메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 34, Issue 4, 2004, Pages 675-691

Analytic conservatism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 7644219791     PISSN: 00071234     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0007123404000249     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (43)

References (26)
  • 1
    • 0004009383 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Conservatism might seem to be a poor relation in the contemporary political theory literature, partly because it presents less as an analytic theory and more as a kind of mystique. For example, there is no discussion of conservatism in Raymond Plant, Modern Political Thought (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991). For a discussion of conservative ideology that raises the contrast between conservatism as ideology and conservatism as disposition, see Anthony Quinton, 'Conservatism', in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds, A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), pp. 244-68. See also Samuel P. Huntington, 'Conservatism as an Ideology', American Political Science Review, 51 (1957), 454-73; Noel O'Sullivan, Conservatism (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1976); Roger Scruton, The Meaning of Conservatism (London: Penguin, 1980); Ted Honderich, Conservatism (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1990).
    • (1991) Modern Political Thought
    • Plant, R.1
  • 2
    • 0010088673 scopus 로고
    • Conservatism
    • Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • Conservatism might seem to be a poor relation in the contemporary political theory literature, partly because it presents less as an analytic theory and more as a kind of mystique. For example, there is no discussion of conservatism in Raymond Plant, Modern Political Thought (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991). For a discussion of conservative ideology that raises the contrast between conservatism as ideology and conservatism as disposition, see Anthony Quinton, 'Conservatism', in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds, A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), pp. 244-68. See also Samuel P. Huntington, 'Conservatism as an Ideology', American Political Science Review, 51 (1957), 454-73; Noel O'Sullivan, Conservatism (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1976); Roger Scruton, The Meaning of Conservatism (London: Penguin, 1980); Ted Honderich, Conservatism (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1990).
    • (1993) A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy , pp. 244-268
    • Quinton, A.1
  • 3
    • 34248987460 scopus 로고
    • Conservatism as an ideology
    • Conservatism might seem to be a poor relation in the contemporary political theory literature, partly because it presents less as an analytic theory and more as a kind of mystique. For example, there is no discussion of conservatism in Raymond Plant, Modern Political Thought (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991). For a discussion of conservative ideology that raises the contrast between conservatism as ideology and conservatism as disposition, see Anthony Quinton, 'Conservatism', in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds, A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), pp. 244-68. See also Samuel P. Huntington, 'Conservatism as an Ideology', American Political Science Review, 51 (1957), 454-73; Noel O'Sullivan, Conservatism (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1976); Roger Scruton, The Meaning of Conservatism (London: Penguin, 1980); Ted Honderich, Conservatism (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1990).
    • (1957) American Political Science Review , vol.51 , pp. 454-473
    • Huntington, S.P.1
  • 4
    • 84860772277 scopus 로고
    • New York: St. Martin's Press
    • Conservatism might seem to be a poor relation in the contemporary political theory literature, partly because it presents less as an analytic theory and more as a kind of mystique. For example, there is no discussion of conservatism in Raymond Plant, Modern Political Thought (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991). For a discussion of conservative ideology that raises the contrast between conservatism as ideology and conservatism as disposition, see Anthony Quinton, 'Conservatism', in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds, A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), pp. 244-68. See also Samuel P. Huntington, 'Conservatism as an Ideology', American Political Science Review, 51 (1957), 454-73; Noel O'Sullivan, Conservatism (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1976); Roger Scruton, The Meaning of Conservatism (London: Penguin, 1980); Ted Honderich, Conservatism (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1990).
    • (1976) Conservatism
    • O'Sullivan, N.1
  • 5
    • 0003836383 scopus 로고
    • London: Penguin
    • Conservatism might seem to be a poor relation in the contemporary political theory literature, partly because it presents less as an analytic theory and more as a kind of mystique. For example, there is no discussion of conservatism in Raymond Plant, Modern Political Thought (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991). For a discussion of conservative ideology that raises the contrast between conservatism as ideology and conservatism as disposition, see Anthony Quinton, 'Conservatism', in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds, A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), pp. 244-68. See also Samuel P. Huntington, 'Conservatism as an Ideology', American Political Science Review, 51 (1957), 454-73; Noel O'Sullivan, Conservatism (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1976); Roger Scruton, The Meaning of Conservatism (London: Penguin, 1980); Ted Honderich, Conservatism (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1990).
    • (1980) The Meaning of Conservatism
    • Scruton, R.1
  • 6
    • 0004337091 scopus 로고
    • London: Hamish Hamilton
    • Conservatism might seem to be a poor relation in the contemporary political theory literature, partly because it presents less as an analytic theory and more as a kind of mystique. For example, there is no discussion of conservatism in Raymond Plant, Modern Political Thought (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991). For a discussion of conservative ideology that raises the contrast between conservatism as ideology and conservatism as disposition, see Anthony Quinton, 'Conservatism', in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds, A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), pp. 244-68. See also Samuel P. Huntington, 'Conservatism as an Ideology', American Political Science Review, 51 (1957), 454-73; Noel O'Sullivan, Conservatism (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1976); Roger Scruton, The Meaning of Conservatism (London: Penguin, 1980); Ted Honderich, Conservatism (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1990).
    • (1990) Conservatism
    • Honderich, T.1
  • 7
    • 0004161626 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Freidrich Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960) makes the same point in his well-known piece on 'Why I am not a Conservative'. The situation can scarcely be said to have improved over the intervening years.
    • (1960) The Constitution of Liberty
    • Hayek, F.1
  • 8
    • 7644231793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conservatism
    • Edward Craig, ed., (London: Routledge), section 1
    • Anthony O'Hear, 'Conservatism', in Edward Craig, ed., Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1998), section 1.
    • (1998) Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • O'Hear, A.1
  • 10
    • 7644236059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Huntington, 'Conservatism as an Ideology' refers to conservatism as a 'positional' ideology, somewhat in the same spirit as our 'posture'; the conservative 'temper' is discussed by O'Hear, 'Conservatism'.
  • 11
    • 7644235797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Indeed, pragmatism might in some ways be a more descriptive term if it had not been appropriated for other purposes by Richard Rorty and his followers.
  • 12
    • 7644228112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We characterize Hayek as a conservative despite his famous protestations to the contrary because he, as much as any recent writer, provides the sort of analytic foundation for a principled defence of the status quo of the type that we take to be characteristic of the conservative position.
  • 13
    • 7644231794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We recognize other forms of analysis - such as the conceptual analysis offered in some parts of political philosophy - and their value; we merely argue that this economic form of analysis has value here.
  • 14
    • 52849103347 scopus 로고
    • Disciplinary contributions: Economics
    • Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds (Oxford: Basil Blackwell)
    • A fuller account of the distinction between issues of feasibility and desirability is provided by Geoffrey Brennan, 'Disciplinary Contributions: Economics', in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds, A Companion to Contemporary Political Theory (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1993), pp. 123-56.
    • (1993) A Companion to Contemporary Political Theory , pp. 123-156
    • Brennan, G.1
  • 16
    • 0034336793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Increasing returns, path dependence and the study of politics
    • Paul Pierson, 'Increasing Returns, Path Dependence and the Study of Politics', American Political Science Review, 94 (2000), 251-67, p. 251.
    • American Political Science Review , vol.94 , Issue.2000 , pp. 251-267
    • Pierson, P.1
  • 18
    • 7644241852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflections on the revolution in France
    • Muller
    • Edmund Burke, 'Reflections on the Revolution in France', in Muller, Conservatism, p. 99.
    • Conservatism , pp. 99
    • Burke, E.1
  • 19
    • 84937343311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republican liberty and resilience
    • In a different context, we have discussed the relationship between risk aversion and the idea of resilience that forms apart of the republican ideal of liberty; this might be seen as a particular aspect of conservative liberalism (see Geoffrey Brennan and Alan Hamlin, 'Republican Liberty and Resilience', The Monist, 84 (2001), 45-59).
    • (2001) The Monist , vol.84 , pp. 45-59
    • Brennan, G.1    Hamlin, A.2
  • 20
    • 7644235236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We leave on one side the distributional question involved in the case where the impact is positive for some and negative for others. In that case inequality aversion plays the role of risk aversion discussed here.
  • 21
    • 7644227860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This fact makes it clear that our discussion assumes cardinal measurability - mirroring the standard economic account of risk aversion. If either dimension of Figure 2 is only ordinally measurable, it is not possible to distinguish between convex and concave value functions (since they may identify the same ordering). We do not pursue the ordinal case here.
  • 22
    • 0034961603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A theory of conservatism
    • An interesting and rather different line of defence for a conservative posture is found in Hao Li, 'A Theory of Conservatism', Journal of Political Economy, 109 (2001), 617-36. Li's argument revolves around the proposition that placing the burden of proof on those who would secure change provides an appropriate incentive for information gathering and encourages a more informed decision-making body. For an exploration of related issues from an economic viewpoint, see Timur Kuran, 'The Tenacious Past: Theories of Personal and Collective Conservatism', Journal of Economic Behavior and Organisation, 10 (1988), 143-72.
    • (2001) Journal of Political Economy , vol.109 , pp. 617-636
    • Li, H.1
  • 23
    • 0000711169 scopus 로고
    • The tenacious past: Theories of personal and collective conservatism
    • An interesting and rather different line of defence for a conservative posture is found in Hao Li, 'A Theory of Conservatism', Journal of Political Economy, 109 (2001), 617-36. Li's argument revolves around the proposition that placing the burden of proof on those who would secure change provides an appropriate incentive for information gathering and encourages a more informed decision-making body. For an exploration of related issues from an economic viewpoint, see Timur Kuran, 'The Tenacious Past: Theories of Personal and Collective Conservatism', Journal of Economic Behavior and Organisation, 10 (1988), 143-72.
    • (1988) Journal of Economic Behavior and Organisation , vol.10 , pp. 143-172
    • Kuran, T.1
  • 24
    • 7644243277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that it is possible for posture to vary across dimensions - that is, the value function may be concave with respect to one argument and convex with respect to another. Beyond suggesting that the most thoroughgoing conservative would be one whose value function is convex in each of the arguments, we do not pursue the multidimensional case further here.
  • 25
    • 0021501701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Selecting people randomly
    • On the ex ante / expost distinction and its ethical relevance, see, for example, John Broome, 'Selecting People Randomly', Ethics, 95 (1984), 38-55; John Broome, 'Uncertainty and Fairness', Economic Journal, 94 (1984), 624-32.
    • (1984) Ethics , vol.95 , pp. 38-55
    • Broome, J.1
  • 26
    • 0021501701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Uncertainty and fairness
    • On the ex ante / expost distinction and its ethical relevance, see, for example, John Broome, 'Selecting People Randomly', Ethics, 95 (1984), 38-55; John Broome, 'Uncertainty and Fairness', Economic Journal, 94 (1984), 624-32.
    • Economic Journal , vol.94 , Issue.1984 , pp. 624-632
    • Broome, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.