메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 97, Issue 1, 1997, Pages 263-280

Reason and agency

(1)  Pink, Thomas a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77952466913     PISSN: 00667374     EISSN: 14679264     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1467-9264.00016     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (9)

References (21)
  • 1
    • 0010952683 scopus 로고
    • Intending
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • 'Intending' pp. 86-7 in D. Davidson Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980)
    • (1980) Essays on Actions and Events , pp. 86-87
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 2
    • 79957310279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Intending' p. 90
    • Intending , pp. 90
  • 3
    • 79957084544 scopus 로고
    • Davidson puts forward the view of intention motivation which follows on of his replies in eds B. Vermazen and M. Hintikka Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Davidson puts forward the view of intention motivation which follows on pp. 213-14 of his replies in Essays on Davidson eds B. Vermazen and M. Hintikka (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985)
    • (1985) Essays on Davidson , pp. 213-214
  • 4
    • 0004287799 scopus 로고
    • Chapter 6, References are to the edition of R. Tuck Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Leviathan (1651) chapter 6, p. 44. References are to the edition of R. Tuck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991)
    • (1651) Leviathan , pp. 44
  • 5
    • 0009388938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I endorse, as essential to a practical reason-based account of agency, Aquinas's conception of the human will as a rational or reason-applying appetite. But I omit from the main text, as inessential to a practical reason-based account, a further important aspect of Aquinas's conception of the will - his intellectualism. Aquinas conceived the will - our capacity for decision making and intention formation - as tied to our deliberative capacity to reflect and form practical judgments about how we should act. As involving the will, human actions, in Aquinas's view, were based on a view of the good. The acts of electio by which we decide to perform actions A were given their content by corresponding judgments that it would be good to do A. The will was notionally a power distinct from the intellect: but its actual operations were conceived by Aquinas as integrated with and informed by a corresponding exercise of the practical intellect
    • I endorse, as essential to a practical reason-based account of agency, Aquinas's conception of the human will as a rational or reason-applying appetite. But I omit from the main text, as inessential to a practical reason-based account, a further important aspect of Aquinas's conception of the will - his intellectualism. Aquinas conceived the will - our capacity for decision making and intention formation - as tied to our deliberative capacity to reflect and form practical judgments about how we should act. As involving the will, human actions, in Aquinas's view, were based on a view of the good. The acts of electio by which we decide to perform actions A were given their content by corresponding judgments that it would be good to do A. The will was notionally a power distinct from the intellect: but its actual operations were conceived by Aquinas as integrated with and informed by a corresponding exercise of the practical intellect. In my The Psychology of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) I defend a rival, voluntarist theory which firmly distinguishes intellect and will. On this theory, our capacity for decision making and intention is still a rational appetite - a capacity for applying reason. For the will has precisely the function of executing practical judgments about how we should act. But decisions and intentions are quite distinct from the prior practical judgments which it is their function to execute - so that we can sometimes, irrationally, decide to act contrary to our judgments about how we should act. The will's reason-applying role is purely executive, not deliberative
    • (1996) The Psychology of Freedom
  • 6
    • 79957276049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a typically forceful expression of Hobbes's failure to understand this point, see chapter 6 The Definition of the Will, given commonly by the Schooles, that it is a Rationall Appetite, is not good. For if it were, then there could be no Voluntary Act against Reason
    • For a typically forceful expression of Hobbes's failure to understand this point, see Leviathan, chapter 6 p. 44: The Definition of the Will, given commonly by the Schooles, that it is a Rationall Appetite, is not good. For if it were, then there could be no Voluntary Act against Reason
    • Leviathan , pp. 44
  • 7
    • 79957241499 scopus 로고
    • 1a 2ae q6 a1. Page references are to volume 2 of the BAC edition, Madrid 1985
    • Summa Theologiae (1265-74) 1a 2ae q6 a1, p. 54. Page references are to volume 2 of the BAC edition, Madrid 1985
    • (1265) Summa Theologiae , pp. 54
  • 8
    • 79957077263 scopus 로고
    • There is a translation by J. Oesterle of this part of the Summa dealing with agency entitled (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press)
    • There is a translation by J. Oesterle of this part of the Summa dealing with agency entitled Treatise on Happiness (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983)
    • (1983) Treatise on Happiness , vol.2
  • 9
    • 60950154413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1a 2ae q6 a3
    • Summa Theologiae 1a 2ae q6 a3 p. 56
    • Summa Theologiae , pp. 56
  • 10
    • 0003784144 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Elbow Room (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984) p. 78
    • (1984) Elbow Room , pp. 78
  • 12
    • 0003738758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A variety of considerations against second order agency are proposed in, for example, the second book of
    • A variety of considerations against second order agency are proposed in, for example, the second book of Calvin's Institutes of the Christian Religion (1559)
    • (1559) Institutes of the Christian Religion
    • Calvin1
  • 14
    • 0003553033 scopus 로고
    • and in qualified form in the chapter on power in
    • , and in qualified form in the chapter on power in Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690)
    • (1690) Essay Concerning Human Understanding
    • Locke1
  • 15
    • 24244476371 scopus 로고
    • Considerations for are to be found in, for example, the nineteenth of Suarez's Metaphysical Disputations (1597)
    • (1597) Metaphysical Disputations
    • Suarez1
  • 18
    • 79957318365 scopus 로고
    • The knowledge of God the Redeemer
    • book 2, chapter 2, page reference to of the translation by F.L. Battles, ed. J. T. McNeill London:S.C.M. Press
    • Institutes of the Christian Religion book 2, chapter 2, 'The knowledge of God the Redeemer', pp. 270-1 - page reference to volume 1 of the translation by F.L. Battles, ed. J. T. McNeill (London:S.C.M. Press, 1961)
    • (1961) Institutes of the Christian Religion , vol.1 , pp. 270-271
  • 20
    • 79957199635 scopus 로고
    • Of the influencing motives of the will
    • See book 2, part 3, section 3 Page references will be to the edition of L.A. Selby-Bigge/P.H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978)
    • See Treatise of Human Nature (1739-40), book 2, part 3, section 3 'Of the influencing motives of the will'. Page references will be to the edition of L.A. Selby-Bigge/P.H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978)
    • (1739) Treatise of Human Nature
  • 21
    • 79955153903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Treatise p. 399
    • Treatise , pp. 399


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.