-
4
-
-
79958998965
-
Die Wissenschaftslehre Bolzanos
-
Abhandlungen der Fries'schen Schule (N. F.); pp. 452-53
-
H. Scholz, "Die Wissenschaftslehre Bolzanos. Eine Jahrhundert-Betrachtung." Abhandlungen der Fries'schen Schule (N. F.) 6 (1937), 399-472; cf. pp. 452-53
-
(1937)
Eine Jahrhundert-Betrachtung
, vol.6
, pp. 399-472
-
-
Scholz, H.1
-
5
-
-
33646715525
-
-
Stockholm
-
J. Berg, Bolzano's Logic. Stockholm 1962, pp. 161-62
-
(1962)
Bolzano's Logic
, pp. 161-162
-
-
Berg, J.1
-
6
-
-
70449977500
-
Kantstudien, Ergänzungshefte
-
G. Buhl, "Ableitbarkeit und Abfolge in der Wissenschaftstheorie Bolzanos." Kantstudien, Ergänzungshefte 83 (1961), cf. pp. 57-64
-
(1961)
, vol.83
, pp. 57-64
-
-
Buhl, G.1
-
7
-
-
12844260602
-
How Is Metaphysics as a Science Possible? Kant on the Distinction between Philosophical and Mathematical Method
-
W. R. de Jong, "How Is Metaphysics as a Science Possible? Kant on the Distinction between Philosophical and Mathematical Method." The Review of Metaphysics 48 (1995), pp. 235-74
-
(1995)
The Review of Metaphysics
, vol.48
, pp. 235-274
-
-
R.de Jong, W.1
-
8
-
-
65849521771
-
Gottlob Frege and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction within the Framework of the Aristotelian Model of Science
-
Idem, "Gottlob Frege and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction within the Framework of the Aristotelian Model of Science." Kant-Studien 87 (1996), 290-324
-
(1996)
Kant-Studien
, vol.87
, pp. 290-324
-
-
R.de Jong, W.1
-
9
-
-
68349101540
-
Bolzano's Definition of Analytic Propositions
-
100
-
Cf. Y. Bar-Hillel, "Bolzano's Definition of Analytic Propositions." Theoria 16 (1950), pp. 91-117; p. 100
-
(1950)
Theoria
, vol.16
, pp. 91-117
-
-
Bar-Hillel, C.Y.1
-
11
-
-
0002057987
-
Introduction
-
B. Bolzano (ed. by J. Berg; transl. by B. Terrell). Dordrecht; p. 18
-
J. Berg, "Introduction." In: B. Bolzano, Theory of Science (ed. by J. Berg; transl. by B. Terrell). Dordrecht 1973, pp. 1-44; p. 18
-
(1973)
Theory of Science
, pp. 1-44
-
-
Berg, J.1
-
13
-
-
70449911000
-
-
B. Bolzano, Wissenschaftslehre (intr. by J. Berg).
-
B. Bolzano, Wissenschaftslehre (intr. by J. Berg)
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
79958968784
-
-
Bernard Bolzano-Gesamtausgabe (ed. by E. Winter et all.). Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt, 1969- ); Reihe 1, 11-14. The Wissenschaftslehre is indicated by WL, followed by the section number. For citations I used Bolzano's Theory of Science. To Berg's introduction I will refer as Einleitung
-
Bernard Bolzano-Gesamtausgabe (ed. by E. Winter et all.). Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt, 1969- ); Reihe 1, vol. 11-14. The Wissenschaftslehre is indicated by WL, followed by the section number. For citations I used Bolzano's Theory of Science. To Berg's introduction I will refer as "Einleitung."
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
84868454669
-
-
WL §§ 123, 291, 19, 34;
-
Cf. WL §§ 123, 291, 19, 34
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
33646715525
-
-
63-65
-
see also: Berg, Bolzano's Logic, pp. 45-48, 63-65
-
Bolzano's Logic
, pp. 45-48
-
-
Berg1
-
17
-
-
70449977495
-
-
Scholz and Beth have endeavored to characterize this concept of science without however distinguishing adequately between the ordo essendi and the ordo cognoscendi
-
Scholz and Beth have endeavored to characterize this concept of science without however distinguishing adequately between the ordo essendi and the ordo cognoscendi
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
84868478016
-
-
WL §§ 216, 220.
-
WL §§ 216, 220
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
84868478018
-
-
Berg, "Introduction," p. 24
-
Cf. Berg, "Introduction," p. 24
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
0004323473
-
-
(trans. by J. Barnes). Oxford
-
Cf. Aristotle, Posterior Analytics (trans. by J. Barnes). Oxford 1994, 71 b30
-
(1994)
Posterior Analytics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
23
-
-
84868496458
-
-
Notice that Bolzano clearly differs from Kant on this point. According to Bolzano a (pure) concept as such does not need to be universal (cf. WL § 73).
-
Notice that Bolzano clearly differs from Kant on this point. According to Bolzano a (pure) concept as such does not need to be universal (cf. WL § 73)
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
84868496460
-
-
WL § 1; § 536; however §§ 39-23, 414, 426-7.
-
WL § 1; cf. § 536; see however §§ 39-23, 414, 426-7
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
79958901355
-
-
References to Kant's works are to the well-known Akademie Text-Ausgabe of Kant's Gesammelte Schriften (henceforth AK). However, the Kritik der reinen Vernunft is cited in the customary way with references to the pagination of the first (A) and/or second (B) printing
-
References to Kant's works are to the well-known Akademie Text-Ausgabe of Kant's Gesammelte Schriften (henceforth AK). However, the Kritik der reinen Vernunft is cited in the customary way with references to the pagination of the first (A) and/or second (B) printing
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
79958967062
-
-
For citations I have made use to the extent possible of The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant (ed. by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood), which is presently appearing. I also used: I. Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics that Will Be Able to Present Itself as a Science (transl. by P. G. Lucas). Manchester 1971
-
For citations I have made use to the extent possible of The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant (ed. by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood), which is presently appearing. I also used: I. Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics that Will Be Able to Present Itself as a Science (transl. by P. G. Lucas). Manchester 1971
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
12844257285
-
Kant's Analytic Judgments and the Traditional Theory of Concepts
-
esp. p. 628
-
Cf. W. R. de Jong, "Kant's Analytic Judgments and the Traditional Theory of Concepts." Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1995), 613-41; esp. p. 628
-
(1995)
Journal of the History of Philosophy
, vol.33
, pp. 613-641
-
-
R.de Jong, C.W.1
-
30
-
-
84868496456
-
-
WL §§ 64, 120.
-
WL §§ 64, 120
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
85050419506
-
Ratio 12
-
p. 7
-
See also: U. Neeman, "Analytic and Synthetic Propositions in Kant and Bolzano." Ratio 12 (1970), 1-25; cf. p. 7
-
(1970)
, pp. 1-25
-
-
Neeman, U.1
-
35
-
-
0040701915
-
Bolzano's Deductibility and Tarski's Logical Consequence
-
Cf. P. B. Thompson, "Bolzano's Deductibility and Tarski's Logical Consequence." History and Philosophy of Logic 2 (1981), pp. 11-20
-
(1981)
History and Philosophy of Logic
, vol.2
, pp. 11-20
-
-
Thompson, C.P.B.1
-
36
-
-
84868454656
-
-
WL § 65. Bolzano believes that the general structure of a proposition can be presented as: A has b. But by taking has and not is as the copula he departs strongly from the usual approach in traditional logic: Propositions of the form, A is B, would always be more clearly and correctly expressed as follows: A-has-(the property of a B or) b, in which b is the abstractum corresponding to the concretum B (WL § 127; § 126).
-
Cf. WL § 65. Bolzano believes that the general structure of a proposition can be presented as: A has b. But by taking has and not is as the copula he departs strongly from the usual approach in traditional logic: "Propositions of the form, A is B, would always be more clearly and correctly expressed as follows: A-has-(the property of a B or) b," in which b is the abstractum corresponding to the concretum B (WL § 127; cf. § 126)
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
84868452272
-
-
WL § 147. Lacking a technically precise language Bolzano characterises the notion of universal (contra)validity in a rather loose way. In recent reconstructions this notion of Bolzano is usually defined with respect to sequences or classes of ideas; for instance: Berg, Introduction, pp. 17-18. My speaking of 'simultaneous variation' intends to do the same. The condition that a proposition should be denotative - die Gegenständlichkeit des Satzes - corresponds to the requirement usually found in traditional logic that the (logical) subject of a proposition should have existential import.
-
WL § 147. Lacking a technically precise language Bolzano characterises the notion of universal (contra)validity in a rather loose way. In recent reconstructions this notion of Bolzano is usually defined with respect to sequences or classes of ideas; see for instance: Berg, "Introduction, " pp. 17-18. My speaking of 'simultaneous variation' intends to do the same. The condition that a proposition should be denotative - die Gegenständlichkeit des Satzes - corresponds to the requirement usually found in traditional logic that the (logical) subject of a proposition should have existential import
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
84868489973
-
Der Streit um die 'analytisch-synthetisch' Dichotomy
-
ed. P. Weingartner, Salzburg and Munich, p. 161
-
Haller, "Der Streit um die 'analytisch-synthetisch' Dichotomy." Deskription, Analyticität und Existenz (ed. P. Weingartner). Salzburg and Munich 1966, pp. 159-74, p. 161
-
(1966)
Deskription, Analyticität und Existenz
, pp. 159-174
-
-
Haller1
-
41
-
-
79957107478
-
-
the class of logically analytic propositions is much more interesting from a modern point of view
-
Berg, "Introduction," p. 19: the class of logically analytic propositions "is much more interesting from a modern point of view."
-
Introduction
, pp. 19
-
-
Berg1
-
42
-
-
79958943350
-
-
Berg, "Einleitung", 12.1, p. 18
-
Einleitung
, vol.12
, Issue.1
, pp. 18
-
-
Berg1
-
45
-
-
84868496445
-
-
WL § 155. Berg, Introduction, pp. 20-22;
-
Cf. WL § 155. See also: Berg, "Introduction", pp. 20-22
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
84868454650
-
-
B truth represents a rather simple type of derivability. It is what is traditionally called an immediate inference; that is, an argument in which a conclusion is inferred from one premiss.
-
B truth represents a rather simple type of derivability. It is what is traditionally called an immediate inference; that is, an argument in which a conclusion is inferred from one premiss
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
34249073689
-
-
pp. 145-53, p. 171
-
Proust, Questions de Forme, p. 149; cf. pp. 145-53, p. 171
-
Questions de Forme
, pp. 149
-
-
Proust1
-
50
-
-
84868496443
-
-
WL § 198, § 162. Scholz, Die Wissenschaftslehre Bolzanos, pp. 452-60.
-
WL § 198, cf. § 162. See also Scholz, "Die Wissenschaftslehre Bolzanos," pp. 452-60
-
-
-
-
51
-
-
84868452265
-
-
WL § 221 n.; WL §§ 603, 604.
-
WL § 221 n.; cf. WL §§ 603, 604
-
-
-
-
52
-
-
84868454646
-
-
B truth F(x) ∧ (G(x) ∨ ∼G(x)) and not the other way around (cf. the simplicity condition)
-
B truth F(x) ∧ (G(x) ∨ ∼G(x)) and not the other way around (cf. the simplicity condition)
-
-
-
-
53
-
-
79958974910
-
-
Various aspects of the matter ought really to be worked out against the background of the development of Bolzano's thought, but to do that here would convey us beyond the scope of this article
-
Various aspects of the matter ought really to be worked out against the background of the development of Bolzano's thought, but to do that here would convey us beyond the scope of this article
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
84868496441
-
-
also WL § 532 and the manuscript Einleitung zur 'Grossenlehre.' Bernard Bolzano Gesamtausgabe, series IIA, 7, p. 31.
-
See also WL § 532 and the manuscript "Einleitung zur 'Grossenlehre.'" Bernard Bolzano Gesamtausgabe, series IIA, vol. 7, p. 31
-
-
-
-
56
-
-
12844285978
-
-
Th. L. Heath ed, New York
-
See also Th. L. Heath (ed.), The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements. New York 1966. Vol. 1, pp. 117-24
-
(1966)
The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements
, vol.1
, pp. 117-124
-
-
|