regularly attempt to use the Court to promote their own policy preferences and political fortunes").
-
(examining how often and under what circumstances "partisan elites regularly attempt to use the Court to promote their own policy preferences and political fortunes").
-
-
-
-
67
-
-
77954341780
-
-
supra note 42, at
-
See Keck, Beyond Backlash, supra note 42, at 172.
-
Beyond Backlash
, pp. 172
-
-
Keck1
-
68
-
-
18444393325
-
-
539 U.S. 558, (holding a Texas sodomy law to be a violation of substantive due process).
-
See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 578-79 (2003) (holding a Texas sodomy law to be a violation of substantive due process).
-
(2003)
Lawrence V. Texas
, pp. 578-579
-
-
-
70
-
-
77954326856
-
-
note
-
WALDRON, supra note 9, at 289-94 (discussing how "limited review" may have improved the quality of political dialogue on issues such as abortion and gay rights in the United Kingdom and New Zealand); see also TUSHNET, supra note 45 at 157 ("[T]he performance of legislators and executive officials [in systems with weak judicial review] in interpreting the constitution is not . . . dramatically different from the performance of judges.").
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
77954344301
-
-
DWORKIN, supra note 3 (manuscript at 251).
-
DWORKIN, supra note 3 (manuscript at 251).
-
-
-
-
72
-
-
77954332928
-
-
See id. (manuscript at 219-20) ("We do better when we recognize that the familiar concepts of political virtue are interpretive concepts.").
-
See id. (manuscript at 219-20) ("We do better when we recognize that the familiar concepts of political virtue are interpretive concepts.").
-
-
-
-
73
-
-
33750523806
-
A right to judicial review
-
991, (arguing that judicial review protects a moral right to a hearing rather than merely a legal "watch-dog" right).
-
See Yuval Eylon & Alon Harel, A Right to Judicial Review, 92 VA. L. REV. 991, 99799 (2006) (arguing that judicial review protects a moral right to a hearing rather than merely a legal "watch-dog" right).
-
(2006)
Va. L. Rev.
, vol.92
, pp. 99799
-
-
Eylon, Y.1
Harel, A.2
-
75
-
-
77954337391
-
-
(arguing that our judicial system provides democratic opportunities for "the development and testing of the law through experimentation by citizens and through the adversarial process").
-
(arguing that our judicial system provides democratic opportunities for "the development and testing of the law through experimentation by citizens and through the adversarial process").
-
-
-
-
76
-
-
77954325711
-
-
For two good discussions responding to Waldron, which I found helpful in writing this paper
-
For two good discussions responding to Waldron, which I found helpful in writing this paper,
-
-
-
-
77
-
-
69949115790
-
Is judicial review undemocratic?
-
Summer
-
see Annabelle Lever, Is Judicial Review Undemocratic?, PUB. L., Summer 2007, at 280,
-
(2007)
Pub. L.
, pp. 280
-
-
Lever, A.1
-
78
-
-
77954334662
-
-
which argues that Waldron has underestimated "the extent to which democratic forms of politics can be judicial," and
-
which argues that Waldron has underestimated "the extent to which democratic forms of politics can be judicial," and
-
-
-
-
79
-
-
69949172264
-
Democracy and judicial review: Are they really incompatible?
-
Annabelle Lever, Democracy and Judicial Review: Are They Really Incompatible?, 7 PERSP. ON POL. 805 (2009),
-
(2009)
Persp. On Pol.
, vol.7
, pp. 805
-
-
Lever, A.1
-
80
-
-
77954323781
-
-
which illustrates a democratic justification for judicial review. For a good discussion of the philosophical and constitutional underpinnings of judicial review and its implications on democracy and equality
-
which illustrates a democratic justification for judicial review. For a good discussion of the philosophical and constitutional underpinnings of judicial review and its implications on democracy and equality,
-
-
-
|