메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 90, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 819-837

Rights, harms, and duties: A response to justice for hedgehogs

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77954322561     PISSN: 00068047     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (8)

References (91)
  • 1
    • 77954335717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RONALD DWORKIN, JUSTICE FOR HEDGEHOGS (forthcoming 2040) (Apr. 17, 2009 manuscript at 208-09, on file with the Boston University Law Review). Dworkin explains: Sometimes ... people use the idea of a political right in a stronger... way: to declare that some interests people have are so important that these interests must be protected even from policies that would indeed make people as a whole better off. We might say, capturing that idea, that political rights are trumps over otherwise adequate justifications for political action... This chapter studies political rights understood as tramps.
    • See RONALD DWORKIN, JUSTICE FOR HEDGEHOGS (forthcoming 2040) (Apr. 17, 2009 manuscript at 208-09, on file with the Boston University Law Review). Dworkin explains: Sometimes ... people use the idea of a political right in a stronger... way: to declare that some interests people have are so important that these interests must be protected even from policies that would indeed make people as a whole better off. We might say, capturing that idea, that political rights are trumps over otherwise adequate justifications for political action... This chapter studies political rights understood as tramps.
  • 2
    • 77954325878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 3
    • 77954320384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 209).
    • See id. (manuscript at 209).
  • 4
    • 77954327765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 208) (When we come to political morality, rights plainly provide a better focus than duties because their location is more precise: individuals have political rights, and some of those rights, at least, are matched only by collective duties of community as a whole rather than of particular individuals.).
    • See id. (manuscript at 208) ("When we come to political morality, rights plainly provide a better focus than duties because their location is more precise: individuals have political rights, and some of those rights, at least, are matched only by collective duties of community as a whole rather than of particular individuals.").
  • 5
    • 77954336845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 232, 235-37) (Government must not abridge total freedom when its putative justification relies on some collective decision about what makes a life good or well-lived. We must each make that decision for himself:[sic] that is the core of our ethical responsibility.).
    • See id. (manuscript at 232, 235-37) ("Government must not abridge total freedom when its putative justification relies on some collective decision about what makes a life good or well-lived. We must each make that decision for himself:[sic] that is the core of our ethical responsibility.").
  • 6
    • 77954344466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 230-35).
    • See id. (manuscript at 230-35).
  • 7
    • 77954317990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 221-27).
    • See id. (manuscript at 221-27).
  • 8
    • 77954341783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 238-48).
    • See id. (manuscript at 238-48).
  • 9
    • 77954329936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 226-27).
    • See id. (manuscript at 226-27).
  • 10
    • 77954347413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 203-05).
    • See id. (manuscript at 203-05).
  • 11
    • 77954330129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 210).
    • Id. (manuscript at 210).
  • 12
    • 77954339730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 209).
    • Id. (manuscript at 209).
  • 14
    • 77954347414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 200, 218-22.
    • See id. at 200, 218-22.
  • 15
    • 77954323323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 209).
    • DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 209).
  • 16
    • 77954344308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two examples include: We say that the government should negotiate trade treaties because these are good for America's trade balance, or that government should subsidize farmers because that would improve the economy as a whole, or that government should abolish capital punishment because its use demeans our society. Many such claims are informal versions of a utilitarian trade-off argument. Id. The timid lady on the streets of Chicago is not entitled to just the degree of quiet that now obtains, nor is she entitled to have boys drafted to fight in wars she approves. These are laws - perhaps desirable laws - that provide for advantages for her, but the justification for these laws, if they can be justified at all, is the common desire of a large majority, nor her personal right
    • Two examples include: We say that the government should negotiate trade treaties because these are good for America's trade balance, or that government should subsidize farmers because that would improve the economy as a whole, or that government should abolish capital punishment because its use demeans our society. Many such claims are informal versions of a utilitarian trade-off argument. Id. The timid lady on the streets of Chicago is not entitled to just the degree of quiet that now obtains, nor is she entitled to have boys drafted to fight in wars she approves. These are laws - perhaps desirable laws - that provide for advantages for her, but the justification for these laws, if they can be justified at all, is the common desire of a large majority, nor her personal right
  • 17
    • 77954320538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 12, at 195.
    • DWORKIN, supra note 12, at 195.
  • 18
    • 77954317880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 209).
    • See DWORIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 209).
  • 19
    • 9744266789 scopus 로고
    • 413 U.S. 49, 54 (deciding films defined as obscene under Georgia obscenity law are not protected by First Amendment)
    • See Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S. 49, 54 (1973) (deciding films defined as "obscene" under Georgia obscenity law are not protected by First Amendment);
    • (1973) Paris Adult Theatre i V. Slaton
  • 20
    • 0038695288 scopus 로고
    • 413 U.S. 15, 23 (upholding California's obscenity law because distribution of obscene materials not protected under First Amendment)
    • Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15, 23 (1973) (upholding California's obscenity law because distribution of obscene materials not protected under First Amendment);
    • (1973) Miller V. California
  • 21
    • 77954320109 scopus 로고
    • 771 F.2d 323, 324 7th Cir. (concluding Indiana's attempt to provide a civil rights remedy for injuries caused by pornography is different from "obscenity," which Supreme Court has held not protected under First Amendment and therefore is unconstitutional).
    • Am. Booksellers Ass'n, Inc. v. Hudnut 771 F.2d 323, 324 (7th Cir. 1985) (concluding Indiana's attempt to provide a civil rights remedy for injuries caused by pornography is different from "obscenity," which Supreme Court has held not protected under First Amendment and therefore is unconstitutional).
    • (1985) Am. Booksellers Ass'n, Inc. V. Hudnut
  • 22
    • 72749122817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 128 S. Ct 2783,2821-22 (invalidating D.C. gun control law as violation of Second Amendment)
    • See District of Columbia v. Heller, 128 S. Ct 2783,2821-22 (2008) (invalidating D.C. gun control law as violation of Second Amendment);
    • (2008) District of Columbia V. Heller
  • 23
    • 77954345536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 567 F.3d 856, 858-60 7th Cir. cert, granted sub nom.
    • NRA v. City of Chicago, 567 F.3d 856, 858-60 (7th Cir. 2009), cert, granted sub nom.
    • (2009) NRA V. City of Chicago
  • 24
    • 77954331385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 130 S. Ct. 48 Sept. 30, (indicating that the Second Amendment is not incorporated against the states).
    • McDonald v. City of Chicago, 130 S. Ct. 48 (Sept. 30, 2009) (indicating that the Second Amendment is not incorporated against the states).
    • (2009) McDonald V. City of Chicago
  • 25
    • 67649435546 scopus 로고
    • 461 U.S. 352, 353 (declaring California loitering statute unconstitutionally vague)
    • See, e.g., Kolender v. Lawson, 461 U.S. 352, 353 (1983) (declaring California loitering statute unconstitutionally vague);
    • (1983) Kolender V. Lawson
  • 26
    • 77954319172 scopus 로고
    • 999 F.2d 699, 705 2d Cir. (finding New York loitering statute unconstitutionally vague).
    • Loper v. N.Y. City Police Dep't 999 F.2d 699, 705 (2d Cir. 1993) (finding New York loitering statute unconstitutionally vague).
    • (1993) Loper V. N.Y. City Police Dep't
  • 27
    • 18444393325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 539 U.S. 558, 578 (invalidating Texas law criminalizing homosexual sodomy).
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 578 (2003) (invalidating Texas law criminalizing homosexual sodomy).
    • (2003) Lawrence V. Texas
  • 28
    • 77952270763 scopus 로고
    • 508 U.S. 520, 534 (ruling that Hialeah's ordinance regarding animal sacrifice was unconstitutional for targeting Santeria religion).
    • See Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520, 534 (1993) (ruling that Hialeah's ordinance regarding animal sacrifice was unconstitutional for targeting Santeria religion).
    • (1993) Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. V. City of Hialeah
  • 30
    • 0011298491 scopus 로고
    • (invalidating most but not all of Pennsylvania abortion statute at issue); 410 U.S. 113, 154 (invalidating Texas abortion law as violation of right to privacy).
    • (invalidating most but not all of Pennsylvania abortion statute at issue); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 154 (1973) (invalidating Texas abortion law as violation of right to privacy).
    • (1973) Roe V. Wade
  • 32
    • 44949088427 scopus 로고
    • 354 U.S. 298, 334
    • See, e.g., Yates v. United States, 354 U.S. 298, 334 (1957).
    • (1957) Yates V. United States
  • 33
    • 77950396126 scopus 로고
    • 494 U.S. 872, 878-79 (upholding Oregon's denial of compensation to workers fired for using peyote in a religious ceremony, in face of First Amendment challenge).
    • See Employment Div. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 878-79 (1990) (upholding Oregon's denial of compensation to workers fired for using peyote in a religious ceremony, in face of First Amendment challenge).
    • (1990) Employment Div. V. Smith
  • 34
    • 33947682096 scopus 로고
    • 381 U.S. 479, 485 (invalidating Connecticut's ban on contraception because it violated the "right to marital privacy").
    • See Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 485 (1965) (invalidating Connecticut's ban on contraception because it violated the "right to marital privacy").
    • (1965) Griswold V. Connecticut
  • 36
    • 0012043543 scopus 로고
    • 198 U.S. 45, 6264 (invalidating N.Y. LAB. LAW § 110 (McKinney 1897), which limited labor hours for bakers).
    • See Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45, 62-64 (1905) (invalidating N.Y. LAB. LAW § 110 (McKinney 1897), which limited labor hours for bakers).
    • (1905) Lochner V. New York
  • 37
    • 77954322739 scopus 로고
    • 260 U.S. 393, 414-15 (establishing the doctrine of "regulatory taking," expanding the power of the Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment).
    • See Pa. Coal v. Mahon, 260 U.S. 393, 414-15 (1922) (establishing the doctrine of "regulatory taking," expanding the power of the Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment).
    • (1922) Pa. Coal V. Mahon
  • 38
    • 77954326087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • N.Y. Times, 376 U.S. at 272-73 ("Injury to official reputation affords no more warrant for repressing speech that would otherwise be free than does factual error.")
    • See, e.g., N.Y. Times, 376 U.S. at 272-73 ("Injury to official reputation affords no more warrant for repressing speech that would otherwise be free than does factual error.");
  • 39
    • 77954317991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mahon, 260 U.S. at 415-16 ("The general rule at least is, that while property may be regulated to a certain extent, if regulation goes too far it will be recognized as a taking.").
    • Mahon, 260 U.S. at 415-16 ("The general rule at least is, that while property may be regulated to a certain extent, if regulation goes too far it will be recognized as a taking.").
  • 40
    • 0346036755 scopus 로고
    • Rights
    • (discussing how the "revolutionary . . . natural rights philosophy of the Declaration of Independence" transformed into a "conservative pro-property doctrine" that legitimated slavery)
    • See Morton J. Horowitz, Rights, 23 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 393, 400 (1988) (discussing how the "revolutionary . . . natural rights philosophy of the Declaration of Independence" transformed into a "conservative pro-property doctrine" that legitimated slavery);
    • (1988) HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. , vol.23 , Issue.393 , pp. 400
    • Horowitz, M.J.1
  • 41
    • 34447536569 scopus 로고
    • An essay on rights
    • Mark Tushnet, An Essay on Rights, 62 TEX. L. REV. 1363, 1386-88 (1984).
    • (1984) TEX. L. REV. , vol.62 , Issue.1363 , pp. 1386-1388
    • Tushnet, M.1
  • 42
    • 77954333954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sotomayor Hearings: The Complete Transcript - Part 2, L.A. TIMES, July 14, 2009, http://latimesblogs.latimes.com/washington/2009/07/sotomayor-hearings- complete-transcript-part-two.html (reporting Senator Hatch's questions to Justice Sotomayor regarding her views on gun rights).
    • Sotomayor Hearings: The Complete Transcript - Part 2, L.A. TIMES, July 14, 2009, http://latimesblogs.latimes.com/washington/2009/07/sotomayor-hearings- complete-transcript-part-two.html (reporting Senator Hatch's questions to Justice Sotomayor regarding her views on gun rights).
  • 43
    • 77954334117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • N.Y. Times, 376 U.S at 271.
    • N.Y. Times, 376 U.S at 271.
  • 44
    • 33947682096 scopus 로고
    • 381 U.S. 479,485-86 (recognizing a "right to marital privacy" that covers intimate relations).
    • Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479,485-86 (1965) (recognizing a "right to marital privacy" that covers intimate relations).
    • (1965) Griswold V. Connecticut
  • 45
    • 72649084972 scopus 로고
    • 405 U.S. 438, 453-54 (finding a Massachusetts statute that permitted physicians to provide contraceptives to married couples but not unmarried couples violates the equal protections clause).
    • Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 453-54 (1972) (finding a Massachusetts statute that permitted physicians to provide contraceptives to married couples but not unmarried couples violates the equal protections clause).
    • (1972) Eisenstadt V. Baird
  • 46
    • 0011298491 scopus 로고
    • 410 U.S. 113, 154-55 (holding that "the right of personal privacy includes the abortion decision").
    • Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 154-55 (1973) (holding that "the right of personal privacy includes the abortion decision").
    • (1973) Roe V. Wade
  • 47
    • 18444393325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 539 U.S. 558, 578 (reasoning that mutually consenting adults "are entitled to respect for their private lives").
    • Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 578 (2003) (reasoning that mutually consenting adults "are entitled to respect for their private lives").
    • (2003) Lawrence V. Texas
  • 48
    • 77950496257 scopus 로고
    • 395 U.S. 444, 447
    • See Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444, 447 (1969);
    • (1969) Brandenburg V. Ohio
  • 49
    • 44949263686 scopus 로고
    • 274 U.S. 357,377-78 (Brandeis, J., concurring)
    • Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357,377-78 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring);
    • (1927) Whitney V. California
  • 50
    • 0012554974 scopus 로고
    • 250 U.S. 616, 63031 (Holmes, J., dissenting).
    • Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 63031 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting).
    • (1919) Abrams V. United States
  • 52
    • 77951169068 scopus 로고
    • 360 U.S. 684, 688-89 (holding that the First Amendment's "basic guarantee... of freedom to advocate ideas" extends even to the idea that "adultery may sometimes be proper").
    • See Kingsley Int'l Pictures Corp. v. Regents, 360 U.S. 684, 688-89 (1959) (holding that the First Amendment's "basic guarantee... of freedom to advocate ideas" extends even to the idea that "adultery may sometimes be proper").
    • (1959) Kingsley Int'l Pictures Corp. V. Regents
  • 53
    • 77954338496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare PATRICK DEVLIN, THE ENFORCEMENT OF MORALS 7-25 (1965) (arguing that because moral conformity was necessary to the stability of a society, removal of moral legislation will lead to societal collapse)
    • Compare PATRICK DEVLIN, THE ENFORCEMENT OF MORALS 7-25 (1965) (arguing that because moral conformity was necessary to the stability of a society, removal of moral legislation will lead to societal collapse),
  • 54
    • 77954317103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. HART, LAW, LIBERTY, AND MORALITY 14-15 (1963) (arguing that as long as no one is harmed by an action, prohibiting that action is "not the law's business").
    • with H.L.A. HART, LAW, LIBERTY, AND MORALITY 14-15 (1963) (arguing that as long as no one is harmed by an action, prohibiting that action is "not the law's business").
  • 55
    • 77954320537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 578.
    • See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 578.
  • 56
    • 77954331865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THE TRIAL OF LADY CHATTERLEY 207-25 (C.H. Rolph ed., 1961).
    • See THE TRIAL OF LADY CHATTERLEY 207-25 (C.H. Rolph ed., 1961).
  • 57
    • 72649093827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 798 N.E.2d 941, 960-61 Mass. (finding the state cannot deny same-sex couples the benefits that accompany civil marriage)
    • See Goodridge v. Dep't of Pub. Health, 798 N.E.2d 941, 960-61 (Mass. 2003) (finding the state cannot deny same-sex couples the benefits that accompany civil marriage);
    • (2003) Goodridge V. Dep't of Pub. Health
  • 58
    • 77954347899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE, JR., THE CASE FOR SAME SEX MARRIAGE: FROM SEXUALITY LIBERTY TO CIVILIZED COMMITMENT 87-123 (1996)
    • WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE, JR., THE CASE FOR SAME SEX MARRIAGE: FROM SEXUALITY LIBERTY TO CIVILIZED COMMITMENT 87-123 (1996);
  • 59
    • 77954321258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ROBIN WEST, MARRIAGE, SEXUALITY, AND GENDER 169-71 (2007)
    • ROBIN WEST, MARRIAGE, SEXUALITY, AND GENDER 169-71 (2007);
  • 60
    • 70349592292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral conflict and liberty: Gay rights and religion
    • Chai R. Feldblum, Moral Conflict and Liberty: Gay Rights and Religion, 72 BROOK. L. REV. 61,77-80 (2006).
    • (2006) BROOK. L. REV. , vol.72 , Issue.61 , pp. 77-80
    • Feldblum, C.R.1
  • 61
    • 77954332460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 102 Cong. Rec. 4460 (1956) (statement of Sen. George) (indicating that desegregation was "destroying the amicable relations between the white and Negro races").
    • See, e.g., 102 Cong. Rec. 4460 (1956) (statement of Sen. George) (indicating that desegregation was "destroying the amicable relations between the white and Negro races").
  • 62
    • 77749345509 scopus 로고
    • 347 U.S. 483, 494-95
    • See Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 347 U.S. 483, 494-95 (1954).
    • (1954) Brown V. Bd. of Educ.
  • 63
    • 77954324961 scopus 로고
    • 198 U.S. 45, 62-64 (declaring that the state should not "assume the position of a supervisor" by paternalistically setting working hours for bakers)
    • Compare Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45, 62-64 (1905) (declaring that the state should not "assume the position of a supervisor" by paternalistically setting working hours for bakers),
    • (1905) Compare Lochner V. New York
  • 64
    • 70949093040 scopus 로고
    • 300 U.S. 379,398-99 (upholding the constitutionality of Washington state's Minimum Wages for Women Act).
    • with W. Coast Hotel Co. v. Panish, 300 U.S. 379,398-99 (1937) (upholding the constitutionality of Washington state's Minimum Wages for Women Act).
    • (1937) W. Coast Hotel Co. V. Panish
  • 65
    • 77954330350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CATHERINE A. MACKINNON, ONLY WORDS passim (1993) (arguing that protecting pornography is "protecting sexual abuse as speech").
    • See CATHERINE A. MACKINNON, ONLY WORDS passim (1993) (arguing that protecting pornography is "protecting sexual abuse as speech").
  • 66
    • 70349256669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Robin West From Choice to Reproductive Justice: De- Constitutionalizing Abortion Rights, 118 YALE LJ. 1394, 1411 (2009) (suggesting that by considering parenting a "choice," the community exempts itself from any responsibility in alleviating the burden of childcare that the parent has "chosen").
    • See Robin West From Choice to Reproductive Justice: De- Constitutionalizing Abortion Rights, 118 YALE LJ. 1394, 1411 (2009) (suggesting that by considering parenting a "choice," the community exempts itself from any responsibility in alleviating the burden of childcare that the parent has "chosen").
  • 68
    • 77954345536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 567 F.3d 856, 858-60 7th Cir.
    • See NRA v. City of Chicago, 567 F.3d 856, 858-60 (7th Cir. 2009),
    • (2009) NRA V. City of Chicago
  • 69
    • 77954331385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 130 S. Ct 48 Sept. 30
    • cert, granted sub nom. McDonald v. City of Chicago, 130 S. Ct 48 (Sept. 30, 2009).
    • (2009) McDonald V. City of Chicago
  • 70
    • 77954342456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 226-28).
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 226-28).
  • 71
    • 77954335385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RONALD DWORHN, SOVEREIGN VIRTUE 66-119 (2008) (discussing at length how the equality of resources should be a positive goal of a government interested injustice).
    • See RONALD DWORHN, SOVEREIGN VIRTUE 66-119 (2008) (discussing at length how the equality of resources should be a positive goal of a government interested injustice).
  • 72
    • 77954336517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 226).
    • DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 226).
  • 73
    • 77954332200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 210).
    • See id. (manuscript at 210).
  • 74
    • 77954322883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 208)
    • See id. (manuscript at 208);
  • 75
    • 77954346281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 12, at 171-73,184-86.
    • DWORKIN, supra note 12, at 171-73,184-86.
  • 76
    • 77954342905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin does not neglect duty or obligation altogether. We all have moral duties not to harm others, Dworkin argues, and we all have moral duties to aid others in such a way as to reflect the objective value of their lives.
    • Dworkin does not neglect duty or obligation altogether. We all have moral duties not to harm others, Dworkin argues, and we all have moral duties to aid others in such a way as to reflect the objective value of their lives.
  • 77
    • 77954341223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 174-87).
    • DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 174-87).
  • 78
    • 77954322738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And, we all have a political duty to help ensure that we have a government that respects the objective lives of all citizens, which in turn entails that we should try to install a government that will pursue the redistribution of our collective wealth so as to guarantee to all citizens a minimal entitlement that reflects the hypothetical choice of a reasonable person to the insurance requisite to compensate for the risks of a poor genetic or monetary inheritance.
    • And, we all have a political duty to help ensure that we have a government that respects the objective lives of all citizens, which in turn entails that we should try to install a government that will pursue the redistribution of our collective wealth so as to guarantee to all citizens a minimal entitlement that reflects the hypothetical choice of a reasonable person to the insurance requisite to compensate for the risks of a poor genetic or monetary inheritance.
  • 79
    • 77954319791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 226-27 (proposing a system of hypothetical luck to "erase the consequences of bad luck").
    • Id. at 226-27 (proposing a system of hypothetical luck to "erase the consequences of bad luck").
  • 80
    • 77954344798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To discharge that duty as citizens, we should vote; and as legislators, we should legislate in a way that those minimal entitlements are met. Otherwise, we should protect markets and market outcomes so that they might operate in a way that not only reflects, but actually operationalizes, our individualized conceptions of the good. We then might also, as citizens, have a political duty to obey the law that follows on the heels of these principles. This is quite minimal. It does not tell us, for example, whether the failure of state, local, and national governments to keep the levees in good repair in Louisiana was a breach of a moral duty to exercise sovereignty in the interest of the governed, or for that matter, of the General Welfare Clause of the Constitution. It does not tell us whether the failure of any of those governments to protect us through legislation against climate change is such a failure. It does not tell us even whether a state's disavowal of the duty to educate children is a breach of a constitutional or moral duty. Beyond this duty to redistribute in line with the hypothetical insurance market's outcomes, the distinctive moral, political, or constitutional duties of legislators qua legislators affirmatively to pass law in such a way as to actually pursue "collective goals" beyond the redistributive entitlements that might be generated by the hypothetical insurance market, and in accordance with the moral duties that attach to the possession and exercise of power, gets a pass.
  • 81
    • 84898517974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ennobling politics
    • (H. Jefferson Powell & James Boyd White eds., 2009) (arguing that because the Constitution is "also our code of political morality," by focusing on negative rights defined by courts, the populace at large becomes apathetic to affirmative moral change);
    • See Robin West, Ennobling Politics, in LAW AND DEMOCRACY IN THE EMPIRE OF FORCE 58, 72-80 (H. Jefferson Powell & James Boyd White eds., 2009) (arguing that because the Constitution is "also our code of political morality," by focusing on negative rights defined by courts, the populace at large becomes apathetic to affirmative moral change);
    • Law and Democracy in the Empire of Force , vol.58 , pp. 72-80
    • West, R.1
  • 82
    • 70449939314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unenumerated duties
    • Robin West Unenumerated Duties, 9 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 221, 252-60 (2006).
    • (2006) U. PA. J. CONST. L. , vol.9 , Issue.221 , pp. 252-260
    • West, R.1
  • 83
    • 77954327589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORHN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 221-27).
    • See DWORHN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 221-27).
  • 84
    • 77954319790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 152-61, 235-38).
    • See id. (manuscript at 152-61, 235-38).
  • 85
    • 77954334666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 225-26).
    • See id. (manuscript at 225-26).
  • 86
    • 77954326025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Franklin D. Roosevelt, The Annual Message to the Congress (Jan. 6, 1941), in 1940 THE PUBLIC PAPERS AND ADDRESSES OF FRANKLIN D. ROOSEVELT 663, 672 (Samuel I. Rosenman ed., 1941).
    • See Franklin D. Roosevelt, The Annual Message to the Congress (Jan. 6, 1941), in 1940 THE PUBLIC PAPERS AND ADDRESSES OF FRANKLIN D. ROOSEVELT 663, 672 (Samuel I. Rosenman ed., 1941).
  • 87
    • 77954338339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 219).
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 1 (manuscript at 219).
  • 88
    • 35349009619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Education, equality, and national citizenship
    • See Goodwin Liu, Education, Equality, and National Citizenship, 116 YALE L.J. 330, 334-35 (2006).
    • (2006) YALE L.J. , vol.116 , Issue.330 , pp. 334-335
    • Liu, G.1
  • 89
    • 77954343405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 489 U.S. 189 (1989) (finding that a state was not responsible for child's brain-damage as a result of his father's abuse because the Due Process Clause exists "to protect the people from the State, not to ensure that the State protected them from each other").
    • -489 U.S. 189 (1989) (finding that a state was not responsible for child's brain-damage as a result of his father's abuse because the Due Process Clause exists "to protect the people from the State, not to ensure that the State protected them from each other").
  • 90
    • 77954338657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See West, supra note 49, at 1403
    • See West, supra note 49, at 1403;
  • 91
    • 0347136490 scopus 로고
    • Toward an Abolitionist Interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment
    • Robin West, Toward an Abolitionist Interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment, 94 W. VA. L. REV. 111,141 (1991).
    • (1991) W. VA. L. REV. , vol.94 , Issue.111 , pp. 141
    • West, R.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.