메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 5, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 73-97

Vice and reason

Author keywords

Aristotle; Character; Decision (prohairesis); Ethics; Fine; Pleasure; Reason; Regret; Self love; Vice

Indexed keywords


EID: 77950054429     PISSN: 13824554     EISSN: 15728609     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/A:1011416908374     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (23)

References (37)
  • 1
    • 77950036447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The sparseness of his account becomes especially clear when we compare the relevant parts of Aquinas' Summa Theologiae (ST) with the corresponding parts of the Ethics. Aquinas sees that to understand sin, we must distinguish its different sources. The three that he discusses are passion, ignorance, and deliberate badness (certa malitia). Deliberate badness is the characteristic attitude of the vicious person (It is not confined to the vicious person; see Aquinas, ST 1-2 q71 a4; q78 a2-3). We might reasonably ask, then, whether Aristotle has any plausible account of an attitude that corresponds to deliberate badness, as Aquinas conceives it. Much of what I will say to expound Aristotle is adapted from Aquinas, but I do not intend to discuss Aquinas here
    • The sparseness of his account becomes especially clear when we compare the relevant parts of Aquinas' Summa Theologiae (ST) with the corresponding parts of the Ethics. Aquinas sees that to understand sin, we must distinguish its different sources. The three that he discusses are passion, ignorance, and deliberate badness (certa malitia). Deliberate badness is the characteristic attitude of the vicious person (It is not confined to the vicious person; see Aquinas, ST 1-2 q71 a4; q78 a2-3). We might reasonably ask, then, whether Aristotle has any plausible account of an attitude that corresponds to deliberate badness, as Aquinas conceives it. Much of what I will say to expound Aristotle is adapted from Aquinas, but I do not intend to discuss Aquinas here.
  • 2
    • 84974027155 scopus 로고
    • The nature of immorality
    • A vigorous statement of some of these objections to Aristotle is presented by E.F. Paul, F.D. Miller and J. Paul (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell at pp. 29-31
    • A vigorous statement of some of these objections to Aristotle is presented by Jean Hampton, "The Nature of Immorality," in E.F. Paul, F.D. Miller and J. Paul (eds.), Foundations of Moral and Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990), pp. 22-44, at pp. 29-31.
    • (1990) Foundations of Moral and Political Philosophy , pp. 22-44
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 3
    • 31144446245 scopus 로고
    • Plato and Aristotle on friendship and altruism
    • A more carefully defended statement of the view that Aristotle is inconsistent appears
    • A more carefully defended statement of the view that Aristotle is inconsistent appears in Julia Annas, "Plato and Aristotle on Friendship and Altruism," Mind 86 (1977), pp. 532-554.
    • (1977) Mind , vol.86 , pp. 532-554
    • Annas, J.1
  • 4
    • 0004216889 scopus 로고
    • Her argument is criticized by Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Her argument is criticized by Sarah Broadie, Ethics with Aristotle (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 177n41.
    • (1991) Ethics with Aristotle
    • Broadie, S.1
  • 5
    • 0003986649 scopus 로고
    • See (hereinafter cited as EN) 1166b6, 12, 1168a31, 1169a15, 1110b28, 30, 1113b7, 14 (the clearest sign of the equivalence of agathos / epieikês and of kakos and phaulos), 1115a13. In discussing vice in general, Aristotle mentions adikia and akolasia as salient examples, 1114a5. I cite the EN from the edition of I. Bywater (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • See Nicomachean Ethics (hereinafter cited as EN) 1166b6, 12, 1168a31, 1169a15, 1110b28, 30, 1113b7, 14 (the clearest sign of the equivalence of agathos / epieikês and of kakos and phaulos), 1115a13. In discussing vice in general, Aristotle mentions adikia and akolasia as salient examples, 1114a5. I cite the EN from the edition of I. Bywater (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1892).
    • (1892) Nicomachean Ethics
  • 6
    • 77950024950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This phrase is deleted by some editors
    • This phrase is deleted by some editors.
  • 7
    • 0041096913 scopus 로고
    • I reject Bywater's deletion of the passage anthrôpou de . . .. ei d'houtô, 1098a12-14. See his note in his edition, and his Oxford: Oxford University Press The point I have made about the transition from kata logon ê ouk aneu logou to meta logou is one of a number of indications that Bywater is wrong to say that this passage is a mere duplicate
    • I reject Bywater's deletion of the passage anthrôpou de . . .. ei d'houtô, 1098a12-14. See his note in his edition, and his Contributions to the Textual Criticism of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1892), p. 24f. The point I have made about the transition from kata logon ê ouk aneu logou to meta logou is one of a number of indications that Bywater is wrong to say that this passage is a mere duplicate.
    • (1892) Contributions to the Textual Criticism of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics
  • 8
    • 77950029503 scopus 로고
    • This use of meta logou as broader than kata logon, and as equivalent to ouk aneu logou, reappears in 1144b26-8, if we accept Hardie's and Smith's interpretation. See ed. 2 Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • This use of meta logou as broader than kata logon, and as equivalent to ouk aneu logou, reappears in 1144b26-8, if we accept Hardie's and Smith's interpretation. See W.F.R. Hardie, Aristotle's Ethical Theory, ed. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), pp. 237-239,
    • (1980) Aristotle's Ethical Theory , pp. 237-239
    • Hardie, W.F.R.1
  • 9
    • 77950055343 scopus 로고
    • Aristotelica
    • and, Their interpretation is strongly supported by the context of this passage, and by our passage in I 7
    • and J.A. Smith, "Aristotelica," Classical Quarterly 14 (1920), pp. 16-22. Their interpretation is strongly supported by the context of this passage, and by our passage in I 7.
    • (1920) Classical Quarterly , vol.14 , pp. 16-22
    • Smith, J.A.1
  • 10
    • 77950047717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or perhaps "against."
    • Or perhaps "against."
  • 11
    • 77950050438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We might (less plausibly) take panta as the subject of homophônei
    • We might (less plausibly) take panta as the subject of homophônei.
  • 12
    • 77950055778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A good case can be made for understanding logos as "rational standard," and hence for understanding kata ton orthon logon as "in accordance with the correct rational standard" rather than "in accordance with correct reason." As far as I can see, this issue does not affect my main claims
    • A good case can be made for understanding logos as "rational standard," and hence for understanding kata ton orthon logon as "in accordance with the correct rational standard" rather than "in accordance with correct reason." As far as I can see, this issue does not affect my main claims.
  • 13
    • 77950047716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In EN, 1135b20, mê probouleusas de is not quite accurate, in the light of 1142b18-20
    • In EN, 1135b20, mê probouleusas de is not quite accurate, in the light of 1142b18-20.
  • 14
    • 77950033645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since Book VII is a book common to the Eudemian Ethics and the EN the reference to what has been said before may be a reference to the former work
    • Since Book VII is a book common to the Eudemian Ethics and the EN the reference to what has been said before may be a reference to the former work.
  • 15
    • 77950038745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The first answer conflicts with Aristotle's discussion of good deliberation (euboulia). He does not allow good deliberation to anyone except the prudent person, who also grasps the right end (EN, 1142b29-33). He does not agree, then, that goodness of deliberation can be assessed purely instrumentally, without reference to the end involved
    • The first answer conflicts with Aristotle's discussion of good deliberation (euboulia). He does not allow good deliberation to anyone except the prudent person, who also grasps the right end (EN, 1142b29-33). He does not agree, then, that goodness of deliberation can be assessed purely instrumentally, without reference to the end involved.
  • 16
    • 0040598810 scopus 로고
    • I have discussed this further in Oxford: Oxford University Press, Section 203
    • I have discussed this further in Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), Section 203.
    • (1988) Aristotle's First Principles
  • 17
    • 77950060745 scopus 로고
    • Thought and action in Aristotle
    • This claim about prohairesis and boulêsis, in which I follow Oxford: Blackwell, is not indisputable
    • This claim about prohairesis and boulêsis, in which I follow G.E.M. Anscombe, "Thought and Action in Aristotle," in Collected Papers, I (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981), pp. 66-77, is not indisputable.
    • (1981) Collected Papers, I , pp. 66-77
    • Anscombe, G.E.M.1
  • 19
    • 77950058713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fact that such questions can be raised suggests that Aristotle thinks people could reject the other-regarding virtues on the basis of a conception of their happiness that includes this judgment about concern for others. he suggests that very few people would think the virtues have no place in happiness; they dispute about the relative importance of external goods, since most people think they can get by with just a little virtue, and ought to pursue a high level of other goods (1323a27-38). Apparently, then, we can reach this level of explicitness about happiness, and still form views that encourage the vices
    • This does not by itself show that he has any articulate or explicit conception of happiness. Should we, then, infer that the vicious person's error consists in his failure to form an explicit conception of happiness? It is unlikely that Aristotle means us to infer this. He does not seem to take the absence of an explicit conception of happiness to be a necessary condition for vice. In his discussion of self-love, he mentions people who take any non-instrumental concern for the good of others to conflict with one's own good (EN, 1168a29-35). The fact that such questions can be raised suggests that Aristotle thinks people could reject the other-regarding virtues on the basis of a conception of their happiness that includes this judgment about concern for others. In Politics, VII 1, he suggests that very few people would think the virtues have no place in happiness; they dispute about the relative importance of external goods, since most people think they can get by with just a little virtue, and ought to pursue a high level of other goods (1323a27-38). Apparently, then, we can reach this level of explicitness about happiness, and still form views that encourage the vices.
    • Politics , vol.7 , pp. 1
  • 20
    • 0040029461 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's conception of to kalon
    • Aristotle's First Principles, Section 237, I say more about the fine. What I say has been criticized by
    • In Aristotle's First Principles, Section 237, I say more about the fine. What I say has been criticized by Kelly Rogers, "Aristotle's Conception of to kalon," Ancient Philosophy 13 (1993), pp. 355-371,
    • (1993) Ancient Philosophy , vol.13 , pp. 355-371
    • Rogers, K.1
  • 21
    • 0040622643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reason, moral virtue, and moral value
    • and by M. Frede and G. Striker (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press esp. pp. 102-112. Rogers and Cooper add further helpful discussion on other aspects of the fine. In this paper I do not rely on the connexion between the fine and the common good (though it seems to me to make some of Aristotle's contrasts between virtue and vice more plausible), but on the connexion between the fine and reason (which is perhaps under-estimated by Rogers and Cooper)
    • and by John Cooper, "Reason, Moral Virtue, and Moral Value," in M. Frede and G. Striker (eds.), Rationality in Greek Thought (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 81-114, esp. pp. 102-112. Rogers and Cooper add further helpful discussion on other aspects of the fine. In this paper I do not rely on the connexion between the fine and the common good (though it seems to me to make some of Aristotle's contrasts between virtue and vice more plausible), but on the connexion between the fine and reason (which is perhaps under-estimated by Rogers and Cooper).
    • (1996) Rationality in Greek Thought , pp. 81-114
    • Cooper, J.1
  • 22
    • 77950030065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a bit too brief. I am not saying that only virtuous people can desire or choose virtuous actions because they are fine (to say so would be inconsistent with, e.g., EN, 1116a28-9, 1179b29-31), but that only virtuous people decide, on the basis of a correct prohairesis, on virtuous actions for their own sake because they are fine
    • This is a bit too brief. I am not saying that only virtuous people can desire or choose virtuous actions because they are fine (to say so would be inconsistent with, e.g., EN, 1116a28-9, 1179b29-31), but that only virtuous people decide, on the basis of a correct prohairesis, on virtuous actions for their own sake because they are fine.
  • 23
    • 77950044745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or perhaps I should say "may agree." Perhaps not every vice involves choice of actions because they are fine; but if some involve it, or do not exclude it, choice of actions because they are fine cannot be a distinguishing mark of virtue
    • Or perhaps I should say "may agree." Perhaps not every vice involves choice of actions because they are fine; but if some involve it, or do not exclude it, choice of actions because they are fine cannot be a distinguishing mark of virtue.
  • 24
    • 77950047486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I read oregesthai tou kalou
    • I read oregesthai tou kalou.
  • 25
    • 77950033444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. EN, III 4 (though this chapter is not free of difficulty)
    • Cf. EN, III 4 (though this chapter is not free of difficulty).
  • 26
    • 84872421184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 1358b38-1359a5
    • See Rhetoric, 1390a15-17, 1358b38-1359a5.
    • Rhetoric
  • 27
    • 77950039393 scopus 로고
    • I have discussed the, Oxford: Oxford University Press, Section 208
    • I have discussed the Phaedrus in Plato's Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), Section 208.
    • (1995) Phaedrus in Plato's Ethics
  • 28
    • 77950048614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See EN, 1116a17-29, and cf. 1117a4-9, 1128b16-31
    • See EN, 1116a17-29, and cf. 1117a4-9, 1128b16-31.
  • 29
    • 77950040975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In requiring a virtuous person's aims to be thoroughly good-dependent, Aristotle does not imply that the content of our non-rational desires and inclinations is irrelevant to virtue. He includes our initial desires, preferences, and aspirations among the starting points for the reflexion that produces a correct conception of the good; but he does not take a conception of the good to provide simply a strategy for the satisfaction of our pre-reflective desires
    • In requiring a virtuous person's aims to be thoroughly good-dependent, Aristotle does not imply that the content of our non-rational desires and inclinations is irrelevant to virtue. He includes our initial desires, preferences, and aspirations among the starting points for the reflexion that produces a correct conception of the good; but he does not take a conception of the good to provide simply a strategy for the satisfaction of our pre-reflective desires.
  • 30
    • 0037958548 scopus 로고
    • A related contrast between virtuous and vicious people is developed by Oxford: Oxford Unviersity Press She argues that the vicious person does not give the same role to praxis, as opposed to poiêsis, in his life as the virtuous person gives it. She correctly says that vicious actions do not constitute their own ends in the way that virtuous actions constitute their own ends. I am trying to explain what further feature of the vicious person explains this fact
    • A related contrast between virtuous and vicious people is developed by Nancy Sherman, The Fabric of Character (Oxford: Oxford Unviersity Press, 1989), pp. 113-117. She argues that the vicious person does not give the same role to praxis, as opposed to poiêsis, in his life as the virtuous person gives it. She correctly says that vicious actions do not constitute their own ends in the way that virtuous actions constitute their own ends. I am trying to explain what further feature of the vicious person explains this fact.
    • (1989) The Fabric of Character , pp. 113-117
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 31
    • 77950044416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We cannot remove this difficulty by saying that Aristotle is concerned only with the specific vice of intemperance. Even if we say this about Book VII, where he is concerned with incontinence versus intemperance, we cannot say it about Book IX; for the description of vice in general claims that vicious people aim at pleasure (EN, 1166b6-11)
    • We cannot remove this difficulty by saying that Aristotle is concerned only with the specific vice of intemperance. Even if we say this about Book VII, where he is concerned with incontinence versus intemperance, we cannot say it about Book IX; for the description of vice in general claims that vicious people aim at pleasure (EN, 1166b6-11).
  • 32
    • 77950034763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will use "regret" simply to represent metameleia, without implying that this is always the most appropriate English rendering
    • I will use "regret" simply to represent metameleia, without implying that this is always the most appropriate English rendering.
  • 33
    • 77950031828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In EN, 1166b12-13 I read pepraktai, dia tên mochthêrian misousi te kai pheuogousi to zên, following one ms
    • In EN, 1166b12-13 I read pepraktai, dia tên mochthêrian misousi te kai pheuogousi to zên, following one ms.
  • 34
    • 0003894851 scopus 로고
    • My non-pejorative use of "self-satisfaction" is partly derived from Oxford: Oxford University Press Section 154
    • My non-pejorative use of "self-satisfaction" is partly derived from T.H. Green, Prolegomena to Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1882), Section 154.
    • (1882) Prolegomena to Ethics
    • Green, T.H.1
  • 35
    • 77950065030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle calls this error "ignorance about expedient things," "ignorance in the decision," and"universal ignorance," 1110b27-33. I will not discuss his reasons for taking it to be blameworthy error
    • Aristotle calls this error "ignorance about expedient things," "ignorance in the decision," and"universal ignorance," 1110b27-33. I will not discuss his reasons for taking it to be blameworthy error.
  • 36
    • 77950045377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They are ultimate in so far as they are worthy of choice apart from their contribution to any end outside them. They are subordinate, though not purely instrumental, to happiness
    • They are ultimate in so far as they are worthy of choice apart from their contribution to any end outside them. They are subordinate, though not purely instrumental, to happiness.
  • 37
    • 77950045160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I read versions of this paper in Oxford, Pittsburgh, and Princeton. I especially remember helpful comments by David Charles, Steven Quevedo, Jennifer Whiting, Susan Meyer, Victor Caston, John Cooper, and Michael Frede
    • I read versions of this paper in Oxford, Pittsburgh, and Princeton. I especially remember helpful comments by David Charles, Steven Quevedo, Jennifer Whiting, Susan Meyer, Victor Caston, John Cooper, and Michael Frede.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.