메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 30, Issue 2, 2009, Pages 255-271

Revisiting the contribution of literal meaning to legal meaning

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77954163716     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: 14643820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqp030     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (14)

References (130)
  • 1
    • 0037791008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Absurdity Doctrine
    • John Manning is a prominent exception; '[R]espect for the legislative process requires judges to adhere to the precise terms of statutory texts' and precludes them 'from making ad hoc exceptions to generally worded laws'. 2390, 2391
    • John Manning is a prominent exception; '[R]espect for the legislative process requires judges to adhere to the precise terms of statutory texts' and precludes them 'from making ad hoc exceptions to generally worded laws'. 'The Absurdity Doctrine' 116 Harv L Rev 2387-486 (2003), 2390, 2391.
    • (2003) Harv L Rev , vol.116 , pp. 2387-2486
  • 2
    • 0346975665 scopus 로고
    • The Practice and Problems of Plain Meaning
    • 716. The passage, concerning the US Supreme Court's 1989-90 Term, continues, 'This descriptive claim fits with Judge Wald's conclusions ..., and appears to be acknowledged as well by Professors Macey and Miller ...and elsewhere by Professors Eskridge and Sunstein.' (Citations omitted).
    • Fred Schauer, 'The Practice and Problems of Plain Meaning' 45 Vand L Rev 715-42 (1992), 716. The passage, concerning the US Supreme Court's 1989-90 Term, continues, 'This descriptive claim fits with Judge Wald's conclusions ..., and appears to be acknowledged as well by Professors Macey and Miller ...and elsewhere by Professors Eskridge and Sunstein.' (Citations omitted).
    • (1992) Vand L Rev , vol.45 , pp. 715-742
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 3
    • 77954164709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Robert Alexy and Neil MacCormick are among many who defend this view.
  • 4
    • 77954170234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See n 31, below
    • See n 31, below.
  • 5
    • 84959185663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Semantics, Pragmatics and Interpretation
    • Legal theorists have relied on the radical contextualism advanced by Searle, Travis and Recanati to refute the legal decisiveness of literal meaning, P Comanducci and others (eds), (Giapichelli, Torino), 162, 168
    • Legal theorists have relied on the radical contextualism advanced by Searle, Travis and Recanati to refute the legal decisiveness of literal meaning, see
    • (2008) Analisi e diritto , pp. 159
    • Poggi, F.1
  • 6
    • 77954171471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Legal Inferentialism: Toward a Pragmatics of Semantic Content in Legal Interpretation?
    • D Canale and G Tuzet, 'On Legal Inferentialism: Toward a Pragmatics of Semantic Content in Legal Interpretation?' 20 Ratio Juris 32-44 (2007), 35
    • (2007) Ratio Juris , vol.20 , pp. 32-44
    • Canale, D.1    Tuzet, G.2
  • 7
    • 60249095401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lexical Inderrminacy: Contextualism and Rule-following in Common Law Adjudication
    • A Wagner and others (eds) (Springer, Dordrecht)
    • R Charnock, 'Lexical Inderrminacy: Contextualism and Rule-following in Common Law Adjudication' in A Wagner and others (eds) Interpretation, Law and the Construction of Meaning (Springer, Dordrecht 2006) 21, 36-8
    • (2006) Interpretation, Law and the Construction of Meaning , vol.21 , pp. 36-38
    • Charnock, R.1
  • 8
    • 84937260000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Unintentional Fallacy
    • 927, 930
    • D Sosa, 'The Unintentional Fallacy' 86 Cal L Rev 919-38 (1998), 927, 930
    • (1998) Cal L Rev , vol.86 , pp. 919-938
    • Sosa, D.1
  • 9
    • 77954147210 scopus 로고
    • Marmor on Meaning, Interpretation, and Legislative Intention
    • J Goldsworthy, 'Marmor on Meaning, Interpretation, and Legislative Intention' 1 Legal Theory 439-54 (1995)
    • (1995) Legal Theory , vol.1 , pp. 439-454
    • Goldsworthy, J.1
  • 10
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
    • 606-15
    • HLA Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals' 71 Harv L Rev 593-629 (1958), 606-15
    • (1958) Harv L Rev , vol.71 , pp. 593-629
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 11
    • 0002106227 scopus 로고
    • Naming and Necessity
    • G Harman and others (eds), (Reidel, Dordrecht)
    • See eg S Kripke, 'Naming and Necessity' in G Harman and others (eds), Semantics of Natural Language (Reidel, Dordrecht 1972) 253
    • (1972) Semantics of Natural Language , pp. 253
    • Kripke, S.1
  • 12
    • 0010804169 scopus 로고
    • Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions
    • K Donnellan, 'Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions' 21 Synthese 335-58 (1970)
    • (1970) Synthese , vol.21 , pp. 335-358
    • Donnellan, K.1
  • 14
    • 0345569990 scopus 로고
    • The Semantics of Judging
    • M Moore, 'The Semantics of Judging' 54 S Cal L Rev 151-294 (1981)
    • (1981) S Cal L Rev , vol.54 , pp. 151-294
    • Moore, M.1
  • 15
    • 84928840861 scopus 로고
    • Legal Theory, Legal Interpretation, and Judicial Review
    • D Brink, 'Legal Theory, Legal Interpretation, and Judicial Review' 17 Phil & Pub Affairs 105-48 (1988)
    • (1988) Phil & Pub Affairs , vol.17 , pp. 105-148
    • Brink, D.1
  • 17
    • 31144469047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy
    • 11-13
    • R Dworkin, 'Hart's Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy' (2004) 24 OJLS 1-37, 11-13
    • (2004) OJLS , vol.24 , pp. 1-37
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 18
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Harv U Press, MA)
    • But see R Dworkin, Justice in Robes (Harv U Press, MA 2006) 11-12, 227
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 11-12
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 19
    • 77954166167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The school of thought commonly referred to as two-dimensionalism offers an interpretation of Kripke and Putnam's work that retains an essential role for description in semantic meaning
  • 20
    • 55449112578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Foundations of Two-Dimensional Semantics
    • For an overview and synthesis, M Garca-Carpintero and J Macia (eds), (OUP, NY)
    • For an overview and synthesis, see D Chalmers, 'The Foundations of Two-Dimensional Semantics' in M Garca-Carpintero and J Macia (eds), Two-Dimensional Semantics (OUP, NY 2006) 55
    • (2006) Two-Dimensional Semantics , pp. 55
    • Chalmers, D.1
  • 21
    • 0004230947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (MIT Press, MA), 92
    • Even philosophers who favour a broad reading of the implications of the externalist critique may be cautious about the prospect of deriving positive semantic theories from it, see eg M Devitt and K Sterelny, Language and Reality (MIT Press, MA 1999) 79-81, 92
    • (1999) Language and Reality , pp. 79-81
    • Devitt, M.1    Sterelny, K.2
  • 22
    • 0346113703 scopus 로고
    • Realistic Limits on Realist Interpretation
    • For example, S Munzer, 'Realistic Limits on Realist Interpretation' 58 S Cal L Rev 459-75 (1985)
    • (1985) S Cal L Rev , vol.58 , pp. 459-475
    • Munzer, S.1
  • 23
    • 84933494752 scopus 로고
    • Michael Moore's Realist Approach to Law
    • B Bix, 'Michael Moore's Realist Approach to Law' 140 U Pa L Rev 1293 (1992)
    • (1992) U Pa L Rev , vol.140 , pp. 1293
    • Bix, B.1
  • 24
    • 77954157955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nothing Else to Think? On Meaning, Truth and Objectivity in Law
    • A De Moor, 'Nothing Else to Think? On Meaning, Truth and Objectivity in Law' (1998) 18 OJLS 345-62
    • (1998) OJLS , vol.18 , pp. 345-362
    • De Moor, A.1
  • 25
    • 0742324002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin's Fallacy, or What the Philosophy of Language Can't Teach Us about the Law
    • M Green, 'Dworkin's Fallacy, or What the Philosophy of Language Can't Teach Us about the Law' 89 Va L Rev 1897-952 (2003)
    • (2003) Va L Rev , vol.89 , pp. 1897-1952
    • Green, M.1
  • 27
    • 33748936105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin on the Semantics of Legal and Political Concepts
    • D Patterson, 'Dworkin on the Semantics of Legal and Political Concepts' (2006) 26 OJLS 545-57
    • (2006) OJLS , vol.26 , pp. 545-557
    • Patterson, D.1
  • 29
    • 77954171604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Not all utterances will have propositional content, of course, but those of the legal variety will insofar as they purport to regulate conduct
  • 30
    • 0345138435 scopus 로고
    • Intention, Identity, and the Constitution
    • Intentionalist legal theorists have raised just this problem, G Leyh (ed), (U Cal Press, Berkeley), 192
    • Intentionalist legal theorists have raised just this problem; eg WB Michaels and S Knapp, 'Intention, Identity, and the Constitution' in G Leyh (ed), Legal Hermeneutics (U Cal Press, Berkeley 1992) 187, 192
    • (1992) Legal Hermeneutics , pp. 187
    • Michaels, W.B.1    Knapp, S.2
  • 31
    • 18744390273 scopus 로고
    • Defeasibility in Law and Logic
    • Z Bankowski and others (eds), (Kluwer, MA)
    • 'Defeasibility in Law and Logic' in Z Bankowski and others (eds), Informatics and the Foundations of Legal Reasoning (Kluwer, MA 1995) 99
    • (1995) Informatics and the Foundations of Legal Reasoning , pp. 99
  • 32
    • 77954160943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • We may contrast this with the broader notion of interest-as what we desire for ourselves, or as that which would be good for us to have
  • 33
    • 77954153603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Riggs v Palmer (1889) 115 NY 506
  • 34
    • 77954152149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defeasibility and Legal Positivism
    • The traditional understanding remains well defended, J Ferrer and others (eds), (OUP forthcoming)
    • The traditional understanding remains well defended, see eg WJ Waluchow, 'Defeasibility and Legal Positivism' in J Ferrer and others (eds), Essays on Legal Defeasibility (OUP forthcoming)
    • Essays on Legal Defeasibility
    • Waluchow, W.J.1
  • 35
  • 36
    • 27744571856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defeasibilism
    • 368
    • R Tur, 'Defeasibilism' (2001) 21 OJLS 355-68, 368
    • (2001) OJLS , vol.21 , pp. 355-368
    • Tur, R.1
  • 37
    • 77954146524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Nature of Rules and the Meaning of Meaning
    • 1472-3
    • K Greenawalt, 'The Nature of Rules and the Meaning of Meaning' 72 Notre Dame L Rev 1449-77 (1998), 1472-3
    • (1998) Notre Dame L Rev , vol.72 , pp. 1449-1477
    • Greenawalt, K.1
  • 38
    • 77954165438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It can be traced to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics 5, 10, 'For when the thing is indefinite the rule also is indefinite, like the leaden rule used in making the Lesbian moulding; the rule adapts itself to the shape of the stone and is not rigid and so too the decree is adapted to the facts.' accessed 15 October 2009
    • It can be traced to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics 5, 10, 'For when the thing is indefinite the rule also is indefinite, like the leaden rule used in making the Lesbian moulding; the rule adapts itself to the shape of the stone and is not rigid and so too the decree is adapted to the facts.' accessed 15 October 2009.
  • 39
    • 77954166301 scopus 로고
    • Against Formalism
    • S Levinson and others (eds), (Northwestern U Press, IL), 220-5
    • For example, WB Michaels, 'Against Formalism' in S Levinson and others (eds), Interpreting Law and Literature (Northwestern U Press, IL 1988) 215, 220-5
    • (1988) Interpreting Law and Literature , pp. 215
    • Michaels, W.B.1
  • 41
    • 33646890872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Putting Meaning in Its Place: Originalism and Philosophy of Language
    • 394-400
    • T Booher, 'Putting Meaning in Its Place: Originalism and Philosophy of Language' 25 Law & Phil 387-416 (2006), 394-400
    • (2006) Law & Phil , vol.25 , pp. 387-416
    • Booher, T.1
  • 42
    • 0042094065 scopus 로고
    • Legislators' Intentions and Unintentional Legislation
    • A Marmor (ed), (OUP, Oxford), 353
    • J Waldron, 'Legislators' Intentions and Unintentional Legislation' in A Marmor (ed) Law and Interpretation (OUP, Oxford 1995) 329, 353
    • (1995) Law and Interpretation , pp. 329
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 43
    • 0039233113 scopus 로고
    • A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation
    • 'the job of a legislature is to pass statutes, not to form intentions; accordingly, the choice of a legislature that ought to be respected is limited to the statute itself, exclusive of the hopes, fears and intentions that gave rise to its passage'
    • Similarly see M Moore, 'A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation' 58 S Cal L Rev 277-398 (1985), 355-6 'the job of a legislature is to pass statutes, not to form intentions; accordingly, the choice of a legislature that ought to be respected is limited to the statute itself, exclusive of the hopes, fears and intentions that gave rise to its passage'
    • (1985) S Cal L Rev , vol.58 , pp. 277-398
    • Moore, M.1
  • 44
    • 77954156953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Hart, Oxford), (using Robert Brandom's work on meaning to assert the possibility of 'semantically-clear cases'; esp ch 2)
    • M Klatt, Making the Law Explicit (Hart, Oxford 2008) (using Robert Brandom's work on meaning to assert the possibility of 'semantically-clear cases'; esp ch 2)
    • (2008) Making the Law Explicit
    • Klatt, M.1
  • 45
    • 0042696093 scopus 로고
    • (CUP, Cambridge), (arguing that literal meaning is as democratically plausible a basis for constitutional interpretation as reference to authors' intent)
    • D Lyons, Moral Aspects of Legal Theory: Essays on Law, Justice, and Political Responsibility (CUP, Cambridge 1993) 147-9 (arguing that literal meaning is as democratically plausible a basis for constitutional interpretation as reference to authors' intent)
    • (1993) Moral Aspects of Legal Theory: Essays on Law, Justice, and Political Responsibility , pp. 147-149
    • Lyons, D.1
  • 46
    • 77954154204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Searle himself allows that 'sentences have a conventional meaning independent of whatever authorial intentions they may have been uttered with.'
  • 47
    • 84937317744 scopus 로고
    • Literary Theory and Its Discontents
    • 656
    • 'Literary Theory and Its Discontents' 25 NLH 637-67 (1994), 656
    • (1994) NLH , vol.25 , pp. 637-667
  • 48
    • 77954172327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • If so, then absent some argument to the contrary, the literalist can claim that a statute's legal meaning is just its literal meaning alone
  • 49
    • 77954147476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • It's worth noting that our conclusion entails very little about how we identify an enactment's legal meaning; it just implies that doing so requires more than a theory of its literal meaning. Thus the argument allows-as surely it must-that the literal meaning of an enactment is an essential resource for its legal interpretation.
  • 50
    • 77954148232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As Lysander Spooner observed, 'if the intentions could be assumed independently of the words, the words would be of no use, and the laws of course would not be written'
  • 52
    • 77954164184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Word Meaning in Legal Interpretation
    • 484
    • See similarly, W Sinnott-Armstrong, 'Word Meaning in Legal Interpretation' 42 San Diego L Rev 465-92 (2005), 484
    • (2005) San Diego L Rev , vol.42 , pp. 465-492
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, W.1
  • 53
    • 77954170747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • For example, Frederick Schauer, 'that several centuries of Anglo-American legal cultures have been comfortable with empowering judges to search for and to correct statutory absurdity' is 'empirically contingent rather than inevitable'
  • 54
    • 77954149625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schauer (n 2) 732
    • , Issue.2 , pp. 732
    • Schauer1
  • 55
    • 56149085719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Critical Guide to Vehicles in the Park
    • 1134
    • Similarly, Schauer, 'A Critical Guide to Vehicles in the Park' 83 NYU L Rev 1109-34 (2008), 1128, 1134
    • (2008) NYU L Rev , vol.83 , pp. 1109-1134
    • Schauer1
  • 56
    • 77954146098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Attention is sometimes drawn to the Victorian judge John Jervis, who once held that 'If the precise words used are plain and unambiguous ... we are bound to them in their ordinary sense, even though it do lead, in our view of the case, to an absurdity or manifest injustice': Abley v Dale (1851) 11 CB 378, 391.
  • 57
    • 77954171159 scopus 로고
    • Contrast Shepherd v Conquest 17 CB 427, 441-5 (Jervis J)
    • Contrast Shepherd v Conquest (1856) 17 CB 427, 441-5 (Jervis J)
    • (1856)
  • 58
    • 0038019823 scopus 로고
    • Definitive confirmation of this appears impossible, (Dartmouth, MA), 485 (observing that all nine legal systems in the study recognized an absurdity doctrine)
    • Definitive confirmation of this appears impossible, but see N MacCormick and R Summers, Interpreting Statutes: A Comparative Study (Dartmouth, MA 1991) 461, 485 (observing that all nine legal systems in the study recognized an absurdity doctrine)
    • (1991) Interpreting Statutes: A Comparative Study , pp. 461
    • MacCormick, N.1    Summers, R.2
  • 59
    • 77954158253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Note that every legal system is vulnerable to accidents such as, 'this statute repeals all previous laws' instead of 'all relevant previous laws'
  • 60
    • 0009328199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Hart, Oxford), 115, 'the meaning of [legal] rules, like those of all symbols, must be determined by the actions themselves, that is, by the way the rules are used'
    • Interpretation and Legal Theory (Hart, Oxford 2005), 112-18, 115, 'the meaning of [legal] rules, like those of all symbols, must be determined by the actions themselves, that is, by the way the rules are used'
    • (2005) Interpretation and Legal Theory , pp. 112-118
  • 61
    • 84974224267 scopus 로고
    • Law as Practical Reason
    • 438-40
    • Similarly, MJ Detmold, 'Law as Practical Reason' (1989) 48 CLJ 436-71, 438-40
    • (1989) CLJ , vol.48 , pp. 436-471
    • Detmold, M.J.1
  • 62
    • 26444559831 scopus 로고
    • Wittgenstein, Realism, and CLS
    • (holding that to think of basic social rules as accounting for social regularities 'would be akin to mistakenly conceiving of the Universal Law of Gravitation as accounting for - in the sense of producing - a basic regular feature of the universe, viz., the mutual attraction of masses', n 46, below)
    • S Landers, 'Wittgenstein, Realism, and CLS' 9 Law & Phil 177-203 (1990) (holding that to think of basic social rules as accounting for social regularities 'would be akin to mistakenly conceiving of the Universal Law of Gravitation as accounting for - in the sense of producing - a basic regular feature of the universe, viz., the mutual attraction of masses', n 46, below).
    • (1990) Law & Phil , vol.9 , pp. 177-203
    • Landers, S.1
  • 63
    • 77954163610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Contrast with Wittgenstein's focus on the use of individual words
  • 64
    • 0004251932 scopus 로고
    • GEM Anscombe (tr), (Macmillan, NY) ss 3, (concerning the range of what counts as a 'game')
    • GEM Anscombe (tr), Philosophical Investigations (Macmillan, NY 1953) ss 3, 66-9 (concerning the range of what counts as a 'game')
    • (1953) Philosophical Investigations , pp. 66-69
  • 65
    • 77954146099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Marmor might object that the relevant patterns of usage are not just the applications of the enactment in question but the role that the making of that sort of utterance plays in social life. (This possibility was suggested by an anonymous referee.) In principle, this might be a persuasive response. In practice though, the only role played by the utterance of such sentences in social life is the purported application of some enactment or other. Thus, absent an enactment that, 'no vehicles are permitted in the park', who is going to be using that sentence? Practices of using a sentence to describe some distribution of rights or obligations seem unlikely to emerge in the absence of an act to which the sentence might refer. People will of course be using the words the sentence comprises, but reference to the meanings of individual words is what Marmor's strategy seeks to avoid. People will, after all, be using 'vehicle' to refer to police cars and the like.
  • 67
    • 84976202059 scopus 로고
    • Between Positivism and Idealism
    • See also, NE Simmonds, 'Between Positivism and Idealism' (1991) 50 CLJ 308-29
    • (1991) CLJ , vol.50 , pp. 308-329
    • Simmonds, N.E.1
  • 68
    • 0003701935 scopus 로고
    • Citing, (Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, London)
    • Citing F Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty (Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, London 1973) 134-5.
    • (1973) Law, Legislation and Liberty , pp. 134-135
    • Hayek, F.1
  • 69
    • 85011514399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How a Statute Applies
    • (both characterizing enactments as formal instantiations of convergent practices)
    • BB Levenbook, 'How a Statute Applies' 12 Legal Theory 71 (2006) (both characterizing enactments as formal instantiations of convergent practices)
    • (2006) Legal Theory , vol.12 , pp. 71
    • Levenbook, B.B.1
  • 70
    • 77954172632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Similarly, Cass Sunstein has written of legal perspicuity as owing to the presence of 'background norms ...so widely shared, they appear invisible and are not the object of controversy'.
  • 71
    • 84930558369 scopus 로고
    • Norms in Surprising Places
    • 807
    • 'Norms in Surprising Places' 100 Ethics 803-20 (1990), 807
    • (1990) Ethics , vol.100 , pp. 803-820
  • 73
    • 77954148078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dworkin would add that, to determine the meaning of the law on a particular occasion, one must take into consideration the content of the legal system as a whole, not simply a given enactment. There thus results in no disagreement with Dworkin on the conclusion that literal meaning is not legally decisive, but rather with someone who adopts Dworkin's analysis of rules minus his theory of holistic interpretation.
  • 74
    • 77954159175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defeasibility in Legal Reasoning
    • In contrast to Giovanni Sartor's critique of Dworkin, 142-4
    • In contrast to Giovanni Sartor's critique of Dworkin; 'Defeasibility in Legal Reasoning' in Bankowski (n 12) 119, 142-4
    • Bankowski , Issue.12 , pp. 119
  • 75
    • 77954170891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Some have argued that interpreters ought to be constrained to follow literal meaning if that is more likely, on the whole, to lead to a greater number of correct legal outcomes. See Fred Schauer's work on instrumentalist formalism, according to which, given error prone interpreters, treating literal meaning as decisive may result in a greater number of accurate legal judgments overall.
  • 77
    • 77954162912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Similarly, Adrian Vermeule has suggested that, given their interpretive limitations, judges should follow literal meaning
  • 78
    • 77954145955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Harv U Press, MA)
    • Judging Under Uncertainty (Harv U Press, MA 2006) 183-230
    • (2006) Judging Under Uncertainty , pp. 183-230
  • 79
    • 77954146527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Consideration of instrumental formalism is outside the scope of this article
  • 80
    • 0032238583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law Games: Defeasible Rules and Revisable Rationality
    • 451
    • B Chapman, 'Law Games: Defeasible Rules and Revisable Rationality' 17 Law & Phil 443-80 (1998), 451
    • (1998) Law & Phil , vol.17 , pp. 443-480
    • Chapman, B.1
  • 81
    • 77954150793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (n 12), (holding that the implications of a rule-not merely a judge's beliefs about them-are determined by what he knows)
    • See Bankowski (n 12), 13 (holding that the implications of a rule-not merely a judge's beliefs about them-are determined by what he knows.)
    • Bankowski1
  • 82
    • 77954166303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (n 7), (that there can be no unrevisable legal formula is not to say 'that there can be no defensible, theoretical formula that explains and justifies novel cases' resemblances with the paradigms')
    • Stavropoulos (n 7) 62 (that there can be no unrevisable legal formula is not to say 'that there can be no defensible, theoretical formula that explains and justifies novel cases' resemblances with the paradigms')
    • Stavropoulos1
  • 83
    • 77954151680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • 'Sequencing' is thus the application to statutory interpretation of non-monotonic logic, ie a logic in which the set of conclusions warranted on the basis of a given knowledge base does not increase with the size of the knowledge base itself. Under classical logic, in contrast, one's inferences, being deductively valid, can never be 'undone' by new information.
  • 85
    • 77954160333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Quietist philosophical theories disputing this distinction run into a minefield of contrary intuitions and practices
  • 86
    • 58149337329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Truth and Public Reason
    • See generally J Cohen, 'Truth and Public Reason' 37 Phil & Pub Affairs 2-42 (2009)
    • (2009) Phil & Pub Affairs , vol.37 , pp. 2-42
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 87
    • 77954164186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cohen aptly compares the minimalist about truth to someone who knows 'the rules of a game without knowing that the point of games is to win', 25. The comparison seems readily extendible to someone dealing in justified beliefs without recourse to a (distinct) concept of truth.
  • 88
    • 77954163332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • What Bernard Williams describes as our subjection of our beliefs to 'the disciplines of the virtues of truth'
  • 89
    • 1242316909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Princeton U Press, NJ)
    • Truth and Truthfulness (Princeton U Press, NJ 2002) 83
    • (2002) Truth and Truthfulness , pp. 83
  • 90
    • 69849091143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global Error and Legal Truth
    • Our discussion of legal truth may be contrasted with Brian Bix's recent article in this journal
    • Our discussion of legal truth may be contrasted with Brian Bix's recent article in this journal, 'Global Error and Legal Truth' (2009) 29 OJLS 535-47
    • (2009) OJLS , vol.29 , pp. 535-547
  • 91
    • 77954152150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Professor Bix is concerned with the truth of beliefs about the law and the possibility that they may be in error. We are concerned with the possibility of justified beliefs about correct legal outcomes being in error; we may assume that interpreters had an accurate understanding of the legal proposition itself.
  • 93
    • 77954149473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As any conclusion will depend equally on the relevance of the uncovered facts, the presence of this assumption doesn't presuppose the truth of any legal outcome
  • 94
    • 28244468652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Springer, Dordrecht), (rejecting a classical logic for legal conclusions on the basis that a deduction enabling premise would beg the question of the correct conclusion)
    • Pace J Hage, Studies in Legal Logic (Springer, Dordrecht 2005) 26-8 (rejecting a classical logic for legal conclusions on the basis that a deduction enabling premise would beg the question of the correct conclusion)
    • (2005) Studies in Legal Logic , pp. 26-28
    • Hage, P.J.1
  • 96
    • 77954156800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • On even pragmatist accounts of legal reasoning we find this understanding implicit
  • 97
    • 77954152292 scopus 로고
    • Logic in the Law
    • 908
    • Eg E Patterson, 'Logic in the Law' 90 U Pa L Rev 875-909 (1942), 908
    • (1942) U Pa L Rev , vol.90 , pp. 875-909
    • Patterson, E.1
  • 98
    • 77954153748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Thus in response to Fuller, Hart notes that 'For a legal system often has other resources besides the words used in the formulations of its rules which serve to determine their content or meaning in particular cases. Thus ...the obvious or agreed purpose of a rule may ...serve to show that words in the context of a legal rule may have a meaning different from that which they have in other contexts.
  • 100
    • 0041187328 scopus 로고
    • Does the Constitution Mean What It Always Meant?
    • foreshadowed this development in Hart's thinking; 1055, 1059, (holding that a constitutional bar exists in part because of its being found in the text, where that characteristic is also consistent with a constitutional permission).
    • Stephen Munzer and James Nickel foreshadowed this development in Hart's thinking; 'Does the Constitution Mean What It Always Meant?' 77 Colum L Rev 1029-62 (1977), 1055, 1059 (holding that a constitutional bar exists in part because of its being found in the text, where that characteristic is also consistent with a constitutional permission).
    • (1977) Colum L Rev , vol.77 , pp. 1029-1062
    • Munzer, S.1    Nickel, J.2
  • 101
    • 77954167699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Positivism, Anti-Realism, and the Interpretation of Statutes
    • For recent articulations of the idea of literal meaning as a decisional factor, see in K Segerberg and R Sliwinski (eds), (Uppsala U Press, Uppsala) 141
    • For recent articulations of the idea of literal meaning as a decisional factor, see T Spaak, 'Legal Positivism, Anti-Realism, and the Interpretation of Statutes' in K Segerberg and R Sliwinski (eds), Logic, Law, Morality (Uppsala U Press, Uppsala 2003) 127, 141.
    • (2003) Logic, Law, Morality , pp. 127
    • Spaak, T.1
  • 102
    • 77954162911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Synthetic Approach to Legal Interpretation
    • S Rickless, 'A Synthetic Approach to Legal Interpretation' 42 San Diego L Rev 519-32 (2005).
    • (2005) San Diego L Rev , vol.42 , pp. 519-532
    • Rickless, S.1
  • 103
    • 77954159047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Klatt (n 17) (semantic arguments may be decisive even though 'it is not possible to conclude legal clarity from semantic clarity,' 219). Many more contemporary scholars might be cited. For further examples, see n 15, above.
  • 104
    • 77954158637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Art 2 of the Constitution (the supreme enactment) states; 'No Person except a natural born Citizen ...shall be eligible to the Office of President'. A property that's 'natural' isn't man made, eg made by legislation. Hence we can't make someone natural born by legislative means-we may only legislate consequences for being natural born. It seems that the mere property of being born could only help qualify one for a privileged legal relationship with a state where birth occurs. Since Senator McCain wasn't born in the United States, the provision's literal meaning entails his ineligibility for the office.
  • 105
    • 77954167311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • There has been an article disputing this conclusion (though it does note an interpretive path to eligibility)
  • 106
    • 77951821269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why Senator John McCain Cannot Be President
    • See G Chin, 'Why Senator John McCain Cannot Be President' 107 Mich L Rev First Impressions 1-21 (2008)
    • (2008) Mich L Rev First Impressions , vol.107 , pp. 1-21
    • Chin, G.1
  • 107
    • 77954160785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • To my knowledge, no other legal scholar has written in support of Professor Chin's position nor does Chin base his reading of McCain's eligibility on the Constitution's literal meaning. Note the 2008 Senate Resolution unanimously affirming his eligibility; 110th Cong S Res 511.
  • 108
    • 77954158770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Professor Schauer uses the example of United States v Locke (1985) 471 US 84 to this effect
  • 109
    • 77954164356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (n 2)
    • Schauer (n 2) 728-42
    • Schauer1
  • 110
    • 77954166450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is Defeasibility and Essential Property of Law?
    • J Ferrer and others (eds), (OUP forthcoming)
    • Schauer, 'Is Defeasibility and Essential Property of Law?' in J Ferrer and others (eds), Essays on Legal Defeasibility (OUP forthcoming)
    • Essays on Legal Defeasibility
    • Schauer1
  • 111
    • 0005089976 scopus 로고
    • Compare, (CUP, NY), (countenancing literal decisiveness 'when the purpose of the law is only to coordinate an activity fairly, or when the law seeks to encourage reliance and someone has reasonably relied on its determinacy.')
    • Compare, S Burton, Judging in Good Faith (CUP, NY 1992), 178 (countenancing literal decisiveness 'when the purpose of the law is only to coordinate an activity fairly, or when the law seeks to encourage reliance and someone has reasonably relied on its determinacy.').
    • (1992) Judging in Good Faith , pp. 178
    • Burton, S.1
  • 112
    • 77954170537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • We think this, even though we may sometimes place value on an explicit handling of such points, eg Buckoke v GLC [1971] 1 Ch 655. A remark of the Victorian jurist James Fitzjames Stephen suggests an explanation; 'people continually try to misunderstand ...therefore it is not enough to attain to a degree of precision which a person reading in good faith can understand; but it is necessary to attain if possible to a degree of precision which a person reading in bad faith cannot misunderstand', Re Castioni [1891] 1 QB 149, 167.
  • 113
    • 77954153457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Note that for deictic words, eg 'now', literal meaning prescribes the relevance of a particular element of the context of any utterance thereof (in this case the time of utterance)
  • 114
    • 33646399736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Missing Step of Textualism
    • 'The Missing Step of Textualism' 74 Fordham L Rev 1913-36 (2006)
    • (2006) Fordham L Rev , vol.74 , pp. 1913-1936
  • 115
    • 77954157677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Consider Manning (n 1) 2463, 'If "drew blood" does not apply to an emergency medical procedure, it is because of a settled social connotation that associates that phrase, in predictable contexts, with acts of aggression.'
  • 116
    • 77954167848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The hypothetical, now a commonplace, is owed, of course, to Lon Fuller's original truck-as-memorial example
  • 117
    • 0000842517 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart
    • 663
    • 'Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart' 71 Harv L Rev 630-72 (1958), 663
    • (1958) Harv L Rev , vol.71 , pp. 630-672
  • 118
    • 0348050646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism and the Equity of the Statute
    • 115, 118-19
    • See Manning, 'Textualism and the Equity of the Statute' 101 Colum L Rev 1-127 (2001), 115, 118-19
    • (2001) Colum L Rev , vol.101 , pp. 1-127
    • Manning1
  • 119
    • 77954149053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • John Nagle advocates barring legal interpretations sensitive to 'scrivener's error' and 'absurd results' in light of the rarity of the cases in which such allowances are needed to avert an incorrect result
  • 120
    • 77954158481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism's Exceptions
    • D Farber (ed), accessed 15 October 2009
    • 'Textualism's Exceptions' in D Farber (ed) Dynamic Statutory Interpretation (2002) accessed 15 October 2009.
    • (2002) Dynamic Statutory Interpretation
  • 121
    • 77954153749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Similarly, Marmor has recognized cases where an act's prescriptive content differs from its semantic content as possible but 'very rare'
  • 122
    • 77954159904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Pragmatics of Legal Language
    • 429
    • 'The Pragmatics of Legal Language' 21 Ratio Juris 423-53 (2008), 429
    • (2008) Ratio Juris , vol.21 , pp. 423-453
  • 123
    • 77954168386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • To the theorist, the point is not that such cases must frequently be confronted, but that our reaction to them follows from the nature of our legal reasoning
  • 124
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • (2nd edn OUP, Oxford)
    • Hart, The Concept of Law (2nd edn OUP, Oxford 1994) 129
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 129
    • Hart1
  • 125
    • 0000852991 scopus 로고
    • Rules and Standards
    • 381
    • P Schlag, 'Rules and Standards' 33 UCLA L Rev 379-430 (1985), 381
    • (1985) UCLA L Rev , vol.33 , pp. 379-430
    • Schlag, P.1
  • 126
    • 77954166022 scopus 로고
    • The distinction has played a role in framing arguments about the nature of legal reasoning since, (Yale U Press, New Haven)
    • The distinction has played a role in framing arguments about the nature of legal reasoning since Roscoe Pound's Philosophy of Law (Yale U Press, New Haven 1922), 141-2
    • (1922) Philosophy of Law , pp. 141-142
    • Pound, R.1
  • 127
    • 77954172942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • '[R]ules, where we proceed mechanically, are more adapted to property and business transactions, ... [w]here the call is for individuality in the product of the legal mill, we resort to standards.'.
  • 128
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • See eg D Kennedy, 'Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication' 89 Harv L Rev 1685-778 (1976)
    • (1976) Harv L Rev , vol.89 , pp. 1685-1778
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 129
    • 33846647656 scopus 로고
    • The Justices of Rules and Standards
    • K Sullivan, 'The Justices of Rules and Standards' 106 Harv L Rev 22-123 (1992)
    • (1992) Harv L Rev , vol.106 , pp. 22-123
    • Sullivan, K.1
  • 130
    • 33846607277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rules, Standards, and the Internal Point of View
    • 1295 (taking 'as primitive the idea that "rules," as UJYUYnormative directives about conduct, are framed in terms of concepts that can be applied ...by specifying operative facts that trigger the rule.')
    • D Nance, 'Rules, Standards, and the Internal Point of View' 75 Fordham L Rev 1287-316 (2006), 1295 (taking 'as primitive the idea that "rules," as UJYUYnormative directives about conduct, are framed in terms of concepts that can be applied ...by specifying operative facts that trigger the rule.').
    • (2006) Fordham L Rev , vol.75 , pp. 1287-1316
    • Nance, D.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.