-
1
-
-
70449453584
-
-
(Boston MA: Beacon Press), Freyfogle is Professor of Law at the University of Illinois
-
Eric Freyfogle, On Private Property (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 2007), xxi. Freyfogle is Professor of Law at the University of Illinois.
-
(2007)
On Private Property
-
-
Freyfogle, E.1
-
2
-
-
77952591713
-
-
Rousseau's distinction is found in his Social Contract, chapter 8: "What man loses is his natural freedom and an unlimited right to everything that tempts him and that he can get; what he gains is civil freedom and the proprietorship of everything he possesses. . . . [O]ne must distinguish carefully . . . between possession, which is only the effect of force or the right of first occupant, and property, which can only be based on a positive title." See, (with Geneva Manuscript and Political Economy), trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin's Press), emphasis added.3
-
Rousseau's distinction is found in his Social Contract, chapter 8: "What man loses is his natural freedom and an unlimited right to everything that tempts him and that he can get; what he gains is civil freedom and the proprietorship of everything he possesses. . . . [O]ne must distinguish carefully . . . between possession, which is only the effect of force or the right of first occupant, and property, which can only be based on a positive title." See Jean-Jacques Rousseau, On the Social Contract (with Geneva Manuscript and Political Economy), trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1978), 56; emphasis added.3
-
(1978)
On the Social Contract
, pp. 56
-
-
Rousseau, J.-J.1
-
3
-
-
77952586848
-
-
According to the Public Broadcasting System Web site on Rome, "Another difference between Roman slavery and its more modern variety was manumission-the ability of slaves to be freed
-
According to the Public Broadcasting System Web site on Rome (http://www.pbs.org/ empires/romans/empire/slaves-freemen.html): "Another difference between Roman slavery and its more modern variety was manumission-the ability of slaves to be freed.
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
77952645417
-
-
Roman owners freed their slaves in considerable numbers: some freed them outright, while others allowed them to buy their own freedom. The prospect of possible freedom through manumission encouraged most slaves to be obedient and hard working. . . . Formal manumission was performed by a magistrate and gave freed men full Roman citizenship. The one exception was that they were not allowed to hold office. However, the law gave any children born to freedmen, after formal manumission, full rights of citizenship, including the right to hold office." On the idea of buying out of slavery in the modern setting of Sudan, see Kwame Anthony Appiah and Martin Bunzl, eds., (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press)
-
Roman owners freed their slaves in considerable numbers: some freed them outright, while others allowed them to buy their own freedom. The prospect of possible freedom through manumission encouraged most slaves to be obedient and hard working. . . . Formal manumission was performed by a magistrate and gave freed men full Roman citizenship. The one exception was that they were not allowed to hold office. However, the law gave any children born to freedmen, after formal manumission, full rights of citizenship, including the right to hold office." On the idea of buying out of slavery in the modern setting of Sudan, see Kwame Anthony Appiah and Martin Bunzl, eds., Buying Freedom (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007).
-
(2007)
Buying Freedom
-
-
-
5
-
-
0004273805
-
-
(New York: Basic Books), takes this approach
-
Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), takes this approach.
-
(1974)
Anarchy State and Utopia
-
-
Nozick, R.1
-
6
-
-
77952622955
-
-
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), takes Nozick to be doing so; see esp. chap. 3, Self-Ownership, World Ownership, and Equality,"
-
G. A. Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), takes Nozick to be doing so; see esp. chap. 3, "Self-Ownership, World Ownership, and Equality," 67-91.
-
(1995)
Self-Ownership Freedom and Equality
, pp. 67-91
-
-
Cohen, G.A.1
-
7
-
-
0004024838
-
-
(Oxford: Oxford University Press), discusses the notion that liberty is founded on self-ownership at some length. My disagreement with much of Kymlicka's treatment would take too long to explain here. Note that I do not take these writers to suppose that either Locke or Mill themselves took the principle of liberty to be founded on self-ownership. Locke thinks that it is founded on reason, whatever that is supposed to mean, and Mill thinks that it is founded on utility
-
Will Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), 103-125, discusses the notion that liberty is founded on self-ownership at some length. My disagreement with much of Kymlicka's treatment would take too long to explain here. Note that I do not take these writers to suppose that either Locke or Mill themselves took the principle of liberty to be founded on self-ownership. Locke thinks that it is founded on reason, whatever that is supposed to mean, and Mill thinks that it is founded on utility.
-
(1990)
Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction
, pp. 103-125
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
-
8
-
-
77952606151
-
-
In so saying, I disagree with G. A. Cohen, who proposes that self-ownership is fully reflexive, so that "what owns and what is owned are one and the same, namely, the whole person" (Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality, 69). I do not think that pure reflexivity makes sense, metaphysically speaking. What does make sense is the control of the rest of us by our proprietarily so-called "selves," that is, the consciously deliberating, willing, and feeling parts of our minds. This may be a metaphysical issue of little import-apart from its connections to, say, slavery. And in any case, I cannot discuss the issue further in the present essay
-
In so saying, I disagree with G. A. Cohen, who proposes that self-ownership is fully reflexive, so that "what owns and what is owned are one and the same, namely, the whole person" (Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality, 69). I do not think that pure reflexivity makes sense, metaphysically speaking. What does make sense is the control of the rest of us by our proprietarily so-called "selves," that is, the consciously deliberating, willing, and feeling parts of our minds. This may be a metaphysical issue of little import-apart from its connections to, say, slavery. And in any case, I cannot discuss the issue further in the present essay
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
77952607853
-
-
Perhaps minds are entirely physical, in which case perhaps there is a literal location for the decision-making parts of the mind. That metaphysical question is of no special concern in this connection, interesting though it may be in its own right
-
Perhaps minds are entirely physical, in which case perhaps there is a literal location for the decision-making parts of the mind. That metaphysical question is of no special concern in this connection, interesting though it may be in its own right.
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
77952652652
-
-
Current federal income tax rates in the United States do not quite reach the 50 percent level, but they do in Canada, where I live, and in some countries in Europe. In any case, adding up various taxes and charges that amount to taxes (at the municipal, state, and federal level) will yield total tax levels on this order even in the United States
-
Current federal income tax rates in the United States do not quite reach the 50 percent level, but they do in Canada, where I live, and in some countries in Europe. In any case, adding up various taxes and charges that amount to taxes (at the municipal, state, and federal level) will yield total tax levels on this order even in the United States.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
77952587693
-
-
Malcolm Murray analyzes this, brilliantly, as a matter of acting with the consent of the individual affected. See, (New York: Springer), esp. chap. 6
-
Malcolm Murray analyzes this, brilliantly, as a matter of acting with the consent of the individual affected. See Malcolm Murray, The Moral Wager (New York: Springer, 2007), esp. chap. 6.
-
(2007)
The Moral Wager
-
-
Murray, M.1
-
12
-
-
0004274311
-
-
(New York: Oxford University Press)
-
David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), 205.
-
(1986)
Morals by Agreement
, pp. 205
-
-
Gauthier, D.1
-
14
-
-
77952606580
-
-
There is some dispute about Locke's intentions here. But in saying "God, who hath given the World to Men in common . . ." (Second Treatise of Civil Government, sec. 26), he certainly leaves the impression that everyone has a claim to the land, one which needs to be overturned by argument (which he tries to provide)
-
There is some dispute about Locke's intentions here. But in saying "God, who hath given the World to Men in common . . ." (Second Treatise of Civil Government, sec. 26), he certainly leaves the impression that everyone has a claim to the land, one which needs to be overturned by argument (which he tries to provide).
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
77952614620
-
-
(New York: E. P. Dutton) chap. XII
-
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (New York: E. P. Dutton, 1950), chap. XII, p. 107.
-
(1950)
Leviathan
, pp. 107
-
-
Hobbes, T.1
-
16
-
-
84937563725
-
Liberty, property, and the libertarian idea
-
For further discussion, see, Malcolm Murray, ed., (Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing Co.), see also my comments on her arguments (ibid., 231-34)
-
For further discussion, see Ann Levey, "Liberty, Property, and the Libertarian Idea," in Malcolm Murray, ed., Liberty, Games, and Contracts (Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing Co., 2007), 147-56; see also my comments on her arguments (ibid., 231-34).
-
(2007)
Liberty, Games, and Contracts
, pp. 147-156
-
-
Levey, A.1
-
17
-
-
77952665063
-
-
Hobbes Leviathan chap. XIV
-
Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. XIV.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
77952619710
-
-
Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Government, sec. 6
-
Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Government, sec. 6.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
77952602215
-
-
Ibid., sec. 123
-
Ibid., sec. 123.
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0004218365
-
-
It has been popular to maintain that ownership is essentially a "bundle" of distinguishable rights, as if they had nothing to do with each other. For further discussion of this view, which I dismiss as a confusion, see, (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1988; republished, Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press), see esp. note 6 on p. 342
-
It has been popular to maintain that ownership is essentially a "bundle" of distinguishable rights, as if they had nothing to do with each other. For further discussion of this view, which I dismiss as a confusion, see Jan Narveson, The Libertarian Idea (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1988; republished, Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press, 2001), 64; see esp. note 6 on p. 342.
-
(2001)
The Libertarian Idea
, pp. 64
-
-
Narveson, J.1
-
21
-
-
0346040175
-
The invisible hand
-
I mean 'legally' in the sense of called for by some actual body of law. The general point of view of this essay is the classic one in this respect as well-that positive law is properly subordinate to morality, which has often enough, as by Aquinas, been dubbed 'moral law.' Possession used to be said to be nine points of the law; in recent times, however, public intervention is so pervasive that the need for sharply distinguishing positive law and moral law is now evident.19 See
-
I mean 'legally' in the sense of called for by some actual body of law. The general point of view of this essay is the classic one in this respect as well-that positive law is properly subordinate to morality, which has often enough, as by Aquinas, been dubbed 'moral law.' Possession used to be said to be nine points of the law; in recent times, however, public intervention is so pervasive that the need for sharply distinguishing positive law and moral law is now evident.19 See Jan Narveson, "The Invisible Hand," Journal of Business Ethics 46, no.3 (2003): 201-212
-
(2003)
Journal of Business Ethics
, vol.46
, Issue.3
, pp. 201-212
-
-
Narveson, J.1
-
22
-
-
0004238247
-
-
(New York: Oxford University Press), For Christman's definitions of L2 and L3, see ibid, 68 (emphasis in the original). Christman is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Pennsylvania State University
-
John Christman, The Myth of Property (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994), 73-74. For Christman's definitions of L2 and L3, see ibid., 68 (emphasis in the original). Christman is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Pennsylvania State University.
-
(1994)
The Myth of Property
, pp. 73-74
-
-
Christman, J.1
-
23
-
-
77952653235
-
-
The Province of British Columbia's Mineral Tenure Act of 2002 permits this. See, As a case in point, one Bruce Essington, who "lives in a tarp-covered bread truck on the side of Bluenose Mountain . . . has bought rights to about 150 acres of his neighbours' land. For $50." And "Essington was not charged for repeatedly scrawling 'free miners lic.' in blue paint on private property and removing 'For Sale' signs at the entrance of Kurt Yakelashek's driveway, for snooping around the property at night, or for leaving piles of beer cans around the grounds."
-
The Province of British Columbia's Mineral Tenure Act of 2002 permits this. See Kendyl Salcito, "'War Brewing' over Mining Rights in Rural BC," http://thetyee.ca/News/2006/ 06/14/MiningRights/. As a case in point, one Bruce Essington, who "lives in a tarp-covered bread truck on the side of Bluenose Mountain . . . has bought rights to about 150 acres of his neighbours' land. For $50." And "Essington was not charged for repeatedly scrawling 'free miners lic.' in blue paint on private property and removing 'For Sale' signs at the entrance of Kurt Yakelashek's driveway, for snooping around the property at night, or for leaving piles of beer cans around the grounds."
-
War Brewing' over Mining Rights in Rural BC
-
-
Salcito, K.1
-
24
-
-
70449453584
-
-
the prairie dog example is discussed on pp. 1-2
-
Freyfogle, On Private Property, 20; the prairie dog example is discussed on pp. 1-2.
-
On Private Property
, pp. 20
-
-
Freyfogle1
-
25
-
-
0004112075
-
-
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), Braithwaite was for a long time Professor of Moral Philosophy at Cambridge
-
R. B. Braithwaite, The Theory of Games as a Tool for the Moral Philosopher (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1954). Braithwaite was for a long time Professor of Moral Philosophy at Cambridge.
-
(1954)
The Theory of Games As A Tool for the Moral Philosopher
-
-
Braithwaite, R.B.1
-
26
-
-
84968502701
-
A set of five independent postulates for boolean algebras, with application to logical constants
-
Professor Sheffer discovered that all of the standard operations in the propositional calculus (or truth-functional logic) can be defined in terms of the function that amounts to "not p and q," nowadays referred to as the 'NAND' operator, short for 'not both . . . and. . . .' In fact, Charles Sanders Peirce discovered this thirty years earlier, but did not publish it. Sheffer's "discovery" (which there is no reason to think he plagiarized from Peirce) was published in 1913.
-
Professor Sheffer discovered that all of the standard operations in the propositional calculus (or truth-functional logic) can be defined in terms of the function that amounts to "not p and q," nowadays referred to as the 'NAND' operator, short for 'not both . . . and. . . .' In fact, Charles Sanders Peirce discovered this thirty years earlier, but did not publish it. Sheffer's "discovery" (which there is no reason to think he plagiarized from Peirce) was published in 1913. H. M. Sheffer, "A Set of Five Independent Postulates for Boolean Algebras, with Application to Logical Constants," Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 14 (1913): 481-488
-
(1913)
Transactions of the American Mathematical Society
, vol.14
, pp. 481-488
-
-
Sheffer, H.M.1
-
27
-
-
85055307563
-
Common property in anarcho-capitalism
-
(Spring), Holcombe is DeVoe Moore Professor of Economics at Florida State University
-
Randall Holcombe, "Common Property in Anarcho-Capitalism," Journal of Libertarian Studies 19, no.2 (Spring 2005): 3-26. Holcombe is DeVoe Moore Professor of Economics at Florida State University.
-
(2005)
Journal of Libertarian Studies
, vol.19
, Issue.2
, pp. 3-26
-
-
Holcombe, R.1
-
28
-
-
85055307563
-
Common property in anarcho-capitalism
-
Ibid.
-
Randall Holcombe, "Common Property in Anarcho-Capitalism," Journal of Libertarian Studies 19, no.2, (2005) Ibid., 3.
-
(2005)
Journal of Libertarian Studies
, vol.19
, Issue.2
, pp. 3
-
-
Holcombe, R.1
-
29
-
-
85055307563
-
Common property in anarcho-capitalism
-
Ibid.
-
Randall Holcombe, "Common Property in Anarcho-Capitalism," Journal of Libertarian Studies 19, no.2, (2005) Ibid., 5.
-
(2005)
Journal of Libertarian Studies
, vol.19
, Issue.2
, pp. 5
-
-
Holcombe, R.1
-
30
-
-
85055307563
-
Common property in anarcho-capitalism
-
Ibid.
-
Randall Holcombe, "Common Property in Anarcho-Capitalism," Journal of Libertarian Studies 19, no.2, (2005), Ibid., 8.
-
(2005)
Journal of Libertarian Studies
, vol.19
, Issue.2
, pp. 8
-
-
Holcombe, R.1
-
31
-
-
85055307563
-
Common property in anarcho-capitalism
-
Ibid.
-
Randall Holcombe, "Common Property in Anarcho-Capitalism," Journal of Libertarian Studies 19, no.2, (2005), Ibid., 3-4.
-
(2005)
Journal of Libertarian Studies
, vol.19
, Issue.2
, pp. 3-4
-
-
Holcombe, R.1
|