메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 53, Issue 2, 2003, Pages 73-82

Divine omniscience and knowledge de se

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77951904142     PISSN: 00207047     EISSN: 15728684     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/A:1023317625835     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (68)
  • 1
    • 52549105414 scopus 로고
    • Some neglected problems of omniscience
    • Patrick Grim, 'Some Neglected Problems of Omniscience', American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (1983), pp. 265-276;
    • (1983) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.20 , pp. 265-276
    • Grim, P.1
  • 2
    • 52849122569 scopus 로고
    • Against omniscience: The case from essential indexicals
    • Patrick Grim, 'Against Omniscience: The Case from Essential Indexicals', Noûs 19 (1985), pp. 151-180;
    • (1985) Noûs , vol.19 , pp. 151-180
    • Grim, P.1
  • 4
    • 0011221927 scopus 로고
    • Attitudes de dicto and de Se
    • The term 'knowledge de se' was introduced by Lewis. See David Lewis, 'Attitudes De Dicto and De Se', Philosophical Review 88 (1979), pp. 513-543.
    • (1979) Philosophical Review , vol.88 , pp. 513-543
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 5
    • 84935552329 scopus 로고
    • The problem of the essential indexical
    • Perry uses a more general term 'essential indexicals' in his original paper
    • Perry uses a more general term 'essential indexicals' in his original paper, 'The Problem of the Essential Indexical', Noûi 13 (1979), pp. 3-21.
    • (1979) Noûi , vol.13 , pp. 3-21
  • 6
    • 77951887296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grim also provides an argument against divine omniscience from knowledge de presenti; namely, knowledge of 'now'. Since that argument involves enormously controversial issues concerning divine timelessness, I focus on his argument from knowledge de se in this paper.
    • Grim also provides an argument against divine omniscience from knowledge de presenti; namely, knowledge of 'now'. Since that argument involves enormously controversial issues concerning divine timelessness, I focus on his argument from knowledge de se in this paper.
  • 7
    • 0004296633 scopus 로고
    • Thomas Gilby (trans.) London: Eyre and Spottiswoode
    • See, for example, Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Thomas Gilby (trans.) (London: Eyre and Spottiswoode, 1967);
    • (1967) Summa Theologiae
    • Aquinas, T.1
  • 9
    • 1842468655 scopus 로고
    • Anthony Kenny (ed.) Oxford: Oxford, Clarendon Press
    • René Descartes, Philosophical Letters, Anthony Kenny (ed.) (Oxford: Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1970);
    • (1970) Philosophical Letters
    • Descartes, R.1
  • 10
    • 68249157530 scopus 로고
    • Maximal power
    • Alfred J. Freddoso (ed.), Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
    • Thomas P. Flint and Alfred J. Freddoso, 'Maximal Power', in Alfred J. Freddoso (ed.), The Existence and Nature of God (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), pp. 81-113;
    • (1983) The Existence and Nature of God , pp. 81-113
    • Flint, T.P.1    Freddoso, A.J.2
  • 11
    • 33947671155 scopus 로고
    • The logic of omnipotence
    • Harry G. Frankfurt, 'The Logic of Omnipotence', Philosophical Review 73 (1964), pp. 262-263;
    • (1964) Philosophical Review , vol.73 , pp. 262-263
    • Frankfurt, H.G.1
  • 14
    • 77951920744 scopus 로고
    • In defense of omnipotence
    • E. J. Khamara, 'In Defense of Omnipotence', Philosophical Quarterly 28 (1978), pp. 215-228;
    • (1978) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.28 , pp. 215-228
    • Khamara, E.J.1
  • 15
    • 77951933380 scopus 로고
    • The hidden assumption in the paradox of omnipotence
    • Richard R. La Croix, 'The Hidden Assumption in the Paradox of Omnipotence', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 38 (1977), pp. 125-127;
    • (1977) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.38 , pp. 125-127
    • La Croix, R.R.1
  • 16
    • 53249119791 scopus 로고
    • Some puzzles concerning omnipotence
    • George I. Mavrodes, 'Some Puzzles Concerning Omnipotence', Philosophical Review 72 (1963), pp. 221-223;
    • (1963) Philosophical Review , vol.72 , pp. 221-223
    • Mavrodes, G.I.1
  • 17
    • 60949257864 scopus 로고
    • The pardox of the stone
    • C. Wade Savage, 'The Pardox of the Stone', Philosophical Review 76 (1967), pp. 74-79;
    • (1967) Philosophical Review , vol.76 , pp. 74-79
    • Wade Savage, C.1
  • 19
    • 77951893761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grim (1983), p. 272
    • Grim (1983), p. 272;
  • 20
    • 77951935289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grim (1985), p. 151
    • Grim (1985), p. 151;
  • 21
    • 77951894383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grim (2000), p. 142
    • Grim (2000), p. 142.
  • 22
    • 77951887890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A precise interpretation of the phrase 'what I know in knowing (1)' raises a further issue in the philosophy of language. Grim uses this phrase to denote an object of knowledge. But if objects of knowledge are Russellian propositions, then what I know in knowing (1) just is what I know in knowing (2). It follows that Grim cannot think that objects of knowledge are Russellian propositions. Beyond this, however, Grim remains neutral on the nature of objects of knowledge.
    • A precise interpretation of the phrase 'what I know in knowing (1)' raises a further issue in the philosophy of language. Grim uses this phrase to denote an object of knowledge. But if objects of knowledge are Russellian propositions, then what I know in knowing (1) just is what I know in knowing (2). It follows that Grim cannot think that objects of knowledge are Russellian propositions. Beyond this, however, Grim remains neutral on the nature of objects of knowledge.
  • 23
    • 52849125903 scopus 로고
    • Omniscience and indexical reference
    • Hector-Neri Castañeda, 'Omniscience and Indexical Reference', Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967), pp. 203-210.
    • (1967) Journal of Philosophy , vol.64 , pp. 203-210
    • Castañeda, H.-N.1
  • 24
    • 77951927962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the text I treat Castañeda's objection as a criticism of Grim's argument, but in fact, Castañeda's objection, which is older than Grim's argument, is intended to undermine Norman Kretzmann's argument from which Grim derived his basic idea. Kretzmann argues that no one other than Jones can know what the statement 'Jones knows that he is in a hospital' describes Jones as knowing. Kretzmann also writes, 'Anyone could have proved that Descartes existed, but that is not what Descartes proved in the Cogito, and what he proved in the Cogito could not have been proved by anyone else'
    • In the text I treat Castañeda's objection as a criticism of Grim's argument, but in fact, Castañeda's objection, which is older than Grim's argument, is intended to undermine Norman Kretzmann's argument from which Grim derived his basic idea. Kretzmann argues that no one other than Jones can know what the statement 'Jones knows that he is in a hospital' describes Jones as knowing. Kretzmann also writes, 'Anyone could have proved that Descartes existed, but that is not what Descartes proved in the Cogito, and what he proved in the Cogito could not have been proved by anyone else'.
  • 25
    • 0043043334 scopus 로고
    • Omniscience and immutability
    • See Norman Kretzmann, 'Omniscience and Immutability', Journal of Philosophy 63 (1966), pp. 409-421.
    • (1966) Journal of Philosophy , vol.63 , pp. 409-421
    • Kretzmann, N.1
  • 26
    • 77951924341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Castañeda (1967), p. 201
    • Castañeda (1967), p. 201.
  • 27
    • 77951930777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grim argues against Castañeda as follows. Someone may well know that Yujin Nagasawa knows that he (himself) is making the mess and yet not know what I know in knowing (1). S/he may not know it, according to Grim, if s/he does not know that I am Yujin Nagasawa. See Grim (1985, pp. 162-168)
    • Grim argues against Castañeda as follows. Someone may well know that Yujin Nagasawa knows that he (himself) is making the mess and yet not know what I know in knowing (1). S/he may not know it, according to Grim, if s/he does not know that I am Yujin Nagasawa. See Grim (1985, pp. 162-168).
  • 28
    • 77951895567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Abbruzzese contends that Castañeda's argument is unsuccessful because (P) is subject to counter-examples. For instance, Abbruzzese argues, even if the sentence 'I know that Dr. Lawless of the Classics Department knows that vis consili expers mole ruit sua' formulates a true statement for someone s/he cannot be said to know that vis consili expers mole ruit sua unless s/he knows Latin (pp. 26-28)
    • John Abbruzzese contends that Castañeda's argument is unsuccessful because (P) is subject to counter-examples. For instance, Abbruzzese argues, even if the sentence 'I know that Dr. Lawless of the Classics Department knows that vis consili expers mole ruit sua' formulates a true statement for someone s/he cannot be said to know that vis consili expers mole ruit sua unless s/he knows Latin (pp. 26-28).
  • 30
    • 77951882973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am indebted to Daniel Stoljar on this point
    • I am indebted to Daniel Stoljar on this point.
  • 31
    • 1942461859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, For arguments against the know-that/know-how distinction
    • Perry, for example, argues that know-how is a unique form of know-that, which involves a special kind of representations, namely, executable schemas. See John Perry, Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001). For arguments against the know-that/know-how distinction
    • (2001) Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness
    • Perry, J.1
  • 37
    • 77951936715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abbruzzese (1997), p. 28
    • Abbruzzese (1997), p. 28.
  • 38
    • 77951924030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grim (2000), p. 143
    • Grim (2000), p. 143.
  • 39
    • 0013152068 scopus 로고
    • Divine cognitive power
    • For an attempt to define omniscience in terms of power that is slightly different from mine, see Charles Taliaferro, 'Divine Cognitive Power', International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 18 (1985), pp. 133-140.
    • (1985) International Journal for Philosophy of Religion , vol.18 , pp. 133-140
    • Taliaferro, C.1
  • 40
    • 77951897273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the application of the second principle to the paradox of the stone see Brown and Nagasawa (2002), and Mavrodes (1963)
    • For the application of the second principle to the paradox of the stone see Brown and Nagasawa (2002), and Mavrodes (1963).
  • 41
    • 77951933543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas (1967), p. 167
    • Aquinas (1967), p. 167.
  • 43
    • 70449910876 scopus 로고
    • Omnipotence defined
    • Wierenga similarly remarks, 'it has long been realized that in order to be omnipotent God need not be able to do exactly everything; for example, an omnipotent being need not be able to do what is logically impossible' (p. 363)
    • Wierenga similarly remarks, 'it has long been realized that in order to be omnipotent God need not be able to do exactly everything; for example, an omnipotent being need not be able to do what is logically impossible' (p. 363). Edward Wierenga 'Omnipotence Defined', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 43 (1983), pp. 363-375.
    • (1983) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.43 , pp. 363-375
    • Wierenga, E.1
  • 44
    • 77951884111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mavrodes (1963), p. 221
    • See also Mavrodes (1963), p. 221.
  • 45
    • 77951909783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mavrodes (1963), p. 221
    • Mavrodes (1963), p. 221.
  • 46
    • 0004178922 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Saul A. Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972).
    • (1972) Naming and Necessity
    • Kripke, S.A.1
  • 47
    • 77951904800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here I simply mean that the proposition expressed by (20) is necessarily false
    • Here I simply mean that the proposition expressed by (20) is necessarily false.
  • 48
    • 0001489611 scopus 로고
    • What is it like to be a bat
    • See Thomas Nagel, 'What Is It Like To Be a Bat', Philosophical Review 83 (1974), pp. 435-450;
    • (1974) Philosophical Review , vol.83 , pp. 435-450
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 49
    • 77951923170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas vs. Thomas: A new approach to nagel's bat argument
    • (forthcoming)
    • Yujin Nagasawa, 'Thomas vs. Thomas: A New Approach to Nagel's Bat Argument', Inquiry (forthcoming).
    • Inquiry
    • Nagasawa, Y.1
  • 51
    • 77951922867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It does not follow, however, that my strategy is applicable to any possible argument against the doctrine of divine omniscience. Suppose, for example, that there is an argument that allegedly shows that while God can know that p, He just does not. Since this argument does not commit to a claim that God cannot know that p my argument is not applicable to it
    • It does not follow, however, that my strategy is applicable to any possible argument against the doctrine of divine omniscience. Suppose, for example, that there is an argument that allegedly shows that while God can know that p, He just does not. Since this argument does not commit to a claim that God cannot know that p my argument is not applicable to it.
  • 52
    • 77951909183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many philosophers claim that Descartes does believe that God can do what it is necessarily impossible to do . See Harry G. Frankfurt (1964, 1977)
    • Many philosophers claim that Descartes does believe that God can do what it is necessarily impossible to do . See Harry G. Frankfurt (1964, 1977);
  • 53
    • 84976123888 scopus 로고
    • Omnipotence
    • Peter Geach, 'Omnipotence', Philosophy 48 (1973), pp. 7-20;
    • (1973) Philosophy , vol.48 , pp. 7-20
    • Geach, P.1
  • 54
    • 84972344685 scopus 로고
    • Gould god make a contradiction true?
    • D. Goldstick, 'Gould God Make a Contradiction True?', Religious Studies 26 (1990), pp. 377-387;
    • (1990) Religious Studies , vol.26 , pp. 377-387
    • Goldstick, D.1
  • 55
    • 60949226488 scopus 로고
    • Milwaukee: Marquett University Press, For example, the following passage by Descartes is said to prove it: 'I do not think that we should ever say of anything that it cannot be brought about by God. For since everything involved in truth and goodness depends on His omnipotence, I would not dare to say that God cannot make a mountain without a valley, or that one and two should not be three. I merely say that He has given me such a mind that I cannot conceive a mountain without a valley, or an aggregate of one and two which is not three, and that such things involve a contradiction in my conception'. Descartes (1970), pp. 236-237. See also pp. 11-12, 14-15, 150-151, 236-237, 240-241. La Croix argues, however, that Descartes does not really mean to contend that God can turn necessary impossibilities into possibilities
    • Alvin Plantinga, Does God Have a Nature? (Milwaukee: Marquett University Press, 1980). For example, the following passage by Descartes is said to prove it: 'I do not think that we should ever say of anything that it cannot be brought about by God. For since everything involved in truth and goodness depends on His omnipotence, I would not dare to say that God cannot make a mountain without a valley, or that one and two should not be three. I merely say that He has given me such a mind that I cannot conceive a mountain without a valley, or an aggregate of one and two which is not three, and that such things involve a contradiction in my conception'. Descartes (1970), pp. 236-237. See also pp. 11-12, 14-15, 150-151, 236-237, 240-241. La Croix argues, however, that Descartes does not really mean to contend that God can turn necessary impossibilities into possibilities.
    • (1980) Does God Have A Nature?
    • Plantinga, A.1
  • 56
    • 60950185987 scopus 로고
    • Descartes on god's ability to do the logically impossible
    • See Richard R. La Croix, 'Descartes on God's Ability to Do the Logically Impossible', Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (1984), pp. 455-475.
    • (1984) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.14 , pp. 455-475
    • La Croix, R.R.1
  • 57
    • 34447150521 scopus 로고
    • The doctrine of the trinity and the logic of relative identity
    • For the debates on the coherence of the trinity see James Cain, 'The Doctrine of the Trinity and the Logic of Relative Identity', Religious Studies 25 (1989), pp. 141-152;
    • (1989) Religious Studies , vol.25 , pp. 141-152
    • Cain, J.1
  • 58
    • 53249140790 scopus 로고
    • On the logical problem of the trinity
    • in his Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Richard Cartwright, 'On the Logical Problem of the Trinity', in his Philosophical Essays (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987);
    • (1987) Philosophical Essays
    • Cartwright, R.1
  • 60
    • 77951932503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trakakis (1997)
    • Trakakis (1997);
  • 61
    • 51649143621 scopus 로고
    • A trinity on a trinity on a trinity
    • John Zeis, 'A Trinity on a Trinity on a Trinity', Sophia 32 (1993), pp. 45-55;
    • (1993) Sophia , vol.32 , pp. 45-55
    • Zeis, J.1
  • 62
    • 54749134323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1986)
    • on the coherence of the incarnation see Thomas V. Morris, The Logic of God Incarnate, (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1986);
    • The Logic of God Incarnate
    • Morris, T.V.1
  • 63
    • 84981378441 scopus 로고
    • Reduplication and representational christology
    • Thomas V. Morris, 'Reduplication and Representational Christology', Modern Theology 2 (1986), pp. 319-326;
    • (1986) Modern Theology , vol.2 , pp. 319-326
    • Morris, T.V.1
  • 64
    • 77951931641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trakakis (1997)
    • Trakakis (1997);
  • 65
    • 51649135776 scopus 로고
    • A Gross and palpable contradiction?: Incarnation and consistency
    • KeithE. Yandell, 'A Gross and Palpable Contradiction?: Incarnation and Consistency', Sophia 33 (1994), pp. 30-45.
    • (1994) Sophia , vol.33 , pp. 30-45
    • Yandell, K.1
  • 66
    • 84971871467 scopus 로고
    • Omniscience, omnipotence and pantheism
    • Indeed, Francks argues that cases similar to Grim's entail a pantheism that is close to Spinoza's. See Richard Francks, 'Omniscience, Omnipotence and Pantheism', Philosophy 54 (1979), pp. 395-399.
    • (1979) Philosophy , vol.54 , pp. 395-399
    • Francks, R.1
  • 67
    • 77951912191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Throughout this paper I have assumed, for the sake of argument, that Grim is right in contending that God cannot know what I know in knowing (1). It is important to emphasise, however, that my argument is consistent with the claim that ultimately God can know what I know in knowing (1). I am indebted to Thomas Sullivan on this point.
    • Throughout this paper I have assumed, for the sake of argument, that Grim is right in contending that God cannot know what I know in knowing (1). It is important to emphasise, however, that my argument is consistent with the claim that ultimately God can know what I know in knowing (1). I am indebted to Thomas Sullivan on this point.
  • 68
    • 77951899436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Versions of this paper were read at the Pacific Regional Meeting of the Society of Christian Philosophers in Spokane in 2002 and the Eastern Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association in Philadelphia in 2002. I would like to thank all in the audiences. I would also like to thank the American Philosophical Association and the Philosophy Program at the Australian National University for their financial support. I am grateful to Harriet Baber, Karen Bennett, Lisa Bortolotti, Campbell Brown, Frank Jackson, Peter Ludlow, Karen Riley, Laura Schroeter, Charles Taliaferro and Keith Wyma for helpful discussion. I am particularly grateful to and an anonymous referee for for their useful comments and constructive suggestions. Finally, I would like to thank Patrick Grim, who opened my eyes to the interesting issues of divine omniscience
    • Versions of this paper were read at the Pacific Regional Meeting of the Society of Christian Philosophers in Spokane in 2002 and the Eastern Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association in Philadelphia in 2002. I would like to thank all in the audiences. I would also like to thank the American Philosophical Association and the Philosophy Program at the Australian National University for their financial support. I am grateful to Harriet Baber, Karen Bennett, Lisa Bortolotti, Campbell Brown, Frank Jackson, Peter Ludlow, Karen Riley, Laura Schroeter, Charles Taliaferro and Keith Wyma for helpful discussion. I am particularly grateful to Martin Davies, Graham Oppy, Daniel Stoljar, Thomas Sullivan, and an anonymous referee for International Journal for Philosophy of Religion for their useful comments and constructive suggestions. Finally, I would like to thank Patrick Grim, who opened my eyes to the interesting issues of divine omniscience.
    • International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
    • Davies, M.1    Oppy, G.2    Stoljar, D.3    Sullivan, T.4


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.