메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 2, Issue 4, 1996, Pages 359-380

Should the law distinguish between intention and (mere) foresight?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77950062141     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325200000574     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (8)

References (43)
  • 1
    • 85022774144 scopus 로고
    • See An INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION (J.H. Bums & H.LA. Hart eds., ).
    • This terminology originated with Bentham. See An INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION (J.H. Bums & H.LA. Hart eds., 1970), ch. 8.
    • (1970) This terminology originated with Bentham. , Issue.8
  • 2
    • 85022803386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It should he kept in mind, however, that I assume throughout that intended consequences are themselves always to some extent foreseen, so that the real issue is what has to be added to foresight in order to produce intention.
    • From here on I shall generally drop the “merely.” It should he kept in mind, however, that I assume throughout that intended consequences are themselves always to some extent foreseen, so that the real issue is what has to be added to foresight in order to produce intention.
    • From here on I shall generally drop the “merely.
  • 3
    • 85022875779 scopus 로고
    • For a recent, sympathetic discussion of the DDE, see Joseph M. Boyle, Jr., 90 ETHICS 527-38 (1980). Among its more sophisticated critics are Jonathan Bennett, Morality and Consfqurncrs, in THE TANNER LECTURES ON HUMAN VALUES, (Sterling McMurrin ed., 1981); Nancy Davis, The Doctrine of Double Effect: Problems of Interpretation, 65 PACIFIC PHIL. Q. 107-23 (1984); and Shelly Kagan, THE LiMrrsoF MORALITY, ch.
    • For a recent, sympathetic discussion of the DDE, see Joseph M. Boyle, Jr., Toward Understanding the IMnciple of Double Effect, 90 ETHICS 527-38 (1980). Among its more sophisticated critics are Jonathan Bennett, Morality and Consfqurncrs, in THE TANNER LECTURES ON HUMAN VALUES, vol. 2 (Sterling McMurrin ed., 1981); Nancy Davis, The Doctrine of Double Effect: Problems of Interpretation, 65 PACIFIC PHIL. Q. 107-23 (1984); and Shelly Kagan, THE LiMrrsoF MORALITY, ch. 4 (1989).
    • (1989) Toward Understanding the IMnciple of Double Effect , vol.2 , pp. 4
  • 4
    • 85022806778 scopus 로고
    • For example, certain forms of governmental discrimination against a suspect class may be constitutional if the government acts knowingly but not if it acts purposefully; see discussion in Kenneth W. Simons, Rethinking Mental States, 72 B. U. L. REV. sec. I
    • The distinction also appears to play a role in the civil law. For example, certain forms of governmental discrimination against a suspect class may be constitutional if the government acts knowingly but not if it acts purposefully; see discussion in Kenneth W. Simons, Rethinking Mental States, 72 B. U. L. REV. sec. I (1992).
    • (1992) The distinction also appears to play a role in the civil law.
  • 6
    • 85022815148 scopus 로고
    • [] 41 All E.R. In addition, physicians and other medical personnel (such as Dr. Jack Kervorkian) who have been accused of mercy-killing or assisted suicide often attempt to defend themselves by arguing that their actions were not motivated by an intention to cause death (even though that was certainly a foreseen consequence).
    • Hyam [1974] 41 All E.R. In addition, physicians and other medical personnel (such as Dr. Jack Kervorkian) who have been accused of mercy-killing or assisted suicide often attempt to defend themselves by arguing that their actions were not motivated by an intention to cause death (even though that was certainly a foreseen consequence).
    • (1974) Hyam
  • 7
    • 85022825528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • passim, for an extensive discussion of all of the relevant conditions.
    • See Boyle, Hyam note 3, passim, for an extensive discussion of all of the relevant conditions.
    • Hyam note 3
    • Boyle1
  • 9
    • 85022883783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Id. at 156.
    • Id. , pp. 156
  • 10
    • 85022830014 scopus 로고
    • (Alvin I. Goldman & Jacgwon Kim cds., 1978), and Robert Audi, Intending, Intentional Action, andDesire, in THE WA\S OF DESIRE (|ocl Marks ed., 1986). Such a view has also enjoyed considerable support in legal circles. &*Joshua Dressier, UNDERSTANDING CRIMINAL IAW
    • See, e.g., Monroe C. Beardsley, Intending, in VALUES AND MORALS (Alvin I. Goldman & Jacgwon Kim cds., 1978), and Robert Audi, Intending, Intentional Action, andDesire, in THE WA\S OF DESIRE (|ocl Marks ed., 1986). Such a view has also enjoyed considerable support in legal circles. &*Joshua Dressier, UNDERSTANDING CRIMINAL IAW 98-99 (1987).
    • (1987) Intending, in VALUES AND MORALS , pp. 98-99
    • Beardsley, M.C.1
  • 11
    • 85022817824 scopus 로고
    • Additional criticisms of the desire model are found in Michael Moore, in ISSUES IN CONTEMPORARY LEGAL PHIIJOSOPHY 246 (Ruth Gavison ed., ) and Duff, Intending, in VALUES AND MORALS note 7, at
    • Additional criticisms of the desire model are found in Michael Moore, Intentions and Mens Rea, in ISSUES IN CONTEMPORARY LEGAL PHIIJOSOPHY 246 (Ruth Gavison ed., 1987) and Duff, Intending, in VALUES AND MORALS note 7, at 52-73.
    • (1987) Intentions and Mens Rea , pp. 52-73
  • 12
    • 85022906685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Duff, Intentions and Mens Rea note 7, at 61-G3. Although I cannot argue for it here, I believe this proposal is also vulnerable to the criticism mentioned in the text.
    • A good example of this sort of strategy is Duffs “test of failure”; see Duff, Intentions and Mens Rea note 7, at 61-G3. Although I cannot argue for it here, I believe this proposal is also vulnerable to the criticism mentioned in the text.
    • A good example of this sort of strategy is Duffs “test of failure
  • 13
    • 85022783269 scopus 로고
    • A good example of this sort of strategy is Duffs “test of failure”; note 3, at 100-05. Further problems are noted in Alan W. Nome, Oblique Intention and Legal Ihlitics, CRIM. L. R.
    • This line of criticism is developed more fully in Bennett, A good example of this sort of strategy is Duffs “test of failure”; note 3, at 100-05. Further problems are noted in Alan W. Nome, Oblique Intention and Legal Ihlitics, CRIM. L. R. 795-96 (1989).
    • (1989) This line of criticism is developed more fully in Bennett , pp. 795-796
  • 18
    • 85022740945 scopus 로고
    • in REsroNsmiLTTY, CHARACTER, AND THE EMOTIONS 348 (Ferdinand Schoeman cd., ).
    • Gerald Dworkin, Intention, Forestealnlity, and Responsibility, in REsroNsmiLTTY, CHARACTER, AND THE EMOTIONS 348 (Ferdinand Schoeman cd., 1987).
    • (1987) Intention, Forestealnlity, and Responsibility
    • Dworkin, G.1
  • 19
    • 85022838226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Id. at 351.
    • Id. , pp. 351
  • 20
    • 85022814835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Id. at 352.
    • Id. , pp. 352
  • 21
    • 85022843584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 352 (emphasis added).
    • Id. at 352 (emphasis added).
    • Id.
  • 22
    • 85022762702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, the claim that, in cases of indirectly intended harm, the agent is more able to alter his plans than in cases of directly intended harm, would seem to be true only if everything is not equal, i.e., only in cases where the indirectly intended consequence is not required for the achievement of the agent's goal.
    • Moreover, some of Dworkin's suggestions seem premised upon a misunderstanding of what is required to defend the direct/indirect distinction. For example, the claim that, in cases of indirectly intended harm, the agent is more able to alter his plans than in cases of directly intended harm, would seem to be true only if everything is not equal, i.e., only in cases where the indirectly intended consequence is not required for the achievement of the agent's goal.
    • Moreover, some of Dworkin's suggestions seem premised upon a misunderstanding of what is required to defend the direct/indirect distinction.
  • 23
  • 26
    • 0004273012 scopus 로고
    • In fact, the criminal law does evince a concern with a person's intrinsic objectives, as is evidenced (for example) by the general willingness to classify reckless homicide as murder where the conduct involved has no redeeming social value; see George Fletcher
    • In fact, the criminal law does evince a concern with a person's intrinsic objectives, as is evidenced (for example) by the general willingness to classify reckless homicide as murder where the conduct involved has no redeeming social value; see George Fletcher, RETHINKING CRIMINAL LAW 265 (1978).
    • (1978) RETHINKING CRIMINAL LAW , pp. 265
  • 27
    • 85022792684 scopus 로고
    • 1 K.B.616
    • [1915] 1 K.B.616.
    • (1915)
  • 29
    • 85022744542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Id. at 437.
    • Id. , pp. 437
  • 30
    • 5344260032 scopus 로고
    • Oilier important issues that need to be addressed in cases of this sort are discussed by Duff, 9 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUDIES
    • Oilier important issues that need to be addressed in cases of this sort are discussed by Duff, Intentions Legal and Philosophical, 9 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUDIES 84-85 (1989).
    • (1989) Intentions Legal and Philosophical , pp. 84-85
  • 32
    • 85022823061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Id. at 426.
    • Id. , pp. 426
  • 34
    • 85022806812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 113 (emphasis in original).
    • Duff, Id. note 7 note 7, at 113 (emphasis in original).
    • Id. note 7 note 7
    • Duff1
  • 36
    • 85022754257 scopus 로고
    • 20 J. VALUE INQUIRY37-39. Bennett seems to be making a similar point when he asserts that “[t]hc concept of intention has a role [only] in second-order morality, i.e., in guiding judgments on people in respect of past actions,” and that “it is a mistake to think of first-order morality-morality for the guidance of deliberating agents-as making any use of the concept of the delibcrator's future intentions” (Bennett, Ricirr AND WRONG note 3, at 97).
    • Sanford Le\y, ThePrintipbof DoubU'Effect, 20 J. VALUE INQUIRY37-39 (1986). Bennett seems to be making a similar point when he asserts that “[t]hc concept of intention has a role [only] in second-order morality, i.e., in guiding judgments on people in respect of past actions,” and that “it is a mistake to think of first-order morality-morality for the guidance of deliberating agents-as making any use of the concept of the delibcrator's future intentions” (Bennett, Ricirr AND WRONG note 3, at 97).
    • (1986) Sanford Le\y, ThePrintipbof DoubU'Effect
  • 38
    • 85022748376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boyle, for example, argues that the DDE is best construed as a principle at justification rather than a principle of excuse. note 7 at 112. He seems to assume, however, that consequentialists cannot recognize such harms; for a criticism of this assumption, see Gorr, (forthcoming in PiiiLOSoruiA).
    • Duff Boyle, for example, argues that the DDE is best construed as a principle at justification rather than a principle of excuse. note 7 at 112. He seems to assume, however, that consequentialists cannot recognize such harms; for a criticism of this assumption, see Gorr, Motiws and Rightness (forthcoming in PiiiLOSoruiA).
    • Motiws and Rightness
    • Duff1
  • 40
    • 85022830988 scopus 로고
    • Duff is an objectivist with respect to both since he has argued that “What relates me to a criminal harm as a responsible agent is partly the subjective connection of my action to that harm, and partly its objective connection.” (Duff, Motiws and Rightness note note 7, at 204fi). For a rigorous defense of a thoroughgoing subjectivist account of culpability, see Michael Zimmerman, AN ESSAY ON MORAL RESPONSIBILITY
    • I should note that while I am an “objectivist” with respect to questions of liability (since I hold that the latter is not determined exclusively by the agent's psychological states) I am a “subjectivist” with respect to culpability (which I maintain is so determined). Duff is an objectivist with respect to both since he has argued that “What relates me to a criminal harm as a responsible agent is partly the subjective connection of my action to that harm, and partly its objective connection.” (Duff, Motiws and Rightness note note 7, at 204fi). For a rigorous defense of a thoroughgoing subjectivist account of culpability, see Michael Zimmerman, AN ESSAY ON MORAL RESPONSIBILITY (1988).
    • (1988) I should note that while I am an “objectivist” with respect to questions of liability (since I hold that the latter is not determined exclusively by the agent's psychological states) I am a “subjectivist” with respect to culpability (which I maintain is so determined).
  • 42
    • 85022788259 scopus 로고
    • As Gilbert Harman has observed, side effects will normally not be as salient as means or ends, a fact that is of considerable importance in a theory of rational decision making. Set Harman
    • As Gilbert Harman has observed, side effects will normally not be as salient as means or ends, a fact that is of considerable importance in a theory of rational decision making. Set Harman, CHANGE IN VIEW, ch. 9 (1986).
    • (1986) CHANGE IN VIEW , Issue.9


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.