메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 20, Issue 3, 2009, Pages 266-273

Surrogates have not been shown to make inaccurate substituted judgments

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ARTICLE; DECISION MAKING; ETHICS; HUMAN; INFORMED CONSENT; RIGHT TO DIE; TERMINAL CARE; TREATMENT WITHDRAWAL;

EID: 70449732636     PISSN: 10467890     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (3)

References (37)
  • 1
    • 77952124642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For brevity we use the term "surrogate" for every decision maker other than the patient, even though we realize that applying it to a physician may deviate from the linguistic norm
    • For brevity we use the term "surrogate" for every decision maker other than the patient, even though we realize that applying it to a physician may deviate from the linguistic norm.
  • 2
    • 77952174253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is a simplification, since SJS has been formulated in different ways. This stripped-down version, however, is the most common one, and the differences between alternative formulations of the standard are inconsequential to the argument we make in this article.
  • 3
    • 33644976726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The accuracy of surrogate decision makers: A systematic review
    • This literature has been systematically reviewed in D.I. Shalowitz, E. Garrett-Mayer, and D. Wendler, "The Accuracy of Surrogate Decision Makers: A Systematic Review," Archives of Internal Medicine 166, no.5 (2006): 493-7.
    • (2006) Archives of Internal Medicine , vol.166 , Issue.5 , pp. 493-497
    • Shalowitz, D.I.1    Garrett-Mayer, E.2    Wendler, D.3
  • 5
    • 33646725275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Predictors of patient treatment preferences and spouse substituted judgments: The case of dialysis continuation
    • R.A. Pruchno, E.P. Lemay Jr, L. Field, and N.G. Levinsky, "Predictors of Patient Treatment Preferences and Spouse Substituted Judgments: The Case of Dialysis Continuation," Medical Decision Making 26, no. 2 (2006): 112-21;
    • (2006) Medical Decision Making , vol.26 , Issue.2 , pp. 112-121
    • Pruchno, R.A.1    Lemay Jr., E.P.2    Field, L.3    Levinsky, N.G.4
  • 6
    • 0034991194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Projection in surrogate decisions about life-sustaining medical treatments
    • A. Fagerlin et al., "Projection in Surrogate Decisions about Life-Sustaining Medical Treatments," Health Psychology 20, no. 3 (2001): 166-75;
    • (2001) Health Psychology , vol.20 , Issue.3 , pp. 166-175
    • Fagerlin, A.1
  • 7
    • 0035847590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Advance directives as acts of communication: A randomized controlled trial
    • and P.H. Ditto et al., "Advance Directives as Acts of Communication: A Randomized Controlled Trial," Archives of Internal Medicine 161, no. 3 (2001): 421-430
    • (2001) Archives of Internal Medicine , vol.161 , Issue.3 , pp. 421-430
    • Ditto, P.H.1
  • 8
    • 42449103434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Turning failures into successes: A methodological shortcoming in empirai research on surrogate accuracy
    • January makes no difference to the argument that follows
    • This is to simplify matters, in particular because responses that express uncertainty are often treated as preferences (or predictions of preferences) that express a positive attitude towards treatment - a practice that is considered justified because it mirrors the clinical default to provide treatment unless specifically refused. This practice, which is criticized in M. Johansson and L. Broström, "Turning Failures into Successes: A Methodological Shortcoming in Empirai Research on Surrogate Accuracy," Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29, no.1 (January 2008): 17-26, makes no difference to the argument that follows.
    • (2008) Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics , vol.29 , Issue.1 , pp. 17-26
    • Johansson, M.1    Broström, L.2
  • 9
    • 85047700457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Predicting elderly outpatients' life-sustaining treatment preferences over time: The majority rules
    • That people's preferences may change over time is frequently recognized and sometimes adjusted for; see e.g. R.M. Houts et al., "Predicting Elderly Outpatients' Life-Sustaining Treatment Preferences over Time: The Majority Rules," Medical Decision Making 22, no.1 (2002): 39-52. However, the point we are about to make is that, contrary to common belief, it is not enough for substituted judgments to accommodate the fact that preferences are moving targets in this temporal sense.
    • (2002) Medical Decision Making , vol.22 , Issue.1 , pp. 39-52
    • Houts, R.M.1
  • 10
    • 77952130607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fagerlin et al., see note 3 above, p. 173
    • Fagerlin et al., see note 3 above, p. 173.
  • 11
    • 28744441969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spouse as health care proxy for dialysis patients: Whose preferences matter?
    • pp. 817-8
    • Compare with. R.A. Pruchno, E.P. Lemay Jr., L. Field, and N.G. Levinsky, "Spouse as Health Care Proxy for Dialysis Patients: Whose Preferences Matter?" Gerontologist 45, no.6 (2005): 812-9, pp. 817-8.
    • (2005) Gerontologist , vol.45 , Issue.6 , pp. 812-819
    • Pruchno, R.A.1    Lemay Jr., E.P.2    Field, L.3    Levinsky, N.G.4
  • 12
    • 77952233541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fagerlin et al., see note 3 above, p. 173
    • Fagerlin et al., see note 3 above, p. 173.
  • 13
    • 77952160410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A question we address also to Shalowitz et al., see note 3 above, in which the following unelaborated admission can be found: "it is impossible to measure surrogate accuracy in actual cases because it is not possible to know the preferences of patients when they are incapacitated," p. 497.
  • 14
    • 77952235721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Even in those cases when it makes sense to suppose that an incompetent patient's preference is merely "inactivated" temporarily, or cannot be expressed (as when a patient has an epileptic fit or a brief psychotic episode, e.g.), this preference isn't necessarily the one that a surrogate ought to satisfy, according to SJS. One should also adjust for possible factual mistakes underlying a preference, as well as other formative factors that ought to be left out of the equation. More about this below.
  • 15
    • 77952126533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 7 above
    • See note 7 above.
  • 16
    • 77952228558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Preferences and decisions are not the same thing, and they deserve to be distinguished more often in the discussion. For present purposes, however, the issue is not that important, and we shall here largely follow the empirical literature in speaking of a patient's "preferences."
  • 17
    • 0013158341 scopus 로고
    • Study of ethical problems in medicine and biomedical and behavioral research
    • Washington D.C: U.S. Government Printing Office
    • See e.g. the formulations of the standard found in President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Deciding to Forego Life-Sustaining Treatment (Washington D.C: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1983), 132,
    • (1983) Deciding to Forego Life-Sustaining Treatment , pp. 132
  • 19
    • 34548354865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What the patient would have decided': A fundamental problem with the substituted judgment standard
    • L. Broström, M. Johansson, and M.K. Nielsen, " 'What the Patient Would Have Decided': A Fundamental Problem with the Substituted Judgment Standard," Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 10, no.3 (2007): 265-278
    • (2007) Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy , vol.10 , Issue.3 , pp. 265-278
    • Broström, L.1    Johansson, M.2    Nielsen, M.K.3
  • 20
    • 33746758743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S. Lichtenstein and P. Slovic, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, for recent results and discussions regarding such matters
    • See e.g. S. Lichtenstein and P. Slovic, ed., The Construction of Preference (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), for recent results and discussions regarding such matters.
    • (2006) The Construction of Preference
  • 21
    • 0028473518 scopus 로고
    • Rational desires and the limitation of life-sustaining treatment
    • This general idea has been expressed in different ways. For an uncommonly precise (and therefore more vulnerable) version of the suggestion, see e.g. J. Savulescu, "Rational Desires and the Limitation of Life-Sustaining Treatment," Bioethics 8, no.3 (1994): 191-222.
    • (1994) Bioethics , vol.8 , Issue.3 , pp. 191-222
    • Savulescu, J.1
  • 22
    • 77952138971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The alert reader will have realized that this talk about a patient's deepest priorities, or values, is highly problematic, for the same reason as talk about an incompetent patient's "true" preferences is problematic. What could it mean that an incompetent patient has deeply considered values? Or if we have in mind priorities had by this person before the onset of incompetence, couldn't such priorities change over time, and what would then warrant singling out personal values had at one point in time rather than at some other point in time? Such problems again amplify that the notion of what a patient would have wanted is a construction of sorts. Nonetheless, we believe that on any remotely plausible moral justification of SJS, this standard will ask the surrogate to idealize a patient's decision conditions, in roughly the ways sketched above.
  • 24
    • 0029268541 scopus 로고
    • Revising the substituted judgment standard
    • where a similar point is made in terms of SJS's "unintended sensitivity" to "nonvalues."
    • Cf. R. Baergen, "Revising the Substituted Judgment Standard," The Journal of Clinical Ethics 6, no.1 (1995): 30-38, where a similar point is made in terms of SJS's "unintended sensitivity" to "nonvalues."
    • (1995) The Journal of Clinical Ethics , vol.6 , Issue.1 , pp. 30-38
    • Baergen, R.1
  • 25
    • 0027570154 scopus 로고
    • Do physicians' own preferences for life-sustaining treatment influence their perceptions of patients' preferences?
    • p. 31.
    • L.J. Schneiderman, R.M. Kaplan, E. Rosenberg, and H. Teetzel, "Do Physicians' Own Preferences for life-Sustaining Treatment Influence Their Perceptions of Patients' Preferences?" The Journal of Clinical Ethics 4, no.1 (1993): 28-33, p. 31.
    • (1993) The Journal of Clinical Ethics , vol.4 , Issue.1 , pp. 28-33
    • Schneiderman, L.J.1    Kaplan, R.M.2    Rosenberg, E.3    Teetzel, H.4
  • 26
    • 77952172260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Fagerlin et al., see note 3 above
    • See also Fagerlin et al., see note 3 above.
  • 27
    • 77952125897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Another approach to SJS, with some intuitive plausibility, maintains that surrogate decision makers need to make treatment choices that reflect not so much a patient's deeper values, but rather a patient's character. There is much to say about this alternative interpretation of SJS. The important point here is that there is no evidence that patients and surrogates have paid appropriate attention to character when participating in relevant research.
  • 28
    • 3042615480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From informed consent to substituted judgment: Decision-making at the end-of-life
    • Similar misgivings about this research paradigm, although from a somewhat different angle, are expressed in M. Kuczewski, "From Informed Consent to Substituted Judgment: Decision-Making at the End-of-Life," HEC Forum 16, no.1 (2004): 27-37. Kuczewski argues there are "significant reasons to doubt that the responses of the patient and the prospective surrogate (...) are relevant to their future clinical decision-making regarding endof-life care" (p. 30). According to him, the problem is that these responses do not reflect judgments that have come out of an informed-consent process characterized by deliberation and the refinement of values within a longer family dialogue. This is the kind of process that, on Kuczewski's view, patients and their prospective surrogates often go through, and the kind of process that a surrogate should simulate, as it were, once a patient has become incompetent. We think there is much to be said for this kind of approach, but wish to stress that when a patient becomes incompetent, there is an obvious and important sense in which it is up to a surrogate how to continue the "dialogue," and to assess its relevance. A significant normative constraint, we would argue, is that a surrogate takes less seriously imagined conversations that do not help uncover or refine a patient's deeper sentiments.
    • (2004) HEC Forum , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 27-37
    • Kuczewski, M.1
  • 29
    • 85047692242 scopus 로고
    • Surrogates' predictions of seriously 111 patients' resuscitation preferences
    • p. 519
    • Compare P.M. Layde et al., "Surrogates' Predictions of Seriously 111 Patients' Resuscitation Preferences," Archives of Family Medicine 4, no.6 (1995): 518-23, p. 519;
    • (1995) Archives of Family Medicine , vol.4 , Issue.6 , pp. 518-523
    • Layde, P.M.1
  • 30
    • 0025873802 scopus 로고
    • Substituted judgment: How accurate are proxy predictions?
    • p. 97
    • A.B. Seckler et al., "Substituted Judgment: How Accurate Are Proxy Predictions?" Anuais of Internal Medicine 115, no. 2 (1991): 92-8, p. 97.
    • (1991) Anuais of Internal Medicine , vol.115 , Issue.2 , pp. 92-98
    • Seckler, A.B.1
  • 31
    • 77952175559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • If one does understand that the preferences relevant to SJS are hypothetical, and believes that patient respondents have conjectured what these future hypothetical preferences would be, the results regarding the accuracy of predictions would have a bearing on surrogates' abilities to satisfy SJS only under the assumption that patient respondents are likely to be generally right about what they would want in the hypothetical scenario. But this assumption is patently unfounded.
  • 32
    • 77952164247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • President's Commission, p. 133, see note 11 above
    • President's Commission, p. 133, see note 11 above.
  • 33
    • 77952122091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 17 above
    • See note 17 above.
  • 34
    • 77952148335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g. Pruchno et al., see note 3 above
    • E.g. Pruchno et al., see note 3 above.
  • 35
    • 77952179174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g. Fagerlin et al., see note 3 above
    • E.g. Fagerlin et al., see note 3 above;
  • 36
    • 77952208782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schneiderman et al., see note 19 above
    • Schneiderman et al., see note 19 above;
  • 37
    • 0031085074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do physicians' own preferences for life-sustaining treatment influence their perceptions of patients' preferences? A second look
    • and L.J. Schneiderman, R.M. Kaplan, E. Rosenberg, and H. Teetzel, "Do Physicians' Own Preferences for Life-Sustaining Treatment Influence Their Perceptions of Patients' Preferences? A Second Look," Cambridge Quarterly of Health Care Ethics 6, no.2 (1997): 131-137
    • (1997) Cambridge Quarterly of Health Care Ethics , vol.6 , Issue.2 , pp. 131-137
    • Schneiderman, L.J.1    Kaplan, R.M.2    Rosenberg, E.3    Teetzel, H.4


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.