메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 71, Issue 2, 2009, Pages 279-312

Private law, public consequences, and virtue jurisprudence

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77952685785     PISSN: 00419915     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5195/lawreview.2009.137     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (4)

References (160)
  • 1
    • 77952695034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An introduction to aretaic theories of law
    • Colin Farrelly & Lawrence B. Solum eds., (emphasis added)
    • COLIN FARRELLY & LAWRENCE B. SOLUM, An Introduction to Aretaic Theories of Law, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE 2-3 (Colin Farrelly & Lawrence B. Solum eds., 2008) (emphasis added).
    • (2008) Virtue Jurisprudence , pp. 2-3
    • Farrelly, C.1    Solum, L.B.2
  • 2
    • 77952707869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 3
    • 77952730337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id at 2
    • Id at 2.
  • 4
    • 77952725320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The aretaic turn in constitutional theory
    • 498 ("The move from virtue ethics to virtue jurisprudence is simply the translation of the aretaic turn in moral theory to the context of lawmaking and adjudication. For example, virtue jurisprudence postulates that the proper aim of legislation is the promotion of human flourishing through creation of the conditions for the development of human excellence.")
    • Lawrence B. Solum, The Aretaic Turn in Constitutional Theory, 70 BROOK. L. REV. 475, 498 (2005) ("The move from virtue ethics to virtue jurisprudence is simply the translation of the aretaic turn in moral theory to the context of lawmaking and adjudication. For example, virtue jurisprudence postulates that the proper aim of legislation is the promotion of human flourishing through creation of the conditions for the development of human excellence.").
    • (2005) Brook. L. Rev. , vol.70 , pp. 475
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 5
    • 84985348224 scopus 로고
    • Non-relative virtues: An aristotelian approach
    • Further, the most well-known writer in the specific area of virtue and contract law is probably James Gordley
    • Probably the most well-known writer in law and legal philosophy to take virtue seriously is Martha Nussbaum. See, e.g., Martha C Nussbaum, Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach, XIII MIDWEST STUD. PHIL. 32 (1988). Further, the most well-known writer in the specific area of virtue and contract law is probably James Gordley.
    • (1988) Midwest Stud. Phil. , vol.13 , pp. 32
    • Nussbaum, M.C.1
  • 7
    • 0003706045 scopus 로고
    • By "public law" I mean those subjects of law that concern the relationship of state to individual, usually thought of as criminal law, constitutional law, administrative law, and international law, and by "private law" I mean those subjects of law that govern the relationships between private actors, such as contracts, corporate law, most property law, etc. See, e.g., abridged 6th ed.
    • By "public law" I mean those subjects of law that concern the relationship of state to individual, usually thought of as criminal law, constitutional law, administrative law, and international law, and by "private law" I mean those subjects of law that govern the relationships between private actors, such as contracts, corporate law, most property law, etc. See, e.g., BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY (abridged 6th ed. 1991).
    • (1991) Black's Law Dictionary
  • 8
    • 77952731984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As used in this essay, I do not mean to equate or conflate the terms "economics" or "law and economics," each of which is based on the social sciences, with the moral philosophies ofconsequentialism or utilitarisism. However, I do mean to capture a link between also suggested by Heidi Li Feldman, infra note 89, at 51 : that law and economics (as probably the most well-known strand of "neoclassical welfare economics"), is the "public policy counterpart" to certain consequentialist-based moral philosophies, including utilitarianism
    • As used in this essay, I do not mean to equate or conflate the terms "economics" or "law and economics," each of which is based on the social sciences, with the moral philosophies ofconsequentialism or utilitarisism. However, I do mean to capture a link between also suggested by Heidi Li Feldman, infra note 89, at 51 : that law and economics (as probably the most well-known strand of "neoclassical welfare economics"), is the "public policy counterpart" to certain consequentialist-based moral philosophies, including utilitarianism.
  • 9
    • 77952733950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FARRELLY & SOLUM, supra note 1, at 3 (noting that Anscombe's work highlighted the seemingly irresolvable competition between the two leading normative philosophical theories, deontology and consequentialism)
    • FARRELLY & SOLUM, supra note 1, at 3 (noting that Anscombe's work highlighted the seemingly irresolvable competition between the two leading normative philosophical theories, deontology and consequentialism);
  • 10
    • 21144437359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Modern moral philosophy and the virtues
    • Roger Crisp ed., (noting that Anscombe's 1958 essay charged moral philosophers to put aside rights and consequentialism until one could better explain the tenets of the two principles-"pleasure" and "intention"-and suggesting that virtue may be the key to such explanation)
    • see also Roger Crisp, Modern Moral Philosophy and the Virtues, in How SHOULD ONE LIVE? 1-2 (Roger Crisp ed., 1996) (noting that Anscombe's 1958 essay charged moral philosophers to put aside rights and consequentialism until one could better explain the tenets of the two principles-"pleasure" and "intention"-and suggesting that virtue may be the key to such explanation).
    • (1996) How Should One Live? , pp. 1-2
    • Crisp, R.1
  • 11
    • 77952738105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thanks to Dennis Patterson for emphasizing this parallel
    • Thanks to Dennis Patterson for emphasizing this parallel.
  • 12
    • 77952684779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When I mean virtue theory specifically as applied to law, I will try to use the phrase "virtue jurisprudence." But when I am describing virtue theory generally, I will use "aretaic theory" and "virtue theory" interchangeably, and sometimes just "virtue" for short Virtue theory has a specific meaning: Virtue theory is the area of enquiry concerned with the virtues in general; virtue ethics is narrower and prescriptive, and consists primarily in the advocacy of the virtues. Plato and Aristotle engaged in both simultaneously, but many modern philosophers have written on the virtues from positions of neutrality or even hostility. Crisp, supra note 8, at 5
    • When I mean virtue theory specifically as applied to law, I will try to use the phrase "virtue jurisprudence." But when I am describing virtue theory generally, I will use "aretaic theory" and "virtue theory" interchangeably, and sometimes just "virtue" for short Virtue theory has a specific meaning: Virtue theory is the area of enquiry concerned with the virtues in general; virtue ethics is narrower and prescriptive, and consists primarily in the advocacy of the virtues. Plato and Aristotle engaged in both simultaneously, but many modern philosophers have written on the virtues from positions of neutrality or even hostility. Crisp, supra note 8, at 5.
  • 13
    • 3142679947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normative virtue ethics
    • supra note 8, at 23
    • Rosalind Hursthouse, Normative Virtue Ethics, in How SHOULD ONE LIVE?, supra note 8, at 23.
    • How Should One Live?
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 14
    • 77952737308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 15
    • 0004123406 scopus 로고
    • There are numerous normative approaches to virtue theory. See, e.g., (virtue theory is justified because it helps citizens adhere to duty)
    • There are numerous normative approaches to virtue theory. See, e.g., ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, AFTER VIRTUE (1981) (virtue theory is justified because it helps citizens adhere to duty);
    • (1981) After Virtue
    • Macintyre, A.1
  • 16
    • 0040032815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The virtues and human nature
    • supra note 8, at 116 (noting "the consequentialist basis for our judgments of virtue."). By contrast to either of these approaches, neeAristotelian virtue theory derives its justification from virtue as an end in and of itself: virtue promotes human excellence, and human excellence is an end of itself, not tethered either to the concepts of duty or welfare
    • cf. Julia Driver, The Virtues and Human Nature, in How SHOULD ONE LIVE?, supra note 8, at 116 (noting "the consequentialist basis for our judgments of virtue."). By contrast to either of these approaches, neeAristotelian virtue theory derives its justification from virtue as an end in and of itself: virtue promotes human excellence, and human excellence is an end of itself, not tethered either to the concepts of duty or welfare.
    • How should one live?
    • Driver, J.1
  • 17
    • 77952696039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ARISTOTLE, SELECTIONS bk. 1.ch. 13,1102a5, at 363 (Terrence Irwin & Gail Fine trans., 1995) (translating ARISTOTLE, NICHOMACHEAN ETHICS)
    • ARISTOTLE, SELECTIONS bk. 1.ch. 13,1102a5, at 363 (Terrence Irwin & Gail Fine trans., 1995) (translating ARISTOTLE, NICHOMACHEAN ETHICS).
  • 18
    • 77952676155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. bk. 2, ch. 1, 1103a15-34, at 366
    • Id. bk. 2, ch. 1, 1103a15-34, at 366.
  • 20
    • 84925590860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A virtue-centered account of equity and the rule of law
    • supra note 1, at 157 ("Phronesis is the ability to respond appropriately to the particular situation.")
    • Lawrence B. Solum, A Virtue-Centered Account of Equity and the Rule of Law, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 157 ("Phronesis is the ability to respond appropriately to the particular situation.").
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 21
    • 77952715994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • M at 157-158 (discussing phronesis and judging)
    • M at 157-158 (discussing phronesis and judging).
  • 22
    • 77952728241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue and contract aw
    • forthcoming
    • Chapin F. Cimino, Virtue and Contract aw, 88 OR. L. REV. (forthcoming 2010).
    • (2010) Or. L. Rev. , vol.88
    • Cimino, C.F.1
  • 23
    • 77952713185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also ARISTOTLE, supra note 14, bk. 1.ch. 13, 1140a24-b21
    • See also ARISTOTLE, supra note 14, bk. 1.ch. 13, 1140a24-b21.
  • 24
    • 77952677512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., bk. 2, eh. 5, 1106a12-14, at 371
    • Id., bk. 2, eh. 5, 1106a12-14, at 371.
  • 25
    • 77952719593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., bk. 2, eh. 6, 1106a17-18, at 371-372
    • Id., bk. 2, eh. 6, 1106a17-18, at 371-372
  • 26
    • 77952704803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defending virtue ethics from the charge that it does not and cannot provide any guidance as to right action, as opposed to consequentialism and deontology, for example, is the thesis of the Hursthouse essay, Normative Virtue Ethics. See text accompanying note 34, infra. This charge is raised in support of the claim that virtue ethics is in fact not a normative rival to either consequentialism or deontology, which Hursthouse most assuredly believes it is
    • Defending virtue ethics from the charge that it does not and cannot provide any guidance as to right action, as opposed to consequentialism and deontology, for example, is the thesis of the Hursthouse essay, Normative Virtue Ethics. See text accompanying note 34, infra. This charge is raised in support of the claim that virtue ethics is in fact not a normative rival to either consequentialism or deontology, which Hursthouse most assuredly believes it is.
  • 27
    • 77952739831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The origin of the baseline is this: "[i]n everything continuous and divisible we can take more, less and equal, and each of them either in the object itself or relative to us; and the equal is some intermediate between excess and deficiency." ARISTOTLE, supra note 14, bk. 2, ch. 6,1106a27-29, at 372. The notion of the "equal" becomes the baseline: "[the] scientific expert avoids excess and deficiency and seeks and chooses what is intermediate-but intermediate relative to us, not in the object"
    • The origin of the baseline is this: "[i]n everything continuous and divisible we can take more, less and equal, and each of them either in the object itself or relative to us; and the equal is some intermediate between excess and deficiency." ARISTOTLE, supra note 14, bk. 2, ch. 6,1106a27-29, at 372. The notion of the "equal" becomes the baseline: "[the] scientific expert avoids excess and deficiency and seeks and chooses what is intermediate-but intermediate relative to us, not in the object"
  • 28
    • 77952722965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., NE bk. II, chap. 6, 1106b6-8. In other words, "[v]irtue, then, is a mean, insofar as it aims at what is intermediate."
    • Id., NE bk. II, chap. 6, 1106b6-8. In other words, "[v]irtue, then, is a mean, insofar as it aims at what is intermediate."
  • 29
    • 77952679337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., bk.2, ch.6, 1106b6-8, at 372
    • Id., bk.2, ch.6, 1106b6-8, at 372.
  • 30
    • 77952712168 scopus 로고
    • E. Capps, T.E. Page & W.H.D. Rouse eds., H. Rackham trans
    • ARISTOTLE: THE NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS 191-193 (E. Capps, T.E. Page & W.H.D. Rouse eds., H. Rackham trans., 1926).
    • (1926) Aristotle: The Nioomachean Ethics , pp. 191-193
  • 31
    • 80053818331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The virtues: Theory and common sense in greek philosophy
    • The virtues arise in us neither by nature nor contrary to nature; we are naturally receptive of them, but we are completed through habit." supra note 8, at 40-41 (quoting NlCHOMACHEAN ETHICS 1103a23-6)
    • "The virtues arise in us neither by nature nor contrary to nature; we are naturally receptive of them, but we are completed through habit." T.H. Irwin, The Virtues: Theory and Common Sense in Greek Philosophy, in How SHOULD ONE LIVE?, supra note 8, at 40-41 (quoting NlCHOMACHEAN ETHICS 1103a23-6).
    • How Should One Live?
    • Irwin, T.H.1
  • 32
    • 77952739830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The central tradition
    • Aristotle believed that the state should educate its citizens in the virtues. The state would do this in part to make up for the gaps in the family's ability to do so and in part to equip citizens to resist the inclination toward baseness that all humans are subject to. As such, virtue takes on a political cast-educating in the virtues is part of what the state should do for its citizens. See, e.g., supra note 1, at 26 ("Making men moral, Aristotle supposed, is a-if not the-central purpose of any genuine political community.")
    • Aristotle believed that the state should educate its citizens in the virtues. The state would do this in part to make up for the gaps in the family's ability to do so and in part to equip citizens to resist the inclination toward baseness that all humans are subject to. As such, virtue takes on a political cast-educating in the virtues is part of what the state should do for its citizens. See, e.g., Robert F. George, The Central Tradition, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 26 ("Making men moral, Aristotle supposed, is a-if not the-central purpose of any genuine political community.").
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • George, R.F.1
  • 33
    • 77952739160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Irwin, supra note 25, at 38-39
    • Irwin, supra note 25, at 38-39.
  • 34
    • 77952736281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more on how virtue is act-centered, see Hursthouse, supra note 11, at 19-36 (defending against the charge that because virtue is about how to "be" it does not provide guidance for the question of how to "act")
    • For more on how virtue is act-centered, see Hursthouse, supra note 11, at 19-36 (defending against the charge that because virtue is about how to "be" it does not provide guidance for the question of how to "act").
  • 35
    • 77952719172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, supra note 5, at 35 (emphasis in original)
    • Nussbaum, supra note 5, at 35 (emphasis in original).
  • 36
    • 77952707539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 36
    • Id. at 36.
  • 37
    • 77952727593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 35
    • Id. at 35.
  • 38
    • 77952720790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • M at 36. Nussbaum observes that Aristotle identified ten spheres of experience. They, and the corresponding virtue of "appropriate" response, are: fear of death (courage); bodily appetites and their pleasures (moderation); distribution of limited resources (justice); management of one's personal property where others are concerned (generosity); management of one's personal property where hospitality is concerned (expansive hospitality); attitudes and actions toward one's own worth (greatness of soul); attitudes toward slights and damages (mildness of temper); 'association and living together and the fellowship of words and actions' (truthfulness); truthfulness in speech (easy grace, as contrasted with coarseness, rudeness, insensitivity); social association of a playful kind (a kind of friendliness, contrasted with irritability and grumpiness); attitude toward the good and ill fortune of others (proper judgment, contrasted with enviousness, spitefulness, etc.); intellectual life (the various intellectual virtues, such as perceptiveness, knowledge, etc.); planning one's life and conduct (practical wisdom).
  • 39
    • 77952693141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 35-36 (quotation in original)
    • Id. at 35-36 (quotation in original).
  • 40
    • 77952734279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 38-39
    • Id. at 38-39.
  • 41
    • 33746957440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural law: The classical tradition
    • Specifically, a first principle of natural law theory on the question of true and right standards of conduct is "no ought from is," meaning that law is not justifiable until it is justified (by "some higher ought-premise"). 4 Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro ed.
    • Specifically, a first principle of natural law theory on the question of true and right standards of conduct is "no ought from is," meaning that law is not justifiable until it is justified (by "some higher ought-premise"). John Finnis, Natural Law: The Classical Tradition, in OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 3,4 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro ed., 2002).
    • (2002) Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law , pp. 3
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 42
    • 78649342482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural justice: An aretaic account of the virtue of lawfulness
    • supra note 1, at 188 ("At the center of [the natural law] tradition... is the idea that unjust laws are not true laws-lex injusta non est lex") (italics in original)
    • For a related idea, see also Solum, Natural Justice: An Aretaic Account of the Virtue of Lawfulness, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 188 ("At the center of [the natural law] tradition... is the idea that unjust laws are not true laws-lex injusta non est lex") (italics in original).
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Solum1
  • 43
    • 84972592548 scopus 로고
    • Natural right and aristotle's understanding of justice
    • 232
    • Bernard Yack, Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice, 18 POL. THEORY 216, 232 (1990).
    • (1990) Pol. Theory , vol.18 , pp. 216
    • Yack, B.1
  • 44
    • 77952723280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 230. Moreover, natural law represents "the articulation of some basic human goods or needs that any system of positive law must respect promote, or in any case protect"
    • Id. at 230. Moreover, natural law represents "the articulation of some basic human goods or needs that any system of positive law must respect promote, or in any case protect."
  • 45
    • 77952703314 scopus 로고
    • Natural law and virtue: Theories at cross-purposes
    • Robert George ed., Oxford By contrast Aristotelian natural right does not
    • Russell Hittinger, Natural Law and Virtue: Theories at Cross-Purposes, in NATURAL LAW THEORY 42 (Robert George ed., Oxford 1992). By contrast Aristotelian natural right does not.
    • (1992) Natural Law Theory , pp. 42
    • Hittinger, R.1
  • 46
    • 77952717836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Yack, supra note 34, at 231 ("Aristotle does not appeal to nature as a final standard against which to measure the justice of our laws and political judgments....")
    • Yack, supra note 34, at 231 ("Aristotle does not appeal to nature as a final standard against which to measure the justice of our laws and political judgments....").
  • 47
    • 70249108025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ("[W]hereas duty ethics conceives of moral motivation or practical necessity as obedience to rules, virtue ethics conceives of moral motivation or practical necessity as responsiveness to values. An honest person values truth and if she finds herself in a situation where she might tell the truth or tell a lie to advantage herself, she will respond to the value that the truth holds for her.")
    • STAN VAN HOOFT, UNDERSTANDING VIRTUE ETHICS 17 (2006) ("[W]hereas duty ethics conceives of moral motivation or practical necessity as obedience to rules, virtue ethics conceives of moral motivation or practical necessity as responsiveness to values. An honest person values truth and if she finds herself in a situation where she might tell the truth or tell a lie to advantage herself, she will respond to the value that the truth holds for her.").
    • (2006) Understanding Virtue Ethics , pp. 17
    • Van Hooft, S.1
  • 48
    • 77952680312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FARRELLY & SOLUM, supra note 1, at 2
    • FARRELLY & SOLUM, supra note 1, at 2.
  • 49
    • 77952727274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 6
    • Id. at 6.
  • 50
    • 77952727591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, one wonders: Should new laws be passed that incorporate virtuous rules or standards? Are rules inherently too determinate to incorporate indeterminate notions like virtue? Should virtue then inform broad, open-ended standards? Should future lawmaking, either by legislation or adjudication, be guided by or based on virtue? If so, how? Is the goal of law ultimately to encourage virtuous conduct? If so, would virtue over time eventually reduce the need for law-is virtue ultimately libertarian? If so, should law encourage virtuous conduct of only legal decision-makers, and/or ordinary citizens? How? Can legal institutions be structured virtuously? Or, should legal institutions be structured so they promote virtuous conduct of the people who utilize them? If so, how
    • For example, one wonders: Should new laws be passed that incorporate virtuous rules or standards? Are rules inherently too determinate to incorporate indeterminate notions like virtue? Should virtue then inform broad, open-ended standards? Should future lawmaking, either by legislation or adjudication, be guided by or based on virtue? If so, how? Is the goal of law ultimately to encourage virtuous conduct? If so, would virtue over time eventually reduce the need for law-is virtue ultimately libertarian? If so, should law encourage virtuous conduct of only legal decision-makers, and/or ordinary citizens? How? Can legal institutions be structured virtuously? Or, should legal institutions be structured so they promote virtuous conduct of the people who utilize them? If so, how?
  • 51
    • 77952704802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • George, supra note 26, at 24-50
    • George, supra note 26, at 24-50.
  • 52
    • 77952692040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERKOWITZ supra note 16, at 11 (1999)
    • BERKOWITZ supra note 16, at 11 (1999).
  • 53
    • 77952725321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • George, supra note 26, at 26
    • George, supra note 26, at 26.
  • 54
    • 77952720249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id at 29
    • Id at 29.
  • 55
    • 77952725626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 30 and n.16 (quoting NICOMACHEAN ETHICS x. 9.1180a)
    • Id. at 30 and n.16 (quoting NICOMACHEAN ETHICS x. 9.1180a).
  • 56
    • 77952738802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 32-33
    • Id. at 32-33.
  • 57
    • 77952685988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (writing that Aquinas's peculiarly Christian perspective "of course, never would have occurred to Aristotle.")
    • Id. (writing that Aquinas's peculiarly Christian perspective "of course, never would have occurred to Aristotle.").
  • 58
    • 77952731627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 38-42
    • Id. at 38-42.
  • 59
    • 77952685640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 47
    • Id. at 47.
  • 60
    • 77952681334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 33, at 174 (noting the philosophical debate between two conceptions: justice as fairness, or justice as lawfulness)
    • Solum, supra note 33, at 174 (noting the philosophical debate between two conceptions: justice as fairness, or justice as lawfulness).
  • 61
    • 77952729376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 167
    • Id. at 167.
  • 62
    • 77952705811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 63
    • 77952698506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 190. Phronimoi derives from the concept of phronesis, or practical wisdom: "phronesis is the ability to respond appropriately to a particular situation; aphronimos is able to respond appropriately because he or she has the experience to discern what is morally relevant about the situation"
    • Id. at 190. Phronimoi derives from the concept of phronesis, or practical wisdom: "phronesis is the ability to respond appropriately to a particular situation; aphronimos is able to respond appropriately because he or she has the experience to discern what is morally relevant about the situation."
  • 64
    • 77952721435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 157
    • Id. at 157.
  • 65
    • 77952733623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 66
    • 77952712862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. to aretaic theory, "just" positive laws (and so consistent with natural law) are those that are either "congruent" with social norms, or are "supported" by social norms. As unjust social norms and legal rules are not true nomoi, and could not be accepted by phronimoi, unjust norms and laws are not "true law" in the natural law conception of justice
    • Id. to aretaic theory, "just" positive laws (and so consistent with natural law) are those that are either "congruent" with social norms, or are "supported" by social norms. As unjust social norms and legal rules are not true nomoi, and could not be accepted by phronimoi, unjust norms and laws are not "true law" in the natural law conception of justice.
  • 67
    • 77952676819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 188-190
    • Id. at 188-190
  • 68
    • 77952700172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 182-183
    • Id. at 182-183
  • 69
    • 77952697742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 183
    • Id. at 183.
  • 70
    • 77952683051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 186 ("Justice does not need to do all the work in an aretaic legal theory. The end of law is not justice: it is human flourishing...Of course, justice is one of the virtues. So the law should aim at lawfulness....")
    • See id. at 186 ("Justice does not need to do all the work in an aretaic legal theory. The end of law is not justice: it is human flourishing...Of course, justice is one of the virtues. So the law should aim at lawfulness....").
  • 71
    • 77952676495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 190
    • See id. at 190.
  • 72
    • 77952733281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part La.
    • See supra Part La.
  • 73
    • 80051490129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judges of character
    • supra note 1, at 89 and n.3
    • Suzanna Sherry, Judges of Character, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 89 and n.3
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Sherry, S.1
  • 74
    • 84971882881 scopus 로고
    • Practical wisdom and professional character
    • 208 Jules Coleman & Ellen Frankel Paul eds.
    • (citing Anthony Kronman, Practical Wisdom and Professional Character, in PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 203, 208 (Jules Coleman & Ellen Frankel Paul eds., 1987)).
    • (1987) Philosophy of Law , pp. 203
    • Kronman, A.1
  • 75
    • 77952727919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Drawing on Aristotelian conception of virtue as middle ground between extremes. See text accompanying notes 17-19
    • Drawing on Aristotelian conception of virtue as middle ground between extremes. See text accompanying notes 17-19.
  • 76
    • 77952719592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sherry, supra note 61, at 91
    • Sherry, supra note 61, at 91.
  • 77
    • 77952708844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 92
    • Id. at 92.
  • 79
    • 0038759489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 531 U.S. 98
    • Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98 (2000).
    • (2000) Bush V. Gore
  • 80
    • 77952729717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sherry, supra note 61, at 93
    • Sherry, supra note 61, at 93.
  • 81
    • 77952716824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 91
    • Id. at 91.
  • 82
    • 77952694486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 83
    • 34247471382 scopus 로고
    • 323 U.S. 214 (demonstrating inappropriate deference to the legislature)
    • See Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214 (1944) (demonstrating inappropriate deference to the legislature).
    • (1944) Korematsu V. United States
  • 84
    • 77952394462 scopus 로고
    • 367U.S.497 (demonstrating inappropriate refusal to hear a challenge on justiciability grounds). A third example was the Court's refusal to grant certiorari in any case presenting the merits of educational affirmative action, which is now no longer so
    • See Poe v.Ullman, 367U.S.497(1961)(demonstrating inappropriate refusal to hear a challenge on justiciability grounds). A third example was the Court's refusal to grant certiorari in any case presenting the merits of educational affirmative action, which is now no longer so.
    • (1961) Poe V.Ullman
  • 85
    • 77952735220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sherry, supra note 61, at 88, 98-99
    • Sherry, supra note 61, at 88, 98-99.
  • 86
    • 84925590860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A virtue-centered account of equity and the rule of law
    • supra note 1, at 142, 157
    • Lawrence B. Solum, A Virtue-Centered Account of Equity and the Rule of Law, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 142, 157.
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 87
    • 77952710470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 157-60. Solum differentiates his notion of judging with phronimos from an approach that may sound similar: that of Dworkin's ideal judge, Hercules. To Solum, under a virtue-oriented approach, judicial choices are particularized to each case, while Hercules consults grand ideals for each choice. Solum argues that when judging from (with?) phronimos, grand theory building may be appropriate at times, and so a virtuous judge may at times reason as Hercules would, but then again a virtuous judge may be required to depart from "general rules and principles on the basis of their legal and moral perceptions of the facts of a particular case"
    • Id. at 157-60. Solum differentiates his notion of judging with phronimos from an approach that may sound similar: that of Dworkin's ideal judge, Hercules. To Solum, under a virtue-oriented approach, judicial choices are particularized to each case, while Hercules consults grand ideals for each choice. Solum argues that when judging from (with?) phronimos, grand theory building may be appropriate at times, and so a virtuous judge may at times reason as Hercules would, but then again a virtuous judge may be required to depart from "general rules and principles on the basis of their legal and moral perceptions of the facts of a particular case."
  • 88
    • 84864248687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two ways of doing the right thing
    • supra note 1, at 236, 240-242
    • Rosalind Hursthouse, Two Ways of Doing the Right Thing, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 236, 240-242
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 89
    • 77952701252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 244-247
    • Id. at 244-247
  • 90
    • 77952679336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 246, 248
    • Id. at 246, 248.
  • 91
    • 77952692041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civic liberalism and the "dialogical model" of judicial review
    • supra note l, at 107, 109
    • Colin Farrelly, Civic Liberalism and the "Dialogical Model" of Judicial Review, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note l, at 107,109.
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Farrelly, C.1
  • 92
    • 77952713184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 93
    • 77952709185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 94
    • 77952722285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 111 (noting that unlike George, his conception is non-perfectionist)
    • Id. at 111 (noting that unlike George, his conception is non-perfectionist).
  • 95
    • 77952703315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 110 (emphasis in original)
    • Id. at 110 (emphasis in original).
  • 96
    • 77952717494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 111. Farrelly admits that the virtues of toleration, civility and fairness are "elusive and indeterminate," in part given their "multi-track" nature. Farrelly notes: "one cannot completely describe, in the abstract, what the demands of these virtues are. It is only when we consider the context of a particular situation that one can begin to give some concrete life to these elusive virtues"
    • Id. at 111. Farrelly admits that the virtues of toleration, civility and fairness are "elusive and indeterminate," in part given their "multi-track" nature. Farrelly notes: "one cannot completely describe, in the abstract, what the demands of these virtues are. It is only when we consider the context of a particular situation that one can begin to give some concrete life to these elusive virtues."
  • 97
    • 77952708523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 125. The example he uses is how to handle, after 9/11, competing demands for heightened governmental protection against terrorism vs. demands for protections of individual liberties
    • Id. at 125. The example he uses is how to handle, after 9/11, competing demands for heightened governmental protection against terrorism vs. demands for protections of individual liberties.
  • 98
    • 77952706826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id at 123
    • Id at 123.
  • 99
    • 77952678532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 112
    • Id. at 112.
  • 100
    • 77952694139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 117
    • Id. at 117.
  • 101
    • 77952677510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 119
    • Id. at 119.
  • 102
    • 77952740136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 129-136 (describing the origins of "dialogical judicial review" within the Canadian Charter)
    • Id. at 129-136 (describing the origins of "dialogical judicial review" within the Canadian Charter).
  • 103
    • 77952713183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 120
    • Id. at 120.
  • 104
    • 77952703955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 134
    • Id. at 134.
  • 105
    • 77952693140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prudence, benevolence and negligence: Virtue ethics and tort law
    • supra note 1, at 51
    • See generally Heidi Li Feldman, Prudence, Benevolence and Negligence: Virtue Ethics and Tort Law, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 51.
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Feldman, H.L.1
  • 106
    • 77952724983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 107
    • 77952737636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 52
    • Id. at 52.
  • 108
    • 77952733280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 51
    • Id. at 51.
  • 109
    • 77952693478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 52
    • Id. at 52.
  • 110
    • 77952676820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On aristotelian criminal law: A reply to duff
    • supra note 1, at 215
    • Kyron Huigens, On Aristotelian Criminal Law: A Reply to Duff, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 215.
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Huigens, K.1
  • 111
    • 77952713670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 222
    • Id. at 222.
  • 112
    • 77952738438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 223-224
    • Id. at 223-224
  • 113
    • 77952680313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Huigens asserts In a virtue ethics theory of punishments, responsibility for one's character and for the quality of one's practical reasoning-including one's deliberation on ends-is portrayed as essential to just punishment People do not commit crimes because they fail to fit means to ends. They commit crimes because their ends are wrong. The failures of reasoning that lead people to commit crimes are not instrumental errors confined to the immediate circumstances of the offense. Crimes are manifestations of callousness, persistent immaturity, narcissism, greed, lack of empathy, impulsiveness, uncontrolled anger, and so on-failures in the rational constructions of an agent's motivations, including the standing motivations that make up a character. We hold people responsible for failures of character in ordinary morality, and when failures of this kinds result in a violation of a criminal prohibition, we hold people responsible by punishing them.
  • 114
    • 77952707206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 224-225
    • Id. at 224-225
  • 115
    • 77952701253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue, vice, and criminal liability
    • supra note 1, at 206-208
    • Antony Duff, Virtue, Vice, and Criminal Liability, in VIRTUE JURISPRUDENCE, supra note 1, at 206-208
    • Virtue Jurisprudence
    • Duff, A.1
  • 116
    • 77952715993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 203-206
    • Id. at 203-206
  • 117
    • 77952712533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 205
    • Id. at 205.
  • 118
    • 77952679977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 119
    • 77952690499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Cimino, supra note 19
    • See generally Cimino, supra note 19.
  • 120
    • 77952723596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. Another is the reasonableness standard in contract law. As I have written elsewhere, this doctrinal space could be another where virtue could give content to law
    • Id. Another is the reasonableness standard in contract law. As I have written elsewhere, this doctrinal space could be another where virtue could give content to law.
  • 121
    • 77952714312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feldman, supra note 89
    • Feldman, supra note 89.
  • 122
    • 77952710471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distributive justice allocates social and political benefits and burdens between citizens, while corrective justice rights wrongs between private parties
    • Distributive justice allocates social and political benefits and burdens between citizens, while corrective justice rights wrongs between private parties.
  • 123
    • 77952699173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Too many theories
    • Todd D. Rakoff, Too Many Theories, 94 MICH. L. REV. 1799 (1996)
    • (1996) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 1799
    • Rakoff, T.D.1
  • 124
    • 0004140491 scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press ("We thus see in contract scholarship what we see in legal scholarship generally these days-a proliferation of theories.")
    • (reviewing MICHAEL J. TREBUJCOCK, THE LIMITS OF FREEDOM OF CONTRACT (Harvard University Press 1993)) ("We thus see in contract scholarship what we see in legal scholarship generally these days-a proliferation of theories.").
    • (1993) The Limits of Freedom of Contract
    • Trebujcock, M.J.1
  • 125
    • 77952722607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1799 ("Contract law aspires both to state the law governing social interactions-buying, hiring, leasing, and licensing-and to depict an ideal societ - the market free and just.")
    • Id. at 1799 ("Contract law aspires both to state the law governing social interactions-buying, hiring, leasing, and licensing-and to depict an ideal societ - the market free and just.").
  • 126
    • 22744437696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contact and collaboration
    • 419-420
    • Daniel Markovits, Contact and Collaboration, 113 YALE L.J. 1417,419-420 (2004).
    • (2004) Yale L.J. , vol.113 , pp. 1417
    • Markovits, D.1
  • 127
    • 0041405888 scopus 로고
    • Contract law and distributive justice
    • 473
    • Anthony Kronman, Contract Law and Distributive Justice, 89 YALE L.J. 472, 473 (1980).
    • (1980) Yale L.J. , vol.89 , pp. 472
    • Kronman, A.1
  • 128
    • 0005692758 scopus 로고
    • The basis of contract
    • 562
    • Morris R. Cohen, The Basis of Contract, 46 HARV. L. REV. 553, 562 (1933).
    • (1933) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.46 , pp. 553
    • Cohen, M.R.1
  • 129
    • 77952715992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markovits, supra note 108, at 1419-1420
    • Markovits, supra note 108, at 1419-1420
  • 130
    • 77952688845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 1419
    • See, e.g., id. at 1419.
  • 131
    • 77952723593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TREBILCOCK, supra note 106, at 141-142 ("Macneil's approach, no matter how accurately it describes reality, does not yield determinate legal principles for governing the allocation of unassigned risks ....")
    • TREBILCOCK, supra note 106, at 141-142 ("Macneil's approach, no matter how accurately it describes reality, does not yield determinate legal principles for governing the allocation of unassigned risks ....").
  • 132
    • 77952709824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markovits, supra note 108, at 1419
    • Markovits, supra note 108, at 1419.
  • 133
    • 77952739484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1420 (advancing the ideal that a contact creates between the parties a "respectful community")
    • Id. at 1420 (advancing the ideal that a contact creates between the parties a "respectful community").
  • 134
    • 77952705810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Loyola Legal Studies Working Paper No. 2007-29
    • Robin Bradley Kar, Contractualism about Contract Law (Loyola Legal Studies Working Paper No. 2007-29,2007), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract= 993809.
    • (2007) Contractualism about Contract Law
    • Kar, R.B.1
  • 135
    • 77952730978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 136
    • 77952676494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, supra note 110, at 586 ("From this point of view the law of contract may be viewed as a subsidiary branch of public law, as a body of rules according to which the sovereign power of the state will be exercised as between the parties to a more or less voluntary transaction.")
    • Cohen, supra note 110, at 586 ("From this point of view the law of contract may be viewed as a subsidiary branch of public law, as a body of rules according to which the sovereign power of the state will be exercised as between the parties to a more or less voluntary transaction.").
  • 137
    • 77952691166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kronman, supra note 109, at 474 (asserting that the "non- distributive conception of contract law cannot be supported on either liberal or libertarian grounds, and defend[ing] the view that rules of contract law should be used to implement distributional goals whenever alternative ways of doing so are likely to be more costly or intrusive.")
    • See, e.g., Kronman, supra note 109, at 474 (asserting that the "non-distributive conception of contract law cannot be supported on either liberal or libertarian grounds, and defend[ing] the view that rules of contract law should be used to implement distributional goals whenever alternative ways of doing so are likely to be more costly or intrusive.").
  • 138
    • 77952710818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 499
    • Id. at 499.
  • 139
    • 77952686639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Moreover, one could also say that like any unifying theory, contract theory is inherently political. Contract theory asks, why and when do we enforce contracts? As with any theory, different theories of contract have different political foundations and consequences. For example, the will theory of contract, where it is said that courts enforce contracts because, and only to the extent that, contracts are the product of each party's will, is rooted in the same Enlightenment political philosophy valuing personal freedom which informed our Jeffersonian Bill of Rights. And as theory informs doctrine, the rules themselves take on a political cast. This is observable even at the most meta-level of contact doctrine, tracing the evolution of the common law from pre-classical contract to the First Restatement (individualism and will theory), to the Second Restatement and the U.C.C. (both more objective, more reliant on community standards and judgments about "reasonableness").
  • 140
    • 77952678904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FARRELLY & SOLUM, supra note 1, at 109
    • FARRELLY & SOLUM, supra note 1, at 109.
  • 141
    • 77952688294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posting of The Editors to THE NEW YORK TIMES Room for Debate Blog, (Mar. 17, 2009, 18:25 EST) [hereinafter Posting of The Editors]
    • Posting of The Editors to THE NEW YORK TIMES Room for Debate Blog, http://roomfordebate .blogs.nytimes.com/2009/03/17/when-bonus-contracts-can-be- broken/ (Mar. 17, 2009, 18:25 EST) [hereinafter Posting of The Editors].
  • 142
    • 77952694485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posting of Randy Cohen to THE NEW YORK TIMES Moral of the Story Blog, (Apr. 21, 2009, 7:00 EST)
    • Posting of Randy Cohen to THE NEW YORK TIMES Moral of the Story Blog, http://ethicistblogs .nytimes.com/2009/04/21/thy-neighbors-mortgage/ (Apr. 21, 2009, 7:00 EST).
  • 143
    • 77952730637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kar, supra note 116, at 103 (observing that, as compared to its deontological rivals, economic theories of contract have proved "particularly robust")
    • Kar, supra note 116, at 103 (observing that, as compared to its deontological rivals, economic theories of contract have proved "particularly robust").
  • 144
    • 77952686638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posting of The Editors, supra note 123
    • Posting of The Editors, supra note 123.
  • 145
    • 77952704465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The New York Times Dealbook, Geitner Urges Bank Fees to Recoup A.I.G. Bonuses
    • See, e.g., The New York Times Dealbook, Geitner Urges Bank Fees to Recoup A.I.G. Bonuses,
  • 146
    • 77952739485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feb. 24, 2010 available online at
    • Feb. 24, 2010 (available online at http://dealbook.blogs.nytimes.com/ 2010/02/03/geitnner-urges-bank-fees-to-recoup-aig-bonuses/?scp=2).
  • 147
    • 77952720618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mar. 17, 2009, 18:25 EST
    • Posting of Tom Baker to THE NEW YORK TIMES Room for Debate Blog, http://roomfordebate.blogs.nytimes.com/2009/03/17/when-bonus-contracts-can-be- broken/ (Mar. 17, 2009, 18:25 EST) ("Contracts get repudiated, renegotiated, modified, delayed, worked out, managed-pick your euphemism-all the time. A. I. G. knows this.").
    • The New York Times Room for Debate Blog
    • Baker, T.1
  • 148
    • 77952722964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Mar. 17,2009,18:25 EST)
    • Posting of Charles Fried to THE NEW YORK TIMES Room for Debate Blog, http://roomfordebate .blogs.nytimes.com/2009/03/17/when-bonus-contracts-can-be- broken/(Mar. 17,2009,18:25 EST).
    • The New York Times Room for Debate Blog
    • Fried, C.1
  • 149
    • 77952734924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Mar. 17,2009,18:25 EST)
    • Posting of Frank Snyder to THE NEW YORK TIMES Room for Debate Blog, http://roomfordebate .blogs.nytimes.com/2009/03/17/when-bonus-contracts-can-be- broken/ (Mar. 17,2009,18:25 EST).
    • The New York Times Room for Debate Blog
    • Snyder, F.1
  • 150
    • 77952727592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Mar. 17,2009,18:25 EST)
    • Posting of James P. Tuthill to THE NEW YORK TIMES Room for Debate Blog, http://roomfordebate.blogs.nytimes.com/2009/03/17/when-bonus-ccatracts-can-be- broken/ (Mar. 17,2009,18:25 EST).
    • The New York Times Room for Debate Blog
    • Tuthill, J.P.1
  • 151
    • 77952683735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Mar. 17,2009,18:25 EST)
    • Posting of Glenn Greenwald to THE NEW YORK TIMES Room for Debate Blog, http://roomfor debate.blogs.nytimes.com/2009/03/17/when-bonus-contracts-can-be- broken/(Mar. 17,2009,18:25 EST).
    • The New York Times Room for Debate Blog
    • Greenwald, G.1
  • 152
    • 77952725976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cimino, supra note 19
    • Cimino, supra note 19. Virtue theory requires equal consideration of both the means and ends of any particular problem. The two dominant normative theories, by contrast each privilege one over the other deontology privileges the means over the ends, and consequentialism privileges the ends over the means. As I have written elsewhere, virtue analysis is symbiotic: its reasoning embraces both means and ends fully and equally, and so virtue jurisprudence does not suffer from "blindspots" as do both law and economics and rights-based theories.
  • 153
    • 77952713982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The case for paying out bonuses
    • Mar. 17
    • Andrew Ross Sorkin, The Case For Paying Out Bonuses at A. I. G., N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 17, 2009, at B1.
    • (2009) A. I. G., N.Y. Times
    • Sorkin, A.R.1
  • 154
    • 77952724619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fried, supra note 129
    • Fried, supra note 129.
  • 156
    • 77951816802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 136
    • U.S. DEP'T OF THE TREASURY, supra note 136, at 7 (describing new requirement that "all financial institutions receiving Financial Stability Plan financial assistance going forward" to "implement loan modification plans consistent with Treasury Guidelines." The goal of the mandatory modification program is to prevent foreclosures from happening in the first place, and is to apply first to loans issues by Fannie Mae and Freddie Mac, and then to be implemented "across the mortgage market.").
    • U.S. Dep't of the Treasury , pp. 7
  • 157
    • 77952729975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, supra note 124
    • Cohen, supra note 124.
  • 158
    • 77951816802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 136
    • U.S. DEP'T OF THE TREASURY, supra note 136, at 1 ("The deep contraction in the economy and in the housing market has created devastating consequences for homeowners and communities throughout the country. . . The present crisis is real, but temporary. As home prices fall, demand for housing will increase, and conditions will ultimately find a new balance. Yet in the absence of decisive action, we risk an intensifying spiral in which lenders foreclose, pushing areas home prices still lower, reducing the value of household savings and making it harder for all families to refinance, to some studies, foreclosure on a home has been found to reduce the prices of nearby homes by as much as 9%.").
    • U.S. Dep't of the Treasury , pp. 1
  • 160
    • 77952702979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 3 (emphasis in original)
    • The program materials state that the goal is to reconcile these interests by "bring[ing] together lenders, investors, servicers, borrowers, and the government, so that all stakeholders share in the cost of ensuring that responsible homeowners can afford their monthly mortgage payments-helping to reach up to 3 to 4 million at-risk borrowers in all segments of the mortgage market reducing foreclosures, and helping to avoid further downward pressures on overall home prices." Id. at 3 (emphasis in original).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.