메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 61, Issue 4, 2010, Pages 917-968

The contested commitments of property

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77952540057     PISSN: 00178322     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (33)

References (355)
  • 1
    • 68949093633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A statement of progressive property
    • Along with Professor Alexander, the Statement was written by Eduardo M. Peñalver, Joseph William Singer, and Laura S. Underkuffler
    • On progressivism generally, see Gregory S. Alexander et al., A Statement of Progressive Property, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 743 (2009). Along with Professor Alexander, the Statement was written by Eduardo M. Peñalver, Joseph William Singer, and Laura S. Underkuffler.
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 743
    • Alexander, G.S.1
  • 2
    • 77952521365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For reasons described infra note 12
    • For reasons described infra note 12,
  • 3
    • 77952483699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra Part LB.
    • Include Jedediah Purdy among the progressive scholars. The specific claims of progressive scholarship are examined infra Part LB.
  • 4
    • 46149109280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Demystifying the right to exclude: Of property, inviolability, and automatic injunctions
    • 596
    • See, e.g., Shyamkrishna Balganesh, Demystifying the Right to Exclude: Of Property, Inviolability, and Automatic Injunctions, 31 HARV. J.L. A PUB. POL'Y 593, 596 (2008) ("The idea of exclusion, in one form or the other, tends to inform almost any understanding of property, whether private, public, or community.");
    • (2008) Harv. J.L. A Pub. Pol'y , vol.31 , pp. 593
    • Balganesh, S.1
  • 5
    • 77952488631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • June 9 (unpublished manuscript), available at
    • Hanoch Dagan, Exclusion and Inclusion in Property 8 (June 9, 2009) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1416580.
    • (2009) Exclusion and Inclusion in Property , pp. 8
    • Dagan, H.1
  • 6
    • 77952478827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 2
    • "Exclusion is in vogue in property discourse." Id. at 2;
  • 7
    • 77952477725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • June (unpublished manuscript, on file with the Hastings Law Journal)
    • see also Elizabeth M. Glazer, Property's Contingent Right to Exclude I (June 2009) (unpublished manuscript, on file with the Hastings Law Journal) ("Property law's right to exclude has taken on a life of its own.").
    • (2009) Property's Contingent Right to Exclude
    • Glazer, E.M.1
  • 8
    • 77952482517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part I.A.
    • See infra Part I.A.
  • 9
    • 68949122323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The complex core of property
    • 1070
    • Progressive theorists do not argue that exclusion is irrelevant to or trivial in property law, but rather that exclusion does not play the defining role suggested by information theorists. See, e.g., Gregory S. Alexander, Reply, The Complex Core of Property, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 1063, 1070 (2009) ("The core of ownership is more complex than the right to exclude standing alone.");
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 1063
    • Alexander, G.S.1
  • 10
    • 77952537165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dagan, supra note 2, at 8
    • Dagan, supra note 2, at 8 ("[E]xclusion or exclusivity can exhaust the meaning of property and thus be properly described at its core only if we set aside, somewhat arbitrarily, large parts of what constitutes property law....");
  • 11
    • 77952486315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Glazer, supra note 2
    • Glazer, supra note 2;
  • 13
    • 77952487085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TORONTO L.J. 275, 277-78 (2008)
    • TORONTO L.J. 275, 277-78 (2008);
  • 14
    • 0004575044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • No right to exclude: Public accommodations and private property
    • 1295
    • see also Joseph William Singer, No Right to Exclude: Public Accommodations and Private Property, 90 Nw. U. L. REV. 1283, 1295 (1996).
    • (1996) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.90 , pp. 1283
    • Singer, J.W.1
  • 15
    • 34250678122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intellectual property as property: Delineating entitlements in information
    • 1745
    • Information and progressive theorists have explicitly debated one another over this issue. Compare Henry E. Smith, Intellectual Property as Property: Delineating Entitlements in Information, 116 YALE L.J. 1742, 1745 (2007) ("The exclusion strategy protects rights-holders' interests in the use of resources indirectly, by using a simple signal for violations. The prototypical example is trespass to land...."),
    • (2007) Yale L.J. , vol.116 , pp. 1742
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 16
    • 68949178259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The social-obligation norm in american property law
    • 775-810
    • with Gregory S. Alexander, The Social-Obligation Norm in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 745, 775-810 (2009) (describing a variety of property doctrines that are not based on exclusion and that instantiate social obligation norms).
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 745
    • Alexander, G.S.1
  • 17
    • 77952505631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Alexander, supra note 5
    • It is not clear that progressive theorists would have chosen the core/periphery metaphor had information theorists not emphasized it so heavily. See generally Alexander, supra note 5.
  • 18
    • 0348199091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "Bundle of rights" picture of property
    • 714
    • See J.E. Penner, The "Bundle of Rights" Picture of Property, 43 UCLA L. REV. 711, 714 (1996).
    • (1996) Ucla L. Rev. , vol.43 , pp. 711
    • Penner, J.E.1
  • 19
    • 0004057243 scopus 로고
    • Yale Univ. Press
    • Among other problems, it conflicts with what Bruce Ackerman calls the "Ordinary Observer's" understanding of property, rooted in "the ordinary talk of non-lawyers," see BRUCE A. ACKERMAN, PRIVATE PROPERTY AND THE CONSTITUTION 10 (Yale Univ. Press 1977), and with what Joan Williams calls the "intuitive image," which emphasizes property's "absolutism,"
    • (1977) Private Property and the Constitution , pp. 10
    • Ackerman, B.A.1
  • 20
    • 22444453649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rhetoric of property
    • 280-95
    • see Joan Williams, The Rhetoric of Property, 83 IOWA L. REV. 277, 280-95 (1998).
    • (1998) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.83 , pp. 277
    • Williams, J.1
  • 21
    • 77952481771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Penner, supra note 7, at 714
    • It has been attacked as normatively empty, see Penner, supra note 7, at 714 ("[T]he bundle of rights... schema [does not] suggest any clear methodology for dealing with property issues."),
  • 22
    • 0005289458 scopus 로고
    • Chix nix bundle-o-stix: A feminist critique of the disaggregation of property
    • 243
    • as incoherent, see Jeanne L. Schroeder, Chix Nix Bundle-O-Stix: A Feminist Critique of the Disaggregation of Property, 93 MICH. L. REV. 239, 243 (1994) ("[A]though its proponents usually present the 'bundle of sticks' metaphor as an alternative to the 'property as thing' metaphor, the former is in fact merely a variation of the latter."),
    • (1994) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.93 , pp. 239
    • Schroeder, J.L.1
  • 23
    • 0000259630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The boundaries of private property
    • 1165
    • and as dysfunctional, see Michael A. Heller, The Boundaries of Private Property, 108 YALE L.J. 1163, 1165 (1999) (noting the potential of the bundle theory to create overly fragmented anticommons property).
    • (1999) Yale L.J. , vol.108 , pp. 1163
    • Heller, M.A.1
  • 24
    • 77952479650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Finally, as noted infra note 129
    • Finally, as noted infra note 129, the "bundle of rights" theory potentially renders every "stick" in the bundle a separate property interest, capable of being "taken" in the Fifth Amendment sense by government regulation that reduces or eliminates it.
  • 25
    • 0001845692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Optimal standardization in the law of property: The numerus clausus principle
    • See generally Thomas W. Merrill & Henry E. Smith, Optimal Standardization in the Law of Property: The Numerus Clausus Principle, 110 YALE L.J. I (2000).
    • (2000) Yale L.J. , vol.110
    • Merrill, T.W.1    Smith, H.E.2
  • 26
    • 77952485155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As explained infra Part III.A, progressive theorists focus less on the duties of nonowners to owners
    • As explained infra Part III.A, progressive theorists focus less on the duties of nonowners to owners (which are central in information theories) and more on owners' duties to nonowners and other members of their communities. Putting this another way, information theorists tend to be concerned with "negative" duties, such as duties to "keep off." Progressive theorists are concerned, in contrast with whether owners might owe "positive" duties, such as a duty to permit access.
  • 27
    • 77952488989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part I.A.
    • See infra Part I.A.
  • 28
    • 77952536038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Alexander, supra note 5, at 748
    • Without purporting to be exhaustive, I survey theories offered by Gregory Alexander, Eduardo Peñalver, Jedediah Purdy, and Joseph Singer. See generally Alexander, supra note 5, at 748 (flourishing);
  • 29
    • 68949134356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Land virtues
    • Eduardo M. Peñalver, Land Virtues, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 821 (2009) (virtue);
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 821
    • Peñalver, E.M.1
  • 30
    • 58149401835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democratic estates: Property law in a free and democratic society
    • 1047
    • Joseph William Singer, Democratic Estates: Property Law in a Free and Democratic Society, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 1009, 1047 (2009) (democracy);
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 1009
    • Singer, J.W.1
  • 31
    • 29844436956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A freedom-promoting approach to property: A renewed tradition for new debates
    • [hereinafter Purdy, A FreedomPromoting Approach]
    • Jedediah Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach to Property: A Renewed Tradition for New Debates, 72 U. CHI. L. REV. 1237 (2005) [hereinafter Purdy, A FreedomPromoting Approach];
    • (2005) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.72 , pp. 1237
    • Purdy, J.1
  • 32
    • 33947168295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • People as resources: Recruitment and reciprocity in the freedom-promoting approach to property
    • [hereinafter Purdy, People as Resources] (respect for humanity of others)
    • Jedediah Purdy, People as Resources: Recruitment and Reciprocity in the Freedom-Promoting Approach to Property, 56 DUKE L.J. 1047 (2007) [hereinafter Purdy, People as Resources] (respect for humanity of others).
    • (2007) Duke L.J. , vol.56 , pp. 1047
    • Purdy, J.1
  • 33
    • 77952501939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As explained supra note 1, Purdy did not sign the Statement of Progressive Property. Nonetheless, his work reflects many progressive themes, and he is described by at least one of the Statement's signatories as a fellow progressive.
    • As explained supra note 1, Purdy did not sign the Statement of Progressive Property. Nonetheless, his work reflects many progressive themes, and he is described by at least one of the Statement's signatories as a fellow progressive.
  • 34
    • 77952507213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Singer, supra.
    • See Singer, supra. I take no position in this Article as to whether the theories offered as part of the statement are actually progressive in the political or historical sense; I simply adopt the authors' own label.
  • 35
    • 77949833129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The morality of property
    • 1850 [hereinafter Merrill & Smith, Morality of Property]
    • Thomas W. Merrill & Henry E. Smith, The Morality of Property, 48 WM. A MARY L. REV. 1849, 1850 (2007) [hereinafter Merrill & Smith, Morality of Property]. The term "things" as used by information theorists refers to intangible as well as tangible property.
    • (2007) Wm. A Mary L. Rev. , vol.48 , pp. 1849
    • Merrill, T.W.1    Smith, H.E.2
  • 36
    • 10844258847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property and property rules
    • 1754 [hereinafter Smith, Property]
    • See Henry E. Smith, Property and Property Rules, 79 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1719, 1754 (2004) [hereinafter Smith, Property] (making no distinction between tangible and intangible things).
    • (2004) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.79 , pp. 1719
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 37
    • 69849110864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-help and the nature of property
    • 79
    • Henry E. Smith, Self-Help and the Nature of Property, 1 J.L. ECON. & POL'Y 69, 79 (2005).
    • (2005) J.L. Econ. & Pol'y , vol.1 , pp. 69
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 38
    • 0005303148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What happened to property in law and economics?
    • 387 [hereinafter Merrill & Smith, What Happened to Property]
    • Thomas W. Merrill & Henry E. Smith, What Happened to Property in Law and Economics?, III YALE L.J. 357, 387 (2001) [hereinafter Merrill & Smith, What Happened to Property] (footnote omitted);
    • (2001) Yale L.J. , vol.3 , pp. 357
    • Merrill, T.W.1    Smith, H.E.2
  • 39
    • 0142231834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The language of property: Form, context, and audience
    • 1147 [hereinafter Smith, Language of Property]
    • see also Henry E. Smith, The Language of Property: Form, Context, and Audience, 55 STAN. L. REV. 1105, 1147 (2003) [hereinafter Smith, Language of Property] ("[P]otential violators' information costs bear on the design of the law. Property presents a simple message to the outside world....[T]he dutyholder only needs to know that he does not own the asset in order to know that he must keep out. This keeps informational demands on the dutyholder to a minimnm."(footnotes omitted)).
    • (2003) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.55 , pp. 1105
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 40
    • 77952478826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 26-42
    • For more on the "measurement costs" faced by those seeking to avoid violating others' property rights, see Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 26-42.
  • 41
    • 77952468795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 77
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 77.
  • 42
    • 0002071502 scopus 로고
    • The problem of social cost
    • This observation derives from Coase's well-known work. See R. H. Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, 3 J.L. A ECON. I (1960).
    • (1960) J.L. A Econ. , vol.3
    • Coase, R.H.1
  • 43
    • 77952523390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 78
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 78.
  • 44
    • 77952479651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id. (footnotes omitted);
  • 45
    • 77952503313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1754
    • see also Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1754 ("Protection of a large and indefinite class of uses by delineating a thing and giving the owner a right to exclude all others from the thing is a strategy well suited to situations in which it is not economical to decide first-order questions of use on a use-by-use basis.").
  • 46
    • 77952531352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 79
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 79.
  • 47
    • 77952508402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 79-80, 87-89
    • Id. at 79-80, 87-89;
  • 48
    • 77952490175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1755-58
    • see Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1755-58.
  • 49
    • 0041669218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exclusion versus governance: Two strategies for delineating property rights
    • For an explication of the basics of exclusion and governance, see Henry E. Smith, Exclusion Versus Governance: Two Strategies for Delineating Property Rights, 31 J. LEGAL STUD. 453 (2002).
    • (2002) J. Legal Stud. , vol.31 , pp. 453
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 50
    • 0345975442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The property/contract interface
    • 797
    • Thomas W. Merrill & Henry E. Smith, The Property/Contract Interface, 101 COLUM. L. REV. 773, 797(2001).
    • (2001) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.101 , pp. 773
    • Merrill, T.W.1    Smith, H.E.2
  • 51
    • 77952500066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 798
    • Id. at 798.
  • 52
    • 77952517956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 53
    • 77952526629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 794
    • Id. at 794.
  • 54
    • 84962313031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15
    • Smith, Language of Property, supra note 15, at 1125 ("The communication of legal relations is subject to a tradeoff between intensiveness and extensiveness of information: For the same cost, one can communicate a lot to a small, close-knit audience or a little to a large, anonymous audience.").
    • Language of Property , pp. 1125
    • Smith1
  • 55
    • 77952520980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 802
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 802.
  • 56
    • 77952523780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 803
    • Id. at 803.
  • 57
    • 77952504070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 768.
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 768. The relationship between Alexander's notion of human flourishing and the notion of human flourishing famously proposed by Margaret Radin in her article Property and Personhood, is not entirely clear, but Alexander explicitly locates his vision in the "Aristotelian tradition."
  • 58
    • 77952506375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 760-68
    • See Alexander, supra note 5, at 760-68;
  • 59
    • 0000542896 scopus 로고
    • Property and personhood
    • Margaret Jane Radin, Property and Personhood, 34 STAN. L. REV. 957 (1982).
    • (1982) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.34 , pp. 957
    • Radin, M.J.1
  • 60
    • 77952534984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 5, at 762
    • See Alexander, supra note 5, at 762
  • 64
    • 77952527452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 764
    • Id. at 764.
  • 65
    • 77952530949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 765
    • Id. at 765.
  • 66
    • 77952500816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 766
    • Id. at 766.
  • 67
    • 77952467659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 774
    • Id. at 774.
  • 68
    • 77952515134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 776
    • Id. at 776.
  • 69
    • 77952467284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 805
    • Id. at 805.
  • 70
    • 77952520623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 819
    • Id. at 819.
  • 71
    • 77952489379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 864
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 864.
  • 72
    • 77952496265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 73
    • 77952514400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 876
    • Id. at 876.
  • 74
    • 77952468417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 867-68
    • Id. at 867-68.
  • 75
    • 77952510485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 868
    • Id. at 868.
  • 76
    • 77952469573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 868-69
    • Id. at 868-69 (footnotes omitted).
  • 77
    • 77952511909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id at 869
    • Id at 869.
  • 78
    • 77952519085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 876
    • Id. at 876.
  • 79
    • 77952492041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 871
    • Id. at 871.
  • 80
    • 77952486314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 81
    • 77952478825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 872
    • Peñalver cites nondiscrimination norms embodied in the Civil Rights Act of 1964 as "contribut[ing] to dramatic changes in racial attitudes." Id. at 872.
  • 82
    • 77952514772 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 83
    • 77952499395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • For example, "environmental statutes or regulations... can help spread the word about best practices to landowners already inclined to act responsibly but lacking information about the remote consequences of their behavior." Id.
  • 84
    • 77952482918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 880
    • Id. at 880.
  • 85
    • 77952536037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 882
    • Id. at 882.
  • 86
    • 77952502937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 277 A.2d 369, 374-75 (N.J. 1971)
    • 277 A.2d 369, 374-75 (N.J. 1971) (holding that entry onto a farmer's land to offer services to migrant workers housed thereon was not trespass, despite the fact that the owner objected to the entry);
  • 87
    • 77952539621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Peñalver, supra note 12, at 883
    • see also Peñalver, supra note 12, at 883.
  • 88
    • 0036058106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The expressive transparency of property
    • [hereinafter Baron, Expressive Transparency of Property]
    • Jane B. Baron, The Expressive Transparency of Property, 102 COLUM. L. REV. 208 (2002) [hereinafter Baron, Expressive Transparency of Property];
    • (2002) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.102 , pp. 208
    • Baron, J.B.1
  • 89
    • 73449137763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property and "No property"
    • [hereinafter Baron, Property and "No Property"]
    • Jane B. Baron, Property and "No Property", 42 Hous. L. REV. 1425 (2006) [hereinafter Baron, Property and "No Property"];
    • (2006) Hous. L. Rev. , vol.42 , pp. 1425
    • Baron, J.B.1
  • 90
    • 21344464214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property as the keystone right?
    • Carol M. Rose, Property as the Keystone Right?, 71 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 329 (1996).
    • (1996) Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 329
    • Rose, C.M.1
  • 94
    • 77952479649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 95
    • 77952472616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1242
    • Id. at 1242 ("Today [the] theoretical underpinnings [of the freedom-promoting conception] are experiencing a revival, most prominently in the thought of Nobel laureate economist Amartya Sen.").
  • 96
    • 77952481228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1243
    • Id. at 1243.
  • 97
    • 77952506374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1244
    • Id. at 1244.
  • 98
    • 77952522553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1244-45
    • Id. at 1244-45.
  • 99
    • 77952520979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1285
    • Id. at 1285.
  • 101
    • 77952516696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1060-68
    • Id. at 1060-68.
  • 102
    • 77952515540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1068-79
    • Id. at 1068-79;
  • 104
  • 106
    • 77952515133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 107
    • 77952530948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1046-47
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1046-47.
  • 108
    • 77952492788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1047
    • Id. at 1047 (emphasis added).
  • 109
    • 77952482516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1048
    • Id. at 1048.
  • 110
    • 77952504475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 111
    • 77952517201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1050
    • Id. at 1050.
  • 112
    • 77952528243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1050-51
    • Id. at 1050-51.
  • 113
    • 77952538027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1051-52
    • Id. at 1051-52.
  • 114
    • 77952480038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1052
    • Id. at 1052.
  • 115
    • 77952513542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1052-53
    • Id. at 1052-53.
  • 116
    • 77952520260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 192-95
    • See infra text accompanying notes 192-95.
  • 117
    • 77952527451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dagan, supra note 2, at 2
    • Dagan, supra note 2, at 2 ("The bundle-of-sticks picture of property... had for decades been regarded as the conventional wisdom.").
  • 119
    • 50949129526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6th ed.
    • See, e.g., JESSE DUKEMINIER ET AL., PROPERTY 81 (6th ed. 2006) ("[T]he abstraction we call property is multi- not monolithic. It consists of a number of disparate rights, a 'bundle' of them....").
    • (2006) Property , pp. 81
    • Dukeminier, J.1
  • 120
    • 77952518687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Heller, supra note 8, at 1192 n.150
    • Heller, supra note 8, at 1192 n.150 (reporting the increase in the number of cases using the term, from four state and federal cases before 1940, to 775 cases between 1980 and 1999, when Heller's article appeared).
  • 121
    • 77952478824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See sources cited supra note 8
    • See sources cited supra note 8.
  • 122
    • 77952526242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DUKEMINIER ET AL., supra note 79, at 81 n.40
    • DUKEMINIER ET AL., supra note 79, at 81 n.40.
  • 123
    • 0040521206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4th ed.
    • For example, owners have the power to use what they own, to exclude others from it, to sell it, to devise it, to grant others rights to use it, and so on. See, e.g., JOSEPH WILLIAM SINGER, PROPERTY LAW: RULES, POLICIES, AND PRACTICES 505 (4th ed. 2006). ("An owner of a fee simple interest in real property has the present right to possess and use the property, to sell it or give it away, and the right to devise it by will or leave it to her heirs.").
    • (2006) Property Law: Rules, Policies, and Practices , pp. 505
    • Singer, J.W.1
  • 124
    • 77952536036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the sense of being an agglomeration of separable powers, property can be said to be a "bundle of rights." In this usage, the "bundle" metaphor emphasizes the multiplicity of powers owners have. They can give and sell; they can keep others out and set the terms on which others can enter
    • In the sense of being an agglomeration of separable powers, property can be said to be a "bundle of rights." In this usage, the "bundle" metaphor emphasizes the multiplicity of powers owners have. They can give and sell; they can keep others out and set the terms on which others can enter.
  • 125
    • 77952490832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus, different persons might own different physical interests in the same land, with separate persons owning the mineral rights, the surface rights, or the air rights in a given parcel of land
    • Thus, different persons might own different physical interests in the same land, with separate persons owning the mineral rights, the surface rights, or the air rights in a given parcel of land.
  • 126
    • 77952476143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SINGER, supra note 83, at 493
    • Thus, one person may own the right to present possession, and a different person own the right to possession in the future, as is true in the case of leaseholds and life estates followed by remainders. SINGER, supra note 83, at 493.
  • 127
    • 77952513947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • In addition, multiple people may own interests in the same property at the same time, via joint tenancy or tenancy in common. Id.
  • 128
    • 0004130870 scopus 로고
    • Take the example of a condominium owner who "might have a 'fee simple' interest in her unit's living space, an exclusive easement in her balcony area and parking space, tenancy in common in the hallways and the swimming pool, defined participatory rights in the community's governance, and so forth." CAROL M. ROSE, PROPERTY AND PERSUASION: ESSAYS ON THE HISTORY, THEORY, AND RHETORIC OF OWNERSHIP 280 (1994). The condo owner's rights are the sum (or "bundle") of these separate interests.
    • (1994) Property and Persuasion: Essays on the History, Theory, and Rhetoric of Ownership , pp. 280
    • Rose, C.M.1
  • 129
    • 77952472615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 282
    • Id. at 282.
  • 130
    • 77952483313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 280
    • The metaphor might seem problematic insofar as it is inattentive to, or may even weaken, "the sense that groupings of property rights might be interconnected and interdependent." Id. at 280;
  • 131
    • 0035982093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The reconstitution of property: Property as a web of interests
    • 282
    • see also Craig Anthony (Tony) Arnold, The Reconstitution of Property: Property as a Web of Interests, 26 HARV. ENVTL. L. REV. 281, 282 (2002) ("In this Article, I articulate a new understanding of property as a web of interests, not a bundle of rights.").
    • (2002) Harv. Envtl. L. Rev. , vol.26-281
    • Arnold, C.A.1
  • 132
    • 77952500453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ROSE, supra note 86, at 282
    • Yet, its disaggregative tendencies notwithstanding, "the bundle of sticks is not just sticks but a bundle," and thus "the bundle metaphor acts at least as much to 'package' the various elements as it does to give an impression of their separateness." ROSE, supra note 86, at 282.
  • 133
    • 77952535649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15
    • See, e.g., Merrill & Smith, What Happened to Property, supra note 15, at 365 ("Hohfeld did not use the metaphor 'bundle of rights' to describe property. But his theory of jural opposites and correlatives, together with his effort to reduce in rem rights to clusters of in personam rights, provided the intellectual justification for this metaphor.....");
    • What Happened to Property , pp. 365
    • Merrill1    Smith2
  • 135
    • 77952506022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U. TORONTO L.J. 117, 120 (1988)
    • U. TORONTO L.J. 117, 120 (1988) ("[S]ince the writings of W.N. Hohfeld it has been generally agreed that 'property' refers to legal interests that exist only as between persons, in respect of things." (footnote omitted)).
  • 136
    • 0002953848 scopus 로고
    • Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning
    • 24
    • Hohfeld did write that "all legal interests are 'incorporeal'- consisting, as they do, of more or less limited aggregates of abstract legal relations." Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 YALE L.J. 16, 24 (1913).
    • (1913) Yale L.J. , vol.23 , pp. 16
    • Hohfeld, W.N.1
  • 137
    • 77952488988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g.. SINGER, supra note 83, at 2
    • See, e.g.. SINGER, supra note 83, at 2 ("It is sometimes thought that property concerns power over things. One problem with this definition is that many property rights do not concern 'things' at all, but intangible resources, such as copyright or interests in an ongoing business.");
  • 139
    • 77952508401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 13 and accompanying text
    • Of course, intangibles can be "things." See supra note 13 and accompanying text.
  • 140
    • 77952534151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see infra Part II.B.
    • On historical changes in property forms and the conclusions some have drawn from those changes, see infra Part II.B.
  • 141
    • 77952503312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ALEXANDER, supra note 89, at 320
    • ALEXANDER, supra note 89, at 320.
  • 142
    • 77952510095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOSEPH WILLIAM SINGER, ENTITLEMENT: THE PARADOXES OF PROPERTY 10 (2000) ("The right to exclude nonowners, for example, regulates nonowners by requiring them to stay off the owner's property.").
    • (2000) Entitlement: The Paradoxes of Property , vol.10
    • Singer, J.W.1
  • 143
    • 77952506373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hohfeld, supra note 88, at 21
    • See Hohfeld, supra note 88, at 21 (describing property as an "aggregate of legal relations" appertaining to a "physical object").
  • 144
    • 77952494342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Property was simply a "striking example" of the "ambiguity and looseness of our legal terminology." Id.
  • 145
    • 77952518686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 24-25
    • Though many of Hohfeld's illustrations involved property, he noted that in the field of contracts as well there was comparable "ambiguity and confusion." Id. at 24-25.
  • 146
    • 77952517200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 28
    • Id. at 28.
  • 147
    • 77952506857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ACKERMAN, supra note 8, at 26
    • ACKERMAN, supra note 8, at 26.
  • 148
    • 77952520259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Penner, supra note 7, at 801
    • Penner, supra note 7, at 801;
  • 149
    • 77952474927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also id. at 808.
    • see also id. at 808.
  • 150
    • 0347678207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two-and three-dimensional property rights
    • 1086
    • Emily Sherwin, Two- and Three-Dimensional Property Rights, 29 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 1075, 1086 (1997);
    • (1997) Ariz. St. L.J. , vol.29 , pp. 1075
    • Sherwin, E.1
  • 151
    • 77952492040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schroeder, supra note 8, at 292
    • see also Schroeder, supra note 8, at 292 ("Unfortunately, [Hohfeld] missed the point that property is a relationship between subjects that is mediated through an object.").
  • 152
    • 77952519083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 243
    • Schroeder argues that "although its proponents usually present the 'bundle of sticks' metaphor as an alternative to the 'property as thing' metaphor, the former is in fact merely a variation of the latter." Id. at 243 (footnote omitted).
  • 154
    • 77952477724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 360
    • Id. at 360 (emphasis added).
  • 155
    • 77952539234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 78-79
    • On the in rem nature of property rights, see, for example, Smith, supra note 14, at 78-79,
  • 156
    • 77952540411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 786-87
    • and Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 786-87.
  • 157
    • 77952525289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 787
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 787.
  • 158
    • 77952517199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Put another way, citizens A, B, and C have exactly the same duties vis-à-vis an owner of a thing as citizens X, Y, and Z. Id.
  • 159
    • 77952471855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 16-27
    • On the importance of exclusion, see supra text accompanying notes 16-27.
  • 160
    • 77952522940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 787
    • See Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 787.
  • 161
    • 77952471470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Merrill & Smith, supra note 9
    • See generally Merrill & Smith, supra note 9.
  • 162
    • 77952522552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 35
    • Id. at 35 (describing the way in which, like language, the standardized building blocks can be combined in complex ways).
  • 163
    • 77952504474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 8.
    • See id. at 8.
  • 164
    • 77952500814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • When property rights are created, third parties must expend time and resources to determine the attributes of these rights, both to avoid violating them and to acquire them from present holders. The existence of unusual property rights increases the cost of processing information about all property rights. Those creating or transferring idiosyncratic property rights cannot always be expected to take these increases in measurement costs fully into account, making them a true externality. Standardization of property rights reduces these measurement costs. Id.
  • 166
    • 77952479211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 36
    • In a way, the information theorists' antagonism toward the "bundle of rights" metaphor seems odd, because they concede that the basic, building-block forms delineated by the numerus clausus principle- the common law estates-are in a real sense bundles of rights. See, e.g., Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 36 (referring to common law estates as the "set of property rights bundles.") That is, even those who contend that standardization is effectively mandatory do not dispute that the standard packages are bundles. Their issue with the "bundle of rights" metaphor is mainly with its tacit or implicit suggestion that the bundles can be altered at will.
  • 168
    • 77952529856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1032
    • See, e.g., Singer, supra note 12, at 1032 ("[T]he legal realist approach had its own problems. Taken to its extreme, the bundle-of-rights idea could suggest that property has no meaning whatsoever as a legal category....").
  • 169
    • 77952485154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 1049
    • See, e.g., id. at 1049 ("[T]he democratic approach to property understands property not merely as an individual right but a social system.").
  • 170
    • 77952490569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 4, at 1461
    • Singer, supra note 4, at 1461.
  • 171
    • 77952483698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ACKERMAN, supra note 8, at 10
    • See ACKERMAN, supra note 8, at 10.
  • 172
    • 77952473753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 26
    • Id. at 26.
  • 173
    • 77952502314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Singer, supra note 4, at 1453
    • See Singer, supra note 4, at 1453 ("[T]he classical conception of property... is premised on the notion that property rights identify an 'owner' who has title to a set of valued resources with a presumption of full power over those resources.").
  • 174
    • 77952469572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SINGER, supra note 91, at 3
    • In Entitlement, Singer refers to this view as the "ownership" model. See SINGER, supra note 91, at 3.
  • 175
    • 77952482917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Under the ownership model, as under the classical model, we "typically presume that the owner has, not just one or two powers, but all [the] powers-a full bundle-over the property." Id.
  • 176
    • 77952502764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SINGER, supra note 91, at 9
    • SINGER, supra note 91, at 9;
  • 177
    • 77952524537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Singer, supra note 4, at 1459-60
    • see Singer, supra note 4, at 1459-60.
  • 178
    • 77952506372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • After the flood: Equality and humanity in property regimes
    • 272
    • See, e.g., Joseph William Singer, After the Flood: Equality and Humanity in Property Regimes, 52 LOY. L. REV. 243, 272 (2006). [O]wnership of property includes a bundle of rights and it is often the case that some of those rights are limited to protect the legitimate interests of others. In effect, this means that some of those sticks in the bundle are in fact owned by others and not the person we conventionally think of as the owner of the property.
    • (2006) Loy. L. Rev. , vol.52 , pp. 243
    • Singer, J.W.1
  • 179
    • 3042734240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exclusion and property rules in the law of nuisance
    • 984 [hereinafter Smith, Exclusion and Property Rules]
    • 117- Henry E. Smith, Exclusion and Property Rules in the Law of Nuisance, 90 VA. L. REV. 965, 984 (2004) [hereinafter Smith, Exclusion and Property Rules];
    • (2004) Va. L. Rev. , vol.90 , pp. 965
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 180
    • 77952472255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1728
    • see also Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1728 ("Property responds to uncertainty over uses by bundling uses together and delegating to the owner the choice of how to use the asset, thus avoiding the need to specify uses at any stage.").
  • 181
    • 77952537599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1051
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1051.
  • 182
    • 77952500065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1050
    • Id. at 1050;
  • 183
    • 0742323942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The craft of property
    • 1566-67
    • see also Hanoch Dagan, The Craft of Property, 91 CAL. L. REV. 1517, 1566-67 (2003) (arguing that communication costs do not fully explain the numerus clausus principle; rather, "limiting the number of property forms and standardizing their content facilitates the roles of property in consolidating expectations and expressing ideal forms of relationship").
    • (2003) Cal. L. Rev. , vol.91 , pp. 1517
    • Dagan, H.1
  • 184
    • 77952536764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1050. Progressive theorists are not indifferent to how property functions. Yet they focus less on property's mechanics-its "nuts and bolts," so to speak-than on the outcomes it produces
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1050. Progressive theorists are not indifferent to how property functions. Yet they focus less on property's mechanics-its "nuts and bolts," so to speak-than on the outcomes it produces.
  • 185
    • 77952481770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra text accompanying notes 146-62, 246-48
    • For further development of this point, see infra text accompanying notes 146-62, 246-48.
  • 187
    • 0346094958 scopus 로고
    • The twentieth-century revolution in family wealth transmission
    • 723
    • See John H. Langbein, The Twentieth-Century Revolution in Family Wealth Transmission, 86 MICH. L. REV. 722, 723 (1988).
    • (1988) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.86 , pp. 722
    • Langbein, J.H.1
  • 188
    • 77952492787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id
    • John Langbein tells this story to explain changes in inheritance law. See id.
  • 189
    • 77952486313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • As Langbein explains, "Into the eighteenth century, land was the dominant form of wealth." Id.
  • 190
    • 77952537164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • During this period, "wealth transmission from parents to children tended to center upon major items of patrimony such as the family farm or the family firm." Id.
  • 191
    • 77952485536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • But "technological forces" not only "broke up older familycentered modes of economic organization," they also "called forth two new forms of private-sector wealth": financial assets ("stocks, bonds, bank deposits, mutual fund shares, insurance contracts, and the like") and human capital. Id.
  • 192
    • 77952520978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 732-33
    • This change led to a "revolution" in family wealth transmission, a revolution driven by important changes in the form in which property is held. "In today's economic order," Langbein writes, it is "the new human capital rather than the old physical capital, that... advantages a child" and rescues him "from the harsh fate of being a mere laborer." Id. at 732-33.
  • 193
    • 77952511528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 743. Since human capital is transmitted inter vivos and since most wealth remaining after the education of children is annuitized, there is now much less for the probate system to do
    • Relatedly, "most parental wealth (apart from the parents' own human capital) now takes the form of financial assets," most particularly pension wealth, which, unlike the tangible assets of old, is consumed during the parents' own lifetimes via annuitization. Id. at 743. Since human capital is transmitted inter vivos and since most wealth remaining after the education of children is annuitized, there is now much less for the probate system to do.
  • 194
    • 77952530572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HORWITZ, supra note 121, at 156
    • HORWITZ, supra note 121, at 156.
  • 195
    • 0000200388 scopus 로고
    • The new property of the nineteenth century
    • 366
    • Kenneth J. Vandevelde, The New Property of the Nineteenth Century, 29 BUFF. L. REV. 325, 366 (1980).
    • (1980) Buff. L. Rev. , vol.29 , pp. 325
    • Vandevelde, K.J.1
  • 196
    • 77952535649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, at 385
    • As developed below, this view is often associated with legal realism. However, it is by no means confined to realists or their descendants. "Most modern economic accounts endow property with no distinctive character at all. Property rights are simply 'entitlements,' little empty boxes filled with a miscellany of use rights that operate in the background of a world consisting of nothing but in personam obligations." Merrill & Smith, What Happened to Property, supra note 15, at 385.
    • What Happened to Property
    • Merrill1    Smith2
  • 198
    • 77950631399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property 101: Is property a thing or a bundle?
    • 623
    • Eric R. Claeys, Property 101: Is Property a Thing or a Bundle?, 32 SEATTLE U. L. REV. 617, 623 (2009).
    • (2009) Seattle U. L. Rev. , vol.32 , pp. 617
    • Claeys, E.R.1
  • 199
    • 77952492405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SINGER, supra note 91, at 36, 68
    • In its broadest form, the claim here emphasizes the extent to which "private" property requires and depends on the state; without public protection, no one's property rights would be secure. This idea is at the center of much of Joseph Singer's work. See, e.g.. SINGER, supra note 91, at 36, 68;
  • 200
    • 77952540017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Things that we would like to take for granted: Minimum standards for the legal framework of a free and democratic society
    • Joseph William Singer, Things That We Would Like to Take for Granted: Minimum Standards for the Legal Framework of a Free and Democratic Society, 2 HARV. L. & POL'Y REV. 139 (2008).
    • (2008) Harv. L. & Pol'y Rev. , vol.2 , pp. 139
    • Singer, J.W.1
  • 201
    • 36749095897 scopus 로고
    • Bargaining, duress, and economic liberty
    • 626
    • This idea is often traced back to the legal realists-and Robert Hale in particular-who developed it to defend New Deal legislation against the charge that such legislation interfered with the operation of the free market. See Robert L. Hale, Bargaining, Duress, and Economic Liberty, 43 COLUM. L. REV. 603, 626 (1943).
    • (1943) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.43 , pp. 603
    • Hale, R.L.1
  • 202
    • 77952523779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id
    • The defense posited that there was nothing "free" about the market prior to regulation; basic rules of property, even such seemingly innocuous rules as those forbidding the use of goods without the owner's consent, invisibly "regulate" in favor of those who already happen to own goods. Different background rules about who can withhold what from whom would lead to different outcomes, but those different background rules would be no more "regulatory" than the rules that happened to be in place previously. See id.
  • 203
    • 77952520622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 52
    • The question thus is not whether the government can regulate, but in what ways or to what ends it will regulate. For a description of how this argument was meant to work, and why it has failed over time to gain the traction that might otherwise have been expected, see Baron, Expressive Transparency of Property, supra note 52, at 231-32.
    • Expressive Transparency of Property , pp. 231-232
    • Baron1
  • 204
    • 77952535649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15
    • See Merrill & Smith, What Happened to Property, supra note 15, at 365 ("[T]he motivation behind the realists' fascination with the bundle-of-rights conception was mainly political. They sought to undermine the notion that property is a natural right, and thereby smooth the way for activist state intervention in regulating and redistributing property.");
    • What Happened to Property , pp. 365
    • Merrill1    Smith2
  • 205
    • 77952531740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 77
    • see also Smith, supra note 14, at 77 ("The atomized bundle-of-rights picture of property makes the bundles the law provides look arbitrary and makes re-engineering the bundle seem attractive.").
  • 207
    • 77952483697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HORWITZ, supra note 121, at 160
    • One obvious difficulty with this view is its potential to conflict with the view of property emphasizing fragmentation. If, as earlier described, each separate "right" or "stick" in the property rights bundle is itself property (and is its own "bundle of rights"), then any regulatory action that eliminates or even just reduces the value of any individual right or stick arguably "takes" that fragmented property right. See HORWITZ, supra note 121, at 160 ("Th[e] process of abstracting the idea of property into market value was... dangerously over-inclusive [because] it made virtually every change in government policy that caused a decline in market value potentially a taking.....").
  • 208
    • 77952522149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 151
    • During the nineteenth century, Horwitz explains, "American courts came as close as they had ever had to saying that one had a property right to an unchanging world." Id. at 151.
  • 209
    • 77952503678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 801
    • Alexander argues that, in light of this problem, "[t]he whole bundle-of-rights metaphor ought to be abandoned." Alexander, supra note 5, at 801.
  • 210
    • 69849084250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Takings: An appreciative retrospective
    • 448
    • Yet the very fragmentation that creates the potential taking problem may, ironically, solve it. Even if the government "takes" some rights or sticks, other fragments will inevitably remain, and if "enough" remains, there is no taking after all. See Eric R. Claeys, Takings: An Appreciative Retrospective, 15 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 439, 448 (2006).
    • (2006) Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. , vol.15 , pp. 439
    • Claeys, E.R.1
  • 211
    • 77952475313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Because [the bundle-of-rights approach] treats different property claims as disaggregated rights, it expands the free action that legislators and regulators have to set policy. Once property is disaggregated, regulators can sort through particular rights claims piecemeal. Regulators may socialize a few owners' rights to satisfy the demands of legislative majorities while still leaving the owners with a substantial residue. Regulators can insert or remove different sticks in an owner's bag, but the owner still has "property" as long as she still has a bag and other sticks. Id.
  • 212
    • 77952489771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dagan, supra note 119, at 1532
    • See, e.g., Dagan, supra note 119, at 1532 ("The bundle of rights metaphor captures the truism that property is an artifact, a human creation that can be, and has been, modified in accordance with human needs and values.");
  • 213
    • 77952515539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weinrib, supra note 88, at 120-22
    • Weinrib, supra note 88, at 120-22 (emphasizing that the concept of property is "purposive" and that "it follows from the instrumental nature of property that the concept should not be a static one").
  • 214
    • 77952484453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 24
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 24.
  • 215
    • 77952533781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 23
    • Id. at 23.
  • 216
    • 77952475764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 11
    • 133- Id. at 11.
  • 217
    • 77952484454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 51
    • Id. at 51 ("Throughout history and across numerous legal systems, the provision of standards for the basic building blocks of the property system has been largely a government affair.").
  • 218
    • 77952469571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 58
    • Id. at 58.
  • 219
    • 77952540819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • By limiting courts to enforcing the status quo in terms of recognized property interests, the numerus clausus makes the courts an inhospitable forum for modifying existing forms of property or creating new ones. Consequently, parties who wish to secure changes in the pattern of available property rights must look elsewhere-most prominently, to the legislature. Id.
  • 220
    • 77952470723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hale, supra note 127, at 625.
    • Interestingly, Hale also argued that the legislature might be institutionally superior as a vehicle for the redistributional changes he envisioned. See Hale, supra note 127, at 625.
  • 221
    • 77952478131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 63
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 63.
  • 222
    • 77952488987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 16
    • Id. at 16.
  • 223
    • 77952468033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 40
    • Id. at 40.
  • 224
    • 77952467283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 69
    • Id. at 69;
  • 225
    • 77952502936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also id. at 61-68
    • see also id. at 61-68 (describing legislative decisionmaking's advantages in terms of "clarity, universality, comprehensiveness, stability, prospectivity, and implicit compensation").
  • 226
    • 77952510484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1023
    • See, e.g., Singer, supra note 12, at 1023.
  • 227
    • 77952481227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SINGER, supra note 91, at 36
    • See SINGER, supra note 91, at 36 ("[P]roperty requires regulation.").
  • 228
    • 77952506021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 127
    • On the realists' views, see supra note 127.
  • 229
    • 77952533405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 796-801
    • See Alexander, supra note 5, at 796-801.
  • 230
    • 77952482515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1026
    • See, e.g.. Singer, supra note 12, at 1026.
  • 231
    • 77952532132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1055
    • Id. at 1055 (describing, among the normative features of property law in a free and democratic society, "widespread distribution of property and realistic potential for access to ownership").
  • 232
    • 77952477313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. ("[W]e value both stability and change....").
  • 233
    • 77952473383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 74-75
    • See supra text accompanying notes 74-75.
  • 234
    • 77952499029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1050-55
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1050-55 (describing the "plural values" underlying democratic property rights, including, inter alia, freedom, stability, family, autonomy, mobility, and "widespread distribution of property").
  • 236
    • 77952481619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 978-79
    • Id. at 978-79.
  • 237
    • 58149401035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Community and custom in property
    • 15
    • Henry E. Smith, Community and Custom in Property, 10 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 5, 15 (2009);
    • (2009) Theoretical Inquiries L. , vol.10 , pp. 5
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 238
    • 84962313031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, 1135.
    • see also Smith, Language of Property, supra note 15, at 1113, 1135.
    • Language of Property , pp. 1113
    • Smith1
  • 239
    • 77952473382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 868
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 868.
  • 240
    • 77952526241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1054
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1054.
  • 241
    • 77952502313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1058
    • Id. at 1058;
  • 242
    • 77952539233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 882
    • see also Peñalver, supra note 12, at 882 ("[A]n obligation to share one's property in kind with others might arise, for example, (1) because exclusion... is inconsistent with the dignity of the excluded person; (2) because of the unusually acute... need for access... ; (3) because of the relationships the recipients have formed with the owner's land; or (4) because of the relationships of dependence or reliance that owners have formed with the recipients.").
  • 243
    • 77952500452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 244
    • 77952517198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1061
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1061;
  • 245
    • 77952513541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Peñalver, supra note 12, at 876 (Virtue theory's lack of an algorithm for social decision making, far from being a fatal weakness, is actually a point of strength... [because] it focuses decision makers' attention exactly where it should be)
    • see also Peñalver, supra note 12, at 876 ("Virtue theory's lack of an algorithm for social decision making, far from being a fatal weakness, is actually a point of strength... [because] it focuses decision makers' attention exactly where it should be.").
  • 246
    • 77952481226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 774
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 774.
  • 249
    • 77952494743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 804
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 804.
  • 250
    • 77952479210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 807; see also id. at 806 (I do suggest... that recreation is an important aspect of health, which is itself a vital dimension of the capability of life, and that providing all persons, including poor people, with reasonable access to basic modes of recreation and relaxation would materially contribute to the goal of being capable of living lives worth living)
    • Id. at 807; see also id. at 806 ("I do suggest... that recreation is an important aspect of health, which is itself a vital dimension of the capability of life, and that providing all persons, including poor people, with reasonable access to basic modes of recreation and relaxation would materially contribute to the goal of being capable of living lives worth living.").
  • 251
    • 77952540410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 791-801
    • Id. at 791-801.
  • 252
    • 77952486312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 807
    • Id. at 807.
  • 253
    • 77952504473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, Morality of Property, supra note 13, at 1857
    • Merrill & Smith, Morality of Property, supra note 13, at 1857.
  • 254
    • 77952482916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1859; see Smith, Exclusion and Property Rules, supra note 117, at 1024-1025 (arguing that where to draw the line between exclusion and governance is an empirical question)
    • Id. at 1859; see Smith, Exclusion and Property Rules, supra note 117, at 1024-1025 (arguing that where to draw the line between exclusion and governance is an "empirical question").
  • 255
    • 64949133945 scopus 로고
    • Crystab and mud in property law
    • 580
    • See Carol M. Rose, Crystab and Mud in Property Law, 40 STAN. L. REV. 577, 580 (1988).
    • (1988) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.40 , pp. 577
    • Rose, C.M.1
  • 256
    • 77952534547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • But see Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 803 ("Because in rem rights are binding on an indefinite class of persons, the rules must communicate information about the scope of protected rights to this large universe of interests at acceptable costs. This means that substantive legal norms associated with in rem rights are more likely to be expressed as rules that turn on one or a small number of publicly observable states of fact, and thus are formalistic or bright line in character.").
  • 257
    • 77952536435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g.. Smith, Exclusion and Property Rules, supra note 117, at 989 ([A]s the pressure on and value of resources rise, we often find a shift from exclusion to governance.); Smith, supra note 14, at 79 (where [m]ore precision in terms of who can do what can be determined in a way that is costeffective, a governance strategy may be appropriate)
    • See, e.g.. Smith, Exclusion and Property Rules, supra note 117, at 989 ("[A]s the pressure on and value of resources rise, we often find a shift from exclusion to governance."); Smith, supra note 14, at 79 (where "[m]ore precision in terms of who can do what" can be determined in a way that is costeffective, a governance strategy may be appropriate).
  • 258
    • 77952524910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dagan, supra note 119, at 1562; see also Dagan, supra note 2, at 8-9
    • Dagan, supra note 119, at 1562; see also Dagan, supra note 2, at 8-9.
  • 259
    • 77952534983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 1064
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 1064.
  • 260
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and substance in private law adjudication
    • See Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 HARV. L. REV. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 261
    • 68949187538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Response, mind the gap: The indirect relation between ends and means in american property law
    • 963-971
    • Henry E. Smith, Response, Mind the Gap: The Indirect Relation Between Ends and Means in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 959, 963-971 (2009).
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 959
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 262
    • 77952468032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 964; see also id. at 965 (Alexander and others... would like to see the end of flourishing more in direct view); Alexander, supra note 5, at 774 (calling for open acknowledgment of the social-obligation norm and explicit development of its parameters)
    • Id. at 964; see also id. at 965 ("Alexander and others... would like to see the end of flourishing more in direct view."); Alexander, supra note 5, at 774 (calling for "open acknowledgment" of the social-obligation norm and "explicit development of its parameters").
  • 263
    • 77952539619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 963
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 963.
  • 264
    • 77952470340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 964
    • Id. at 964.
  • 265
    • 77952523778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. And in individual cases where they do not, the governance strategy is always available: Where problems are important enough and cannot be solved better in a different way, we start to use more tailored solutions-governance- that make more direct reference to the ends that we collectively want to see served Id. at 964-965
    • Id. And in individual cases where they do not, the governance strategy is always available: "Where problems are important enough and cannot be solved better in a different way, we start to use more tailored solutions-governance-that make more direct reference to the ends that we collectively want to see served." Id. at 964-965
  • 266
    • 77952525288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 963. Smith admits that talking about ultimate ends is more glamorous than asking the more engineering-like question of how to serve them, but argues that legal scholars excel at institutional design, and should embrace our role. Id. at 970
    • Id. at 963. Smith admits that "talking about ultimate ends is more glamorous than asking the more engineering-like question of how to serve them," but argues that legal scholars excel at "institutional design," and should "embrace our role." Id. at 970.
  • 267
    • 77952520621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 971; see also id. at 970 (citing coordination in a complex world as one of several emergent properties of the entire property system)
    • Id. at 971; see also id. at 970 (citing "coordination in a complex world" as one of several "emergent properties of the entire property system").
  • 268
    • 77952500064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g.. Singer, supra note 12, at 1059 (In defining rights and obligations with respect to property, we are obligated to consider the full range of human values we care about rather than merely thinking quantitatively about how to maximize preferences)
    • See, e.g.. Singer, supra note 12, at 1059 ("In defining rights and obligations with respect to property, we are obligated to consider the full range of human values we care about rather than merely thinking quantitatively about how to maximize preferences.").
  • 269
    • 77952522148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, The Morality of Property, supra note 13, at 1857
    • Merrill & Smith, The Morality of Property, supra note 13, at 1857.
  • 270
    • 77952484058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See sources cited supra note 2; supra text accompanying notes 16-27
    • See sources cited supra note 2; supra text accompanying notes 16-27.
  • 271
    • 77952508005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nestor Davidson has argued that this issue of complexity does not require a resolution at all
    • Nestor Davidson has argued that this issue of complexity does not require a resolution at all.
  • 272
    • 58149380549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Standardization and pluralbm in property law
    • 1644
    • See Nestor M. Davidson, Standardization and Pluralbm in Property Law, 61 VAND. L. REV. 1597, 1644 (2008).
    • (2008) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.61 , pp. 1597
    • Davidson, N.M.1
  • 273
    • 77952495878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • He asserts that property is fundamentally "pluralist" in nature, and that its standard forms "engraft a variety of (at times clashing) public regulatory goals onto the basic law of private property - It is the variety and sheer messiness of the mandatory content of the forms that make the numerus clausus so interesting." Id. The picture of property as an enormous tent, employing a stable "basic regulatory framework of forms" to encompass or express numerous conflicting values, id. at 1636, has enormous appeal. Yet somehow it fails to address the obvious points of disagreement within contemporary property theory.
  • 274
    • 77952476142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 563 N.W.2d 154 Wis. as consistent with human flourishing. Jacque is usually cited as the quintessential right-to-exclude case. In Jacque, the court upheld an award of punitive damages for what was arguably a harmless, yet clearly intentional, trespass
    • Thus Alexander praises the court's holding for the landowner and against the trespasser in Jacque v. Steenberg Homes, Inc., 563 N.W.2d 154 (Wis. 1997), as consistent with human flourishing. Jacque is usually cited as the quintessential right-to-exclude case. In Jacque, the court upheld an award of punitive damages for what was arguably a harmless, yet clearly intentional, trespass.
    • (1997) Jacque V. Steenberg Homes, Inc.
  • 275
    • 77952478130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 621-22. Alexander avoids the traditional reading of Jacque by emphasizing that the trespass involved the plaintiffs' home and thus their capacity for sociality. See Alexander, supra note 5, at 815-817
    • See id. at 621-22. Alexander avoids the traditional reading of Jacque by emphasizing that the trespass involved the plaintiffs' home and thus their capacity for sociality. See Alexander, supra note 5, at 815-817
  • 276
    • 18944364322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distributive values in copyright
    • See Molly Shaffer Van Houweling, Distributive Values in Copyright, 83 TEX. L. REV. 1535 (2005).
    • (2005) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.83 , pp. 1535
    • Van Houweling, M.S.1
  • 277
    • 77952514399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notwithstanding Alexander's use of Jacque in The Social-Obligation Norm, see supra note 179, progressive theorists are, in general, far less likely to look to trespass cases as paradigmatic of property law, invoking instead the range of statutory and administrative regulations that limit common-law exclusion rights. See supra text accompanying notes 74-75, 146-147
    • Notwithstanding Alexander's use of Jacque in The Social-Obligation Norm, see supra note 179, progressive theorists are, in general, far less likely to look to trespass cases as paradigmatic of property law, invoking instead the range of statutory and administrative regulations that limit common-law exclusion rights. See supra text accompanying notes 74-75, 146-147
  • 278
    • 77950635331 scopus 로고
    • 277 A. 2d 369, 374-75 N.J. is the quintessential example. In this famous casebook case, the court declined to characterize as a trespass an unconsented-to entry by government workers seeking to offer services to migrant workers housed on a farmer's land. Id. The court found illegitimate the farmer's attempt to use his power to exclude in a way that affected the dignity and destiny of the workers on his property. Id
    • State v. Shack, 277 A. 2d 369, 374-75 (N.J. 1971), is the quintessential example. In this famous casebook case, the court declined to characterize as a trespass an unconsented-to entry by government workers seeking to offer services to migrant workers housed on a farmer's land. Id. The court found illegitimate the farmer's attempt to use his power to exclude in a way that affected the dignity and destiny of the workers on his property. Id.
    • (1971) State V. Shack
  • 279
    • 77952486702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Alexander, supra note 4, at 1066 ([T]he core of property is complex, certainly more complex than [exclusion alone]....). But see Smith, supra note 168, at 968 (It is because the world of interactions is so complex that modular[, exclusion-based] solutions must be on the table)
    • See, e.g., Alexander, supra note 4, at 1066 ("[T]he core of property is complex, certainly more complex than [exclusion alone]...."). But see Smith, supra note 168, at 968 ("It is because the world of interactions is so complex that modular[, exclusion-based] solutions must be on the table.").
  • 280
    • 77952496674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Like standardization, complexity comes in degrees. See Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 38. Extreme and minimal complexity, like extreme and minimal standardization, have costs and benefits. But until we discuss complexity as an independent value, how would these costs and benefits be assessed
    • Like standardization, complexity "comes in degrees." See Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 38. Extreme and minimal complexity, like extreme and minimal standardization, have costs and benefits. But until we discuss complexity as an independent value, how would these costs and benefits be assessed?
  • 281
    • 77952493962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a taste of this dispute, see Smith, supra note 168, at 969. Property law provides the overall structure to manage the complexity that Alexander rightly emphasizes, but the need to manage complexity points to the need, at least in theory, for a modular solution. If so, his considerations lead in practice exactly away from his skepticism toward delegation to owners
    • For a taste of this dispute, see Smith, supra note 168, at 969. Property law provides the overall structure to manage the complexity that Alexander rightly emphasizes, but the need to manage complexity points to the need, at least in theory, for a modular solution. If so, his considerations lead in practice exactly away from his skepticism toward delegation to owners.
  • 282
    • 77952467658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hohfeld, supra note 88, at 30. Hohfeld also organized the interests listed above into opposites: rights/no-rights, privileges/duties, powers/disabilities, and immunities/liabilities. Id
    • Hohfeld, supra note 88, at 30. Hohfeld also organized the interests listed above into "opposites": rights/no-rights, privileges/duties, powers/disabilities, and immunities/liabilities. Id.
  • 283
    • 77952473752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baron, Property and No Property, supra note 52, at 1445
    • See Baron, Property and "No Property", supra note 52, at 1445.
  • 284
    • 77952533404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 285
    • 77952536763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For convenience, unless the context requires more precision, I will use the term duties to include all the negative aspects of property interests, including no-rights, disabilities, and liabilities
    • For convenience, unless the context requires more precision, I will use the term "duties" to include all the "negative" aspects of property interests, including no-rights, disabilities, and liabilities.
  • 286
    • 77952484452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the system also operates to delineate rights in such a way that buyers will know exactly what they are obtaining when they acquire property. See Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 26-34
    • Of course, the system also operates to delineate rights in such a way that buyers will know exactly what they are obtaining when they acquire property. See Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 26-34.
  • 287
    • 77952469960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.A
    • See supra Part I.A.
  • 288
    • 77952510483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1728
    • Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1728.
  • 289
    • 77952473381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Smith, Exclusion and Property Rules, supra note 117, at 1023; see also Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 791 ("Exclusion identifies a person or entity as the manager of a resource (the owner), and then delegates to this manager the discretion to select from among an open-ended set of potential uses."); Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1728 ("[T]he right to exclude... protects a reservoir of uses to the owner without officials needing to know what those might be."). On delegation, see supra text accompanying note 117.
  • 290
    • 77952508816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1772 (footnote omitted)
    • Smith, Property, supra note 13, at 1772 (footnote omitted).
  • 291
    • 77952495879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 148-49, 170-172
    • See supra text accompanying notes 148-49, 170-172
  • 292
    • 77952485926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, What Happened to Property, supra note 15, at 387
    • Merrill & Smith, What Happened to Property, supra note 15, at 387.
  • 293
    • 77952475763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 78
    • Smith, supra note 14, at 78.
  • 294
    • 77952498241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 794
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 21, at 794.
  • 295
    • 77952519475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baron, Property and No Property, supra note 52, at 1445
    • See Baron, Property and "No Property", supra note 52, at 1445.
  • 296
    • 77952499779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On consolidation, see supra text accompanying notes 114-117
    • On consolidation, see supra text accompanying notes 114-117
  • 297
    • 77952492786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Putting this point another way, progressive theorists flip the question what duties do nonowners owe to owners? to the question what duties do owners owe to nonowners
    • Putting this point another way, progressive theorists flip the question "what duties do nonowners owe to owners?" to the question "what duties do owners owe to nonowners?"
  • 298
    • 77952522551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1047; see also Purdy, People as Resources, supra note 12, at 1094-1098 (describing our interdependence, and urging emphasis not on the abstract categories of the law, but rather on the concrete social world in which each person is the owner of certain resources and not of others.)
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1047; see also Purdy, People as Resources, supra note 12, at 1094-1098 (describing our "interdependence," and urging emphasis not on "the abstract categories of the law," but rather on "the concrete social world in which each person is the owner of certain resources and not of others.").
  • 299
    • 77952504069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1048
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1048.
  • 300
    • 77952490830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (emphasis added) (footnote omitted); see also SINGER, supra note 91,
    • Id. (emphasis added) (footnote omitted); see also SINGER, supra note 91, at 18 ("Owners have obligations; they have always had obligations. We can argue about what those obligations should be, but no one can seriously argue that they should not exist").
  • 301
    • 77952495164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 870 (footnote omitted)
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 870 (footnote omitted).
  • 302
    • 77952540818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 880; see also id. at 877 ([A] proper concern for human flourishing includes an effort to ensure that the fruits of the land's productivity... are distributed in a manner consistent with that ultimate goal....)
    • Id. at 880; see also id. at 877 ("[A] proper concern for human flourishing includes an effort to ensure that the fruits of the land's productivity... are distributed in a manner consistent with that ultimate goal....").
  • 303
    • 77952511527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 747-748
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 747-748
  • 304
    • 77952529456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 156-158
    • See supra text accompanying notes 156-158
  • 305
    • 77952515131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • With respect, for example, to a car In order to maintain a semblance of stability in [the property] system, not only must each owner recognize and exercise dominion over his own car, but virtually all members of society-owners and nonowners alike-must recognize and respect the unique claims of owners to their own particular auto. In other words, virtually everyone must recognize and consider themselves bound by general duties not to interfere with autos that they know are owned by some anonymous other. Merrill & Smith, Morality of Property, supra note 13, at 1853-54. Lior Strahilevitz has characterized the basic exclusionary right at the core of the system in the information view as a "hermit's right."
  • 306
    • 33746896197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Information asymmetries and the right to exclude
    • 1841
    • See Lior Jacob Strahilevitz, Information Asymmetries and the Right to Exclude, 104 MICH. L. REV. 1835, 1841 (2006).
    • (2006) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.104 , pp. 1835
    • Strahilevitz, L.J.1
  • 307
    • 77952539620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 963
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 963.
  • 308
    • 77952487084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach, supra note 12, at 1243
    • Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach, supra note 12, at 1243.
  • 309
    • 77952504870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1047
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1047.
  • 310
    • 77952519474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1047-48; see also Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach, supra note 12, at 1243 (Property rights... deeply and necessarily structure interpersonal relations.)
    • Id. at 1047-48; see also Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach, supra note 12, at 1243 ("Property rights... deeply and necessarily structure interpersonal relations.").
  • 311
    • 77952479648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1055
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1055.
  • 312
    • 77952520258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 768
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 768.
  • 313
    • 77952474543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 882
    • Peñalver, supra note 12, at 882.
  • 314
    • 77952530209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 66-68
    • See Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 66-68.
  • 315
    • 77952468794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 973
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 973.
  • 316
    • 77952520620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Smith is somewhat ambiguous on this point. At one point he asks why "pleasing old buildings and public beaches" should be provided "at personal expense, rather than the government funding them by taxing other comparably wealthy citizens." Id. at 961. But at another point in the same piece he disclaims having an opinion on whether the redistribution sought by progressive theorists such as Alexander would better be achieved through a tax and transfer system. See id. at 973.
  • 317
    • 77952503677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 24
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 24.
  • 318
    • 77952504068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 319
    • 77952534546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 35
    • Id. at 35.
  • 320
    • 77952468415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 40
    • Id. at 40.
  • 321
    • 77952507624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 58. On the information theorists' institutional choice preference for legislative change, see supra text accompanying notes 135-139
    • Id. at 58. On the information theorists' institutional choice preference for legislative change, see supra text accompanying notes 135-139
  • 322
    • 77952490829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 63
    • Merrill & Smith, supra note 9, at 63.
  • 323
    • 77952472991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 66-67. Legislative inertia, they go on to argue, may be more the product of a lack of consensus about the proper path of reform than of any inherent inability of legislatures to respond to demands for changes in property systems. Id. at 67
    • Id. at 66-67. Legislative inertia, they go on to argue, "may be more the product of a lack of consensus about the proper path of reform than of any inherent inability of legislatures to respond to demands for changes in property systems." Id. at 67.
  • 324
    • 77952509569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach, supra note 12, at 1243
    • Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach, supra note 12, at 1243.
  • 325
    • 77952530571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 819
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 819.
  • 326
    • 77952478513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • While Peñalver, for example, admits that his virtue theory does not provide a full account "of the proper roles of legislatures, courts, administrative agencies, and individual citizens in wise land use decision making," see Peñalver, supra note 12, at 888, he is clear that "exclusive reliance on an aggregated system of taxation and monetary payments will be inadequate," see id. at 882. Alexander and Singer also do not directly address the means by which redistribution should occur, but both praise judicial, as well as regulatory, efforts to promote more just distribution of opportunities. See Singer, supra note 12, at 1055 (citing laws, judicial doctrines, and private agreements that promote equal opportunity); Alexander, supra note 5, at 775-810 (using examples from both case law and legislation).
  • 327
    • 77952481618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Merrill & Smith, What Happened to Property, supra note 15, at 359 (describing "core property rights"); Merrill & Smith, Morality of Property, supra note 13, at 1850 (describing exclusion as a "core aspect of property"); Smith, supra note 168, at 971 ("At its core, property draws on an everyday morality that it is wrong to steal and violate others' exclusion rights."). Alexander's reply to critiques of The Social-Obligation Norm is entitled The Complex Core of Property. See Alexander, supra note 4. But see supra note 6.
  • 328
    • 77952469176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 964
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 964.
  • 329
    • 77952489770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 964-965
    • Id. at 964-965
  • 330
    • 77952496675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1050
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1050.
  • 331
    • 77952491238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1054; see also Alexander, supra note 5, at 748 (arguing that although [t]he law has relegated the social obligations of owners to the margins, while individual rights, such as the right to exclude, have occupied the center stage, this picture should be changed)
    • Id. at 1054; see also Alexander, supra note 5, at 748 (arguing that although "[t]he law has relegated the social obligations of owners to the margins, while individual rights, such as the right to exclude, have occupied the center stage," this picture should be changed).
  • 332
    • 77952534982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 1064
    • 235- Alexander, supra note 4, at 1064.
  • 333
    • 77952499394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1025
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1025.
  • 334
    • 77952486701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 335
    • 77952538827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1026. This statement obviously qualifies Singer's acceptance of the numerus clausus principle
    • Id. at 1026. This statement obviously qualifies Singer's acceptance of the numerus clausus principle.
  • 336
    • 77952482130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merrill & Smith, Morality of Property, supra note 13, at 1852-1853
    • Merrill & Smith, Morality of Property, supra note 13, at 1852-1853.
  • 337
    • 77952495163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 971
    • Smith, supra note 168, at 971.
  • 338
    • 77952481617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1026 (footnote omitted)
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1026 (footnote omitted).
  • 339
    • 77952501938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 1066
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 1066.
  • 340
    • 77952516695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith repeatedly uses the mechanism metaphor. See, e.g.. Smith, supra note 168, at 973, 975. 976
    • Smith repeatedly uses the "mechanism" metaphor. See, e.g.. Smith, supra note 168, at 973, 975. 976.
  • 341
    • 77952521364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 970
    • Id. at 970.
  • 342
    • 77952472254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 343
    • 77952487464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1059
    • Singer, supra note 12, at 1059.
  • 344
    • 77952491237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 764
    • Alexander, supra note 5, at 764.
  • 345
    • 77952469959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach, supra note 12, at 1244-1245
    • Purdy, A Freedom-Promoting Approach, supra note 12, at 1244-1245
  • 346
    • 77952477723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Smith, supra note 168, at 970 (using the term practicality)
    • See Smith, supra note 168, at 970 (using the term " practicality").
  • 347
    • 77952509202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 969 (Property law provides the overall structure to manage... complexity..., but the need to manage complexity points to the need, at least in theory, for a modular solution.)
    • Id. at 969 ("Property law provides the overall structure to manage... complexity..., but the need to manage complexity points to the need, at least in theory, for a modular solution.").
  • 348
    • 77952531351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (Ultimately, what degree and kind of modularization we need is an empirical question.)
    • Id. ("Ultimately, what degree and kind of modularization we need is an empirical question.").
  • 349
    • 77952490828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 967, 973
    • Id. at 967, 973.
  • 350
    • 77952514398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 974
    • Id. at 974.
  • 351
    • 77952471469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 970 (using the example of North Korea)
    • Id. at 970 (using the example of North Korea).
  • 352
    • 77952528242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Singer, supra note 12, at 1051 (We tend to forget this fundamental purpose of the estates system [outlawing certain prohibited social and political relationships] because custom has evolved so that no one seeks to create feudal or slave relationships today.)
    • See Singer, supra note 12, at 1051 ("We tend to forget this fundamental purpose of the estates system [outlawing certain prohibited social and political relationships] because custom has evolved so that no one seeks to create feudal or slave relationships today.").
  • 353
    • 77952533403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 1059 (There are various ways to think through and justify alternative resolutions to difficult property questions, but none of them gives us a mechanical decision procedure to generate an outcome.)
    • See, e.g., id. at 1059 ("There are various ways to think through and justify alternative resolutions" to difficult property questions, but "none of them gives us a mechanical decision procedure to generate an outcome.").
  • 354
    • 77952494742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1061
    • Id. at 1061.
  • 355
    • 77952533780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rose, supra note 163, at 580
    • See Rose, supra note 163, at 580.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.