메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 20, Issue 3, 2009, Pages 897-910

Softness in international law: A self-serving quest for new legal materials: A reply to Jean D'Aspremont

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 74849102178     PISSN: 09385428     EISSN: 14643596     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ejil/chp067     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (21)

References (38)
  • 1
    • 58149460573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Softness in International Law: A Self-Serving Quest for New Legal Materials
    • D'Aspremont, 'Softness in International Law: A Self-Serving Quest for New Legal Materials', 19 EJIL (2008) 1075.
    • (2008) EJIL , vol.19 , pp. 1075
    • D'Aspremont1
  • 3
    • 0031350675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The King's Many Bodies: The Self-Deconstruction of Law's Hierarchy
    • at 783
    • Teubner, 'The King's Many Bodies: The Self-Deconstruction of Law's Hierarchy', 31 Law & Society Review (1997) 763, at 783.
    • (1997) Law & Society Review , vol.31 , pp. 763
    • Teubner1
  • 4
    • 74849101182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Law as an Autopoietic System
    • The self-regulating theory of systems, called autopoiesis, is further discussed in, in R. Wolfrum and V. Roben (eds) 335
    • The self-regulating theory of systems, called autopoiesis, is further discussed in D'Amato, 'International Law as an Autopoietic System', in R. Wolfrum and V. Roben (eds), Developments of International Law in Treaty Making (2005), at 335.
    • (2005) Developments of International Law in Treaty Making
    • D'Amato1
  • 5
    • 74849128508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Law as a Unitary System
    • in D. Armstrong (ed.)
    • D'Amato, 'International Law as a Unitary System', in D. Armstrong (ed.), Routledge Handbook of International Law (2009), at 101.
    • (2009) Routledge Handbook of International Law , pp. 101
    • D'Amato1
  • 6
    • 74849089839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The environment is external to the system, by definition.
  • 7
    • 0003586486 scopus 로고
    • introduced the term 'performative' to account for the special case where the issuing of the utterance is the performance of an action: J.L. Austin
    • J.L. Austin introduced the term 'performative' to account for the special case where the issuing of the utterance is the performance of an action: J.L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (1962).
    • (1962) How to Do Things with Words
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 8
    • 74849128509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Basically the energy required to operate the filter would add external positive entropy to the system which would cancel out the negative entropy that the Demon was trying to achieve.
  • 9
    • 74849096478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Islamic advocate is going beyond the system of equal rights, in a fashion analogous to the problem with Maxwell's Demon. However, in legal argument, there is no a priori designation of the limits of a system.
  • 10
    • 0040560784 scopus 로고
    • Jurisdiction and Admissibility
    • Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. US)
    • Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. US), Jurisdiction and Admissibility [1984] ICJ Rep 392.
    • (1984) ICJ Rep , pp. 392
  • 11
    • 0039970269 scopus 로고
    • Trashing Customary International Law
    • I spell out this argument with examples from the Court's opinion in D'Amato
    • I spell out this argument with examples from the Court's opinion in D'Amato, 'Trashing Customary International Law', 81 AJIL (1987) 101.
    • (1987) AJIL , vol.81 , pp. 101
  • 12
    • 74849116597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • These are not necessarily the correct norms; they are simply the interventionist norms.
  • 13
    • 0042936563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Defence of Relative Normativity: Communitarian Values and the Nicaragua Case
    • Tasioulas, 'In Defence of Relative Normativity: Communitarian Values and the Nicaragua Case', 16 Oxford J Legal Stud (1996) 85.
    • (1996) Oxford J Legal Stud , vol.16 , pp. 85
    • Tasioulas1
  • 14
    • 0035402946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From Nuremberg to Kosovo: The Morality of Illegal International Law Reform
    • Buchanan, 'From Nuremberg to Kosovo: The Morality of Illegal International Law Reform', 111 Ethics (2001) 673.
    • (2001) Ethics , vol.111 , pp. 673
    • Buchanan, X.1
  • 15
    • 74849088799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Ibid., at 686.
  • 16
    • 74849118779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Selling protection was one of the earliest forms of crime. A group of armed bandits would go from farm to farm selling farmers protection against their own predation. Soon the bandits by cooptation became the king's soldiers, and the protection payments they extracted became known as 'taxation'. It is not altogether edifying to look too closely into the origins of governments.
  • 17
    • 74849101681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Franklin Delano Roosevelt's campaign in 1932 for the Presidency hardly mentioned or alluded to Prohibition or the widespread criminality accompanying it. He saw no point in getting into a debate over theology or morality. Yet when he was elected, one of the first things he did was to sponsor and encourage the 21st Amendment to the Constitution which repealed Prohibition.
  • 18
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • See, at 213. For an early critique see D'Amato, 'The Neo-Positivist Concept of International Law, 59 AJIL
    • See H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (1861), at 213. For an early critique see D'Amato, 'The Neo-Positivist Concept of International Law, 59 AJIL (1965) 321.
    • (1861) The Concept of Law , pp. 321
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 19
    • 74849108200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Exercising due caution, however, the international law system has anticipated maladaptive rules. These are called rules of jus cogens.
  • 20
    • 24944530175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, the authors of a widely read book reduce international law to game-theoretic strategies, thus losing sight of international law itself: see
    • For example, the authors of a widely read book reduce international law to game-theoretic strategies, thus losing sight of international law itself: see J.L. Goldsmith and E.A. Posner, The Limits of International Law (2005).
    • (2005) The Limits of International Law
    • Goldsmith, J.L.1    Posner, E.A.2
  • 21
    • 18144391347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally (2nd edn)
    • See generally M. Ridley, Evolution (2nd edn, 2004), at 91-132.
    • (2004) Evolution , pp. 91-132
    • Ridley, M.1
  • 22
    • 74849130112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In turn the predators also survived if they were partially successful in overcoming the prey's defences. However, if they were too successful and extinguished their prey, they would also become extinct.
  • 23
    • 0040998569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The perspective we now have on World War II is that Hitler's primary motivation was a genocidal desire to rid Europe of Jews and Slavs. These goals confl icted with Germany's optimal military strategy, to the consternation of his generals. In particular, Hitler's biggest military blunder was to leave Great Britain alone while opening a second-front war against the Soviet Union in 1941. His motivation was not military but rather to rid the world of Slavs (whom he sometimes confused with Jews). See, e.g
    • The perspective we now have on World War II is that Hitler's primary motivation was a genocidal desire to rid Europe of Jews and Slavs. These goals confl icted with Germany's optimal military strategy, to the consternation of his generals. In particular, Hitler's biggest military blunder was to leave Great Britain alone while opening a second-front war against the Soviet Union in 1941. His motivation was not military but rather to rid the world of Slavs (whom he sometimes confused with Jews). See, e.g., D. Irving, Hitler's War (2002).
    • (2002) Hitler's War
    • Irving, D.1
  • 24
    • 0004149207 scopus 로고
    • Are the norms 'selfish' in Dawkins's sense? See. International norms are selfish in the sense that they want to preserve the aggregate of states. But since each state has the same norms (international law does not vary in content from state to state), each state has the same genetic heritage, like identical twins. Thus the true phenotype - if we want to continue the Dawkinian analogy - is the international system and not the individual states within it
    • Are the norms 'selfish' in Dawkins's sense? See R. Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (1976). International norms are selfish in the sense that they want to preserve the aggregate of states. But since each state has the same norms (international law does not vary in content from state to state), each state has the same genetic heritage, like identical twins. Thus the true phenotype - if we want to continue the Dawkinian analogy - is the international system and not the individual states within it.
    • (1976) The Selfish Gene
    • Dawkins, R.1
  • 25
    • 33847410195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The ancient Hittites had already developed the following rules of international law: legal equality of states, sanctity of boundaries, pacta sunt servanda, diplomatic immunity, and return of fugitives. See (2nd edn)
    • The ancient Hittites had already developed the following rules of international law: legal equality of states, sanctity of boundaries, pacta sunt servanda, diplomatic immunity, and return of fugitives. See G. Beckman, Hittite Diplomatic Texts (2nd edn, 1999).
    • (1999) Hittite Diplomatic Texts
    • Beckman, G.1
  • 26
    • 74849090934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Customary law arguably more closely resembles common law.
  • 28
    • 0040205923 scopus 로고
    • His book was hailed as being realistic in according legal deference to the most powerful states. In fact his theory is deeply unrealistic. If international law gave greater preference and privileges to powerful states over the weaker states, then the latter would reject it. Law is a constraint on power, not a servant of power. Moreover there would be conceptual absurdities: for example, if a state acquires nuclear weapons, will it suddenly get more rights under international law? And who would parcel out those extra rights? And who would defer to them?
    • C. De Visscher, Theory and Reality in Public International Law (1957), at 149. His book was hailed as being realistic in according legal deference to the most powerful states. In fact his theory is deeply unrealistic. If international law gave greater preference and privileges to powerful states over the weaker states, then the latter would reject it. Law is a constraint on power, not a servant of power. Moreover there would be conceptual absurdities: for example, if a state acquires nuclear weapons, will it suddenly get more rights under international law? And who would parcel out those extra rights? And who would defer to them?.
    • (1957) Theory and Reality in Public International Law , pp. 149
    • De Visscher, C.1
  • 29
    • 74849096332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In addition, different observers will observe the emergence of a path at different times.
  • 30
    • 74849133399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Some writers regard the term 'state practice' as including opinio juris. Clarity is served, however, by keeping apart the material and psychological elements of custom.
  • 31
    • 0041433533 scopus 로고
    • Customary International Law: The Problem of Treaties
    • Many states engage in torture; does that mean it is a general practice of states? Professor Arthur Weisburd so asserted, in a criticism of my views in Weisburd,
    • Many states engage in torture; does that mean it is a general practice of states? Professor Arthur Weisburd so asserted, in a criticism of my views in Weisburd, 'Customary International Law: The Problem of Treaties', 31 Vanderbilt J Transn'l L (1988) 1.
    • (1988) Vanderbilt J Transn'l L , vol.31 , pp. 1
  • 32
    • 0042435845 scopus 로고
    • Custom and Treaty: A Response to Professor Weisburd
    • I replied that the practice of states was to outlaw and criminalize torture; this nearuniversal practice belied the claim that the illegal act of torture constituted international customary-law practice
    • I replied that the practice of states was to outlaw and criminalize torture; this nearuniversal practice belied the claim that the illegal act of torture constituted international customary-law practice: see D'Amato, 'Custom and Treaty: A Response to Professor Weisburd', 21 Vanderbilt J Transn'l L (1988) 459.
    • (1988) Vanderbilt J Transn'l L , vol.21 , pp. 459
    • D'Amato1
  • 33
    • 0011863145 scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of articulation as an objective substitute for opinion juris, see
    • For a discussion of articulation as an objective substitute for opinion juris, see A. D'Amato, The Concept of Custom in International Law (1971), at 74-87.
    • (1971) The Concept of Custom in International Law , pp. 74-87
    • D'Amato, A.1
  • 34
    • 74849083327 scopus 로고
    • International Law Commission
    • International Law Commission, Y earbook (1950), at 26.
    • (1950) Yearbook , pp. 26
  • 35
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • In other words, the rule of law is the source of the rule of law. This seemingly paradoxical conclusion was reached, and I believe proven, by H.L.A. Hart in his famous
    • In other words, the rule of law is the source of the rule of law. This seemingly paradoxical conclusion was reached, and I believe proven, by H.L.A. Hart in his famous The Concept of Law (1961).
    • (1961) The Concept of Law
  • 36
    • 84922953135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal Argument
    • See M. Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal Argument (2006).
    • (2006)
    • Koskenniemi, M.1
  • 38
    • 74849103915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The tipping point was the Court's finding that states are presumptively free to act unless blocked by a rule of international law. But international law is clearly not a set of discrete rules as legal positivism asserts. Quite the contrary: the rules are like valleys in a fitness landscape, the space between rules is hilly country. The base of a valley acts as a strange attractor upon nearby contentions, pulling them down into a rule if there is no competing contention. But in any confl ict or controversy, there are always two sides to the story, two competing contentions. The valley is not deep enough to attract both contentions; they end up on the side of a hill. In brief, law is everywhere; it has greater attraction at low levels on the fitness landscape. But when it is not at low levels, it is still stronger than no law at all. There is no lawless zone where states have freedom of action.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.