메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 77, Issue 5-6, 2009, Pages 1135-1172

Justice in time

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 70449120367     PISSN: 00168076     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (5)

References (161)
  • 1
    • 70449134447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We are of course fortunate to have my erstwhile colleague, Doug Kysar, here to say more on that.
    • We are of course fortunate to have my erstwhile colleague, Doug Kysar, here to say more on that.
  • 2
    • 70449100563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More on this will be presented in Neil Buchanan's presentation.
    • More on this will be presented in Neil Buchanan's presentation.
  • 3
    • 70449130854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Four out of four panelists agree: U. S. fiscal policy does not cheat future generations
    • See
    • See Neil H. Buchanan, Four out of Four Panelists Agree: U. S. Fiscal Policy Does Not Cheat Future Generations, 77 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 1402 (2009)
    • (2009) GEo. Wash. L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 1402
    • Buchanan, N.H.1
  • 4
    • 70449106866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bailouts, buy-ins, and ballyhoo, 52
    • see also
    • see also Robert Hockett, Bailouts, Buy-Ins, and Ballyhoo, 52 CHALLENGE 36 (2009)
    • (2009) Challenge , vol.36
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 5
    • 70449100564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A fixer upper for finance
    • forthcoming
    • Robert Hockett, A Fixer Upper for Finance, 87 WASH. U. L. REV. (forthcoming 2010).
    • (2010) Wash. U. L. Rev. , vol.87
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 6
    • 84869689143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Please leave open the possibility that those "beneficiaries" to whom I refer here include more than human beings. If, as we might, we owe obligations to nonhuman animals and perhaps other living-even nonliving?-things, then these too will be among the "beneficiaries" here. See infra Part III. B.
    • Please leave open the possibility that those "beneficiaries" to whom I refer here include more than human beings. If, as we might, we owe obligations to nonhuman animals and perhaps other living-even nonliving?-things, then these too will be among the "beneficiaries" here. See infra Part III. B.
  • 7
    • 84869680771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Or" here to be taken in the inclusive sense-"a, b,..., n, or some combination thereof.
    • "Or" here to be taken in the inclusive sense-"a, b,..., n, or some combination thereof."
  • 8
    • 70449132471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The deep grammar of distribution: A meta-theory of justice
    • See, e.g., [hereinafter Hockett, Deep Grammar]
    • See, e.g., Robert Hockett, The Deep Grammar of Distribution: A Meta-Theory of Justice, 26 CARDOZO L. REV. 1179 (2005) [hereinafter Hockett, Deep Grammar];
    • (2005) Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.26 , pp. 1179
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 9
    • 70449129542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking distribution seriously
    • forthcoming [hereinafter Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously]
    • Robert Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, 59 EMORY L. J. (forthcoming 2010) [hereinafter Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously]
    • (2010) Emory L. J. , vol.59
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 10
    • 70449108957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also infra Parts II and III.
    • see also infra Parts II and III.
  • 11
    • 84869689140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 5, at 1210 n.85 ("I classify questions according as they pertain to what is distributed, to whom it is distributed, and how it is distributed.").
    • See Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5, at 1210 n.85 ("I classify questions according as they pertain to what is distributed, to whom it is distributed, and how it is distributed.").
    • Hockett1    Grammar, D.2
  • 12
    • 70449119742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Uncertainty is of course an episteraic category, while indeterminacy is a metaphysical one. The former is accordingly more salient, in that we would seem to be unavoidably afflicted by it irrespective of whether the future is, as a metaphysical matter, determined or not. We shall presently find some occasion to note, however, that at least one form of bona fide indeterminacy-at any rate, an agent-relative form-afflicts intertemporal justice theorizing. It is the form found in the fact that, in asking what we are obligated to do in respect of the future, we cannot but view certain portions of the future as indeterminate, precisely because what will happen depends upon our decision about what to do and then doing it.
    • Uncertainty is of course an episteraic category, while indeterminacy is a metaphysical one. The former is accordingly more salient, in that we would seem to be unavoidably afflicted by it irrespective of whether the future is, as a metaphysical matter, determined or not. We shall presently find some occasion to note, however, that at least one form of bona fide indeterminacy-at any rate, an agent-relative form-afflicts intertemporal justice theorizing. It is the form found in the fact that, in asking what we are obligated to do in respect of the future, we cannot but view certain portions of the future as indeterminate, precisely because what will happen depends upon our decision about what to do and then doing it.
  • 13
    • 84869677155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Noncom-parabilities and nonstandard logics
    • For more on these forms of indeterminacy, see, for example, forthcoming available at
    • For more on these forms of indeterminacy, see, for example, Robert Hockett, Noncom-parabilities and Nonstandard Logics, 25 ECON. & PHIL, (forthcoming 2009), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm? abstract-id=931042.
    • (2009) Econ. & Phil , vol.25
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 14
    • 84869689139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I shall argue that this is no puzzle at all, but is nonsense. Nevertheless, this interrogative sentence is taken by many theorists to express a bona fide question, so I shall pretend likewise for the moment. The additional puzzles I shall name likewise are afflicted by varying degrees of "pseudo" stature of this sort.
    • I shall argue that this is no puzzle at all, but is nonsense. Nevertheless, this interrogative sentence is taken by many theorists to express a bona fide question, so I shall pretend likewise for the moment. The additional puzzles I shall name likewise are afflicted by varying degrees of "pseudo" stature of this sort.
  • 15
    • 84869680769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If at least one person views one state of the world as better than another, while nobody views it as worse, then "society as a whole" should regard things this way. Weak Pareto: If everyone views one state of the world as better than another, then so should "society as a whole." Pareto Indifference: If everyone is indifferent between two states of the world, then so should "society as a whole" be deemed. For fuller discussion
    • Strong Pareto: If at least one person views one state of the world as better than another, while nobody views it as worse, then "society as a whole" should regard things this way. Weak Pareto: If everyone views one state of the world as better than another, then so should "society as a whole." Pareto Indifference: If everyone is indifferent between two states of the world, then so should "society as a whole" be deemed. For fuller discussion,
    • Pareto, S.1
  • 16
    • 85013282580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why pare-tians can't prescribe: Preferences, principles, and imperatives in law and policy
    • See forthcoming
    • See Robert Hockett, Why Pare-tians Can't Prescribe: Preferences, Principles, and Imperatives in Law and Policy, 18 CORNELL J. L. & PUB. POL'Y (forthcoming 2009).
    • (2009) Cornell J. L. & Pub. Pol'y , vol.18
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 17
    • 70449126895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are yet more renditions of Pareto, most of them developed quite recently.
    • There are yet more renditions of Pareto, most of them developed quite recently.
  • 18
    • 70449108956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., the papers by discussed infra Part IV. B.
    • See, e.g., the papers by Basu & Mitra, and Mitra & Basu, discussed infra Part IV. B.
    • Basu1    Mitra2    Mitra3    Basu4
  • 19
    • 84869675956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pareto versus welfare
    • It has recently been argued that Paretian criteria entail a strict form of "welfarism," according to which worlds can be deemed better or worse only in keeping with the preferences - even if these be morally arbitrary or indeed immoral or anti-ethical preferences-of individuals. It has likewise been argued that this form of welfarism is incompatible with justice. Hence it has been argued that justice is an offence against "welfare" and "the Pareto Principle" alike. This is all nonsense, as shown formally in Robert Hockett, under review and as argued at length in Hockett, supra note 10.
    • It has recently been argued that Paretian criteria entail a strict form of "welfarism," according to which worlds can be deemed better or worse only in keeping with the preferences - even if these be morally arbitrary or indeed immoral or anti-ethical preferences-of individuals. It has likewise been argued that this form of welfarism is incompatible with justice. Hence it has been argued that justice is an offence against "welfare" and "the Pareto Principle" alike. This is all nonsense, as shown formally in Robert Hockett, Pareto Versus Welfare, Soc. CHOICE & WELFARE (under review 2009), and as argued at length in Hockett, supra note 10.
    • (2009) Soc. Choice & Welfare
  • 20
    • 70449091607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • see also Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett1
  • 21
    • 84869689136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I note elsewhere that one can "translate" any distributive imperative into a maximization imperative, and vice versa.
    • I note elsewhere that one can "translate" any distributive imperative into a maximization imperative, and vice versa.
  • 22
    • 84869672301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5. To specify a maximization imperative without reference to distribution is thus effectively the same as to treat maximization as analytically "prior" to distribution. It is to suggest that one can first specify a normatively interesting maximandum without any reference to distribution, and then derive distributive norms therefrom. This, I argue at length elsewhere and shall note again further below, is a form of fetishism. See id.
    • See Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5. To specify a maximization imperative without reference to distribution is thus effectively the same as to treat maximization as analytically "prior" to distribution. It is to suggest that one can first specify a normatively interesting maximandum without any reference to distribution, and then derive distributive norms therefrom. This, I argue at length elsewhere and shall note again further below, is a form of fetishism. See id.
    • Hockett1
  • 23
    • 70449089674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I shall argue that this affords added reason to displace these imperatives from their currently dominant role in intertemporal justice theorizing. But there are many more reasons for such a displacement, which I have offered at length elsewhere and will partly rehearse below. So here we shall find simply another reason to have done with a mode of justice theorizing that is already, independently, worthy of the scrap heap.
    • I shall argue that this affords added reason to displace these imperatives from their currently dominant role in intertemporal justice theorizing. But there are many more reasons for such a displacement, which I have offered at length elsewhere and will partly rehearse below. So here we shall find simply another reason to have done with a mode of justice theorizing that is already, independently, worthy of the scrap heap.
  • 24
    • 70449107919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • See Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett1
  • 25
    • 70449095668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More on why infra Part IV. A. See generally Hockett, supra note 10
    • More on why infra Part IV. A. See generally Hockett, supra note 10
  • 26
    • 70449089675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12. This is scarcely surprising, by the way, when one recalls that Pareto developed his efficiency criteria, in part, precisely in order to duck politically controversial distributional questions.
    • Hockett, supra note 12. This is scarcely surprising, by the way, when one recalls that Pareto developed his efficiency criteria, in part, precisely in order to duck politically controversial distributional questions.
    • Hockett1
  • 27
    • 70449095669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 10
    • See Hockett, supra note 10
    • Hockett1
  • 28
    • 70449121941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12.
    • Hockett, supra note 12.
    • Hockett1
  • 29
    • 0039714965 scopus 로고
    • It is conventional to subdivide justice into distributive, retributive, and nowadays even "corrective" categories. What all have in common, however, is the venerable Aristotelian idea of giving everyone her due. And "due giving" is simply "just distribution" at the level of abstraction at which we are here operating. See, e.g., Martin Oswold trans., (lines 1129a-1130a).
    • It is conventional to subdivide justice into distributive, retributive, and nowadays even "corrective" categories. What all have in common, however, is the venerable Aristotelian idea of giving everyone her due. And "due giving" is simply "just distribution" at the level of abstraction at which we are here operating. See, e.g., ARISTOTLE, NICHOMACHEAN ETHICS 110-14 (Martin Oswold trans., 1962) (lines 1129a-1130a).
    • (1962) Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics , pp. 110-114
  • 30
    • 70449112463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Careful study of case grammar appears to originate with Fillmore.
    • Careful study of case grammar appears to originate with Fillmore.
  • 31
    • 33845511112 scopus 로고
    • Toward a modern theory of case
    • See generally (David A. Reibel & Sanford A. Schane eds.
    • See generally Charles J. Hllmore, Toward a Modern Theory of Case, in MODERN STUDIES IN ENGUSH: READINGS IN TRANSFORMATIONAL GRAMMAR 361, 361-75 (David A. Reibel & Sanford A. Schane eds., 1969)
    • (1969) Modern Studies in Engush: Readings in Transformational Grammar , vol.361 , pp. 361-375
    • Hllmore, C.J.1
  • 32
    • 0002635287 scopus 로고
    • The case for case
    • Emmon Bach & Robert T. Harms eds.
    • Charles J. Fillmore, The Case for Case, in UNIVERSALS IN LINGUISTIC THEORY 1, 1-88 (Emmon Bach & Robert T. Harms eds., 1968)
    • (1968) Universals in Linguistic Theory , vol.1 , pp. 1-88
    • Fillmore, C.J.1
  • 33
    • 0010807743 scopus 로고
    • C. Fillmore & D. J. Langendoen eds.
    • STUDIES IN LINGUISTIC SEMANTICS (C. Fillmore & D. J. Langendoen eds., 1971).
    • (1971) Studies in Linguistic Semantics
  • 34
    • 0012954532 scopus 로고
    • The analysis of predicates as argument-taking functions appears to have originated with Frege. See Gottlob Frege, Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens, translated in Begriffsschrift, a Formula Language, Modeled Upon That of Arithmetic, for Pure Thought, Jan van Heijenoort ed.
    • The analysis of predicates as argument-taking functions appears to have originated with Frege. See Gottlob Frege, Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens, translated in Begriffsschrift, a Formula Language, Modeled Upon That of Arithmetic, for Pure Thought, in FROM FREGE TO GODEL: A SOURCE BOOK IN MATHEMATICAL LOGIC, 1879-1931 1, 5-82 (Jan van Heijenoort ed., 1967)
    • (1967) From Frege to Godel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931 , vol.1 , pp. 5-82
  • 35
    • 70449129540 scopus 로고
    • I make fuller use of case grammatical categories in Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5.
    • GOTTLOB FREGE, FUNKTION UND BEGRIFF (1891). I make fuller use of case grammatical categories in Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5.
    • (1891) Gottlob Frege, Funktion Und Begriff
  • 36
    • 70449129541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For fuller treatment, see Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5.
    • For fuller treatment, see Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5.
  • 37
    • 70449093482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By "extensionally equivalent" in this context, I mean that alternative full sets-"vectors," in the idiom of linear algebra favored by economists and some justice theorists-of variable-fillings can dictate identical distributive outcomes "on the ground." I can, for example, name "exogenous opportunity" as the distribuendum, "responsible agents" as the distribuees, and "distribute equally" as the distribution formula. I can, alternatively, name "satisfaction" as the distribuendum, "responsible agents" as the distribuees, and "to each precisely according to her expense of responsible choice" as the distribution formula. On certain plausible interpretations of the words I have used in characterizing them, these two distribuendum/distribuee/distribu-tion-formula triples recommend identical distributive outcomes "on the ground." In this sense, just distribution can be likened to an isoquant-a sort of "indifference curve" of the sort familiar to decision theory and related disciplines. Two justice theories will bear the same distributive upshot, and in that sense be located on the same "curve," so long as a difference in specification of the distribuendum is matched by a "compensating" difference in specification of the distribution formula. I think that something like this accounts for the impression one has, upon reading some sets of justice theorists, that they don't really disagree as much as their casuistic terminological disputes at the margins might seem to imply.
  • 38
    • 70449084485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Deep Grammar, supra note 5.
    • See Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5.
    • Hockett1
  • 40
    • 70449105814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also supra note 5
    • see also Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5
    • Hockett1    Grammar, D.2
  • 41
    • 70449089678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett1
  • 43
    • 33644907973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The problem of global justice
    • Thomas Nagel, The Problem of Global Justice, 33 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 120 (2005).
    • (2005) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.33 , pp. 120
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 44
    • 70449112459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 22, at 38-39
    • See RAWLS, supra note 22, at 38-39
    • Rawls
  • 45
    • 70449100552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 22, at 120-21. Nagel in particular emphasizes the role of coercive authority exercised in the name of a polity as that which underwrites obligations in justice between members of that polity. I don't see that this can be either necessary or sufficient, but here is not the place to argue the point.
    • Nagel, supra note 22, at 120-21. Nagel in particular emphasizes the role of coercive authority exercised in the name of a polity as that which underwrites obligations in justice between members of that polity. I don't see that this can be either necessary or sufficient, but here is not the place to argue the point.
    • Nagel1
  • 46
    • 70449100556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 22, at 6
    • See, e.g., RAWLS, supra note 22, at 6
    • Rawls
  • 47
    • 70449100554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 22, at 137-38.
    • Nagel, supra note 22, at 137-38.
    • Nagel1
  • 48
    • 84869672302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Organicist" orientations of this sort were commonplace of nationalist ideologies of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.
    • "Organicist" orientations of this sort were commonplace of nationalist ideologies of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.
  • 53
    • 70449095675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most forceful argument of this sort, in my estimation, is that of Michael Thompson, What Is It to Wrong Someone: A Puzzle About Justice, R. Jay Wallace et al. eds.
    • The most forceful argument of this sort, in my estimation, is that of Michael Thompson, What Is It to Wrong Someone: A Puzzle About Justice, in REASON AND VALUE: THEMES FROM THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF JOSEPH RAZ 333, 379-84 (R. Jay Wallace et al. eds., 2004).
    • (2004) Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz , vol.333 , pp. 379-384
  • 54
    • 70449132470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I'll prescind from nonhuman beneficiaries just for a moment here. I do happen to believe that we bear, both individually and collectively, obligations to nonhuman creatures. The obligations for their part are of course keyed to the constitutive features and functions of the creatures in question. For more on the latter
    • I'll prescind from nonhuman beneficiaries just for a moment here. I do happen to believe that we bear, both individually and collectively, obligations to nonhuman creatures. The obligations for their part are of course keyed to the constitutive features and functions of the creatures in question. For more on the latter,
  • 56
    • 84869686495 scopus 로고
    • The locus classicus
    • There is a large literature on the notion of justice as a form of "symmetry," which latter in turn is associated with beauty. Martin Oswold trans.
    • There is a large literature on the notion of justice as a form of "symmetry," which latter in turn is associated with beauty. The locus classicus in ARISTOTLE, NICHOMACHEAN ETHICS 113 (Martin Oswold trans., 1962).
    • (1962) Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics , vol.113
  • 57
    • 0004171197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A stimulating contemporary meditation on the linkages is
    • A stimulating contemporary meditation on the linkages is ELAINE SCARRY, ON BEAUTY AND BEING JUST 86-93 (1999).
    • (1999) On Beauty and Being Just , pp. 86-93
    • Scarry, E.1
  • 58
    • 70449094448 scopus 로고
    • A compelling assimilation of ethics and aesthetics is found in, among other places D. F. Pears & B. F. McGuinness trans., 1974)
    • A compelling assimilation of ethics and aesthetics is found in, among other places WITTGENSTEIN, TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS (D. F. Pears & B. F. McGuinness trans., 1974) (1921).
    • (1921) Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
  • 59
    • 84974286205 scopus 로고
    • Modern moral philosophy
    • As for virtue ethics, the literature is vast and still growing. Let me confine myself, then, simply to citing that article from which the contemporary revival has sprung. That is G. E. M. Anscombe
    • As for virtue ethics, the literature is vast and still growing. Let me confine myself, then, simply to citing that article from which the contemporary revival has sprung. That is G. E. M. Anscombe, Modern Moral Philosophy, 33 PHIL. 1 (1958).
    • (1958) Phil. , vol.33 , Issue.1
  • 60
    • 70449100561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a growing body of empirical evidence grounding this belief. See generally Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5
    • There is a growing body of empirical evidence grounding this belief. See generally Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5
  • 61
    • 70449130285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5. I am again sidestepping, for the moment, nonhuman beneficiaries of justice.
    • Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5. I am again sidestepping, for the moment, nonhuman beneficiaries of justice.
    • Hockett1
  • 62
    • 70449094451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Again see supra note 5
    • Again see Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5
    • Hockett1    Grammar, D.2
  • 64
    • 0002431297 scopus 로고
    • Equality and equal opportunity for welfare
    • See 85-86
    • See Richard Arneson, Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare, 56 PHIL. STUD. 79, 85-86 (1989)
    • (1989) Phil. Stud. , vol.56 , pp. 79
    • Arneson, R.1
  • 65
    • 84935413249 scopus 로고
    • On the currency of egalitarian justice
    • G. A. Cohen, On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, 99 ETHICS 914 (1989)
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , pp. 914
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 68
    • 70449084486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5
    • See, e.g., Hockett, Deep Grammar, supra note 5
  • 69
    • 70449129537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett1
  • 71
    • 70449093483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett1
  • 73
    • 70449100560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Dbtribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett, Taking Dbtribution Seriously, supra note 5.
    • Hockett1
  • 74
    • 84869689135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "But don't problems of measurement and commensuration afflict equalization at the outset just as they might further along?" you might ask. The question is fair, but is answerable. The trick is to start with certain core endowments that can be roughly measured and equalized over persons early on in their lives-before their responsibilities as agents fully kick in. Those include genetic and educational endowments, among others. Then as exchange behavior commences on markets which we do our best to keep process-neutral and complete, we work regular estimates of the degrees to which resultant or persistent inequalities can be attributed to responsible choice or to non-responsible disparities.
    • "But don't problems of measurement and commensuration afflict equalization at the outset just as they might further along?" you might ask. The question is fair, but is answerable. The trick is to start with certain core endowments that can be roughly measured and equalized over persons early on in their lives-before their responsibilities as agents fully kick in. Those include genetic and educational endowments, among others. Then as exchange behavior commences on markets which we do our best to keep process-neutral and complete, we work regular estimates of the degrees to which resultant or persistent inequalities can be attributed to responsible choice or to non-responsible disparities.
  • 76
    • 70449100555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5
    • Hockett, Taking Distribution Seriously, supra note 5
    • Hockett1
  • 77
    • 61049201636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three (potential) pillars of transnational economic justice: The bretton woods institutions as guarantors of global equal treatment and market-completion
    • 99 [hereinafter Hockett, Three Pillars];
    • Robert Hockett, Three (Potential) Pillars of Transnational Economic Justice: The Bretton Woods Institutions as Guarantors of Global Equal Treatment and Market-Completion, 36 METAPHILOSOPHY 93, 99 (2005) [hereinafter Hockett, Three Pillars];
    • (2005) Metaphilosophy , vol.36 , pp. 93
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 78
    • 70449132463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whose ownership? Which society?
    • 37-38
    • Robert Hockett, Whose Ownership? Which Society?, 27 CARDOZO L. REV. 1, 37-38 (2005).
    • (2005) Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.27 , pp. 1
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 79
    • 70449115339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Three Pillars, supra note 37, at 100.
    • See Hockett, Three Pillars, supra note 37, at 100.
    • Hockett1
  • 80
    • 70449126894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part IV
    • See infra Part IV
  • 81
    • 70449134446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also supra note 12.
    • see also Hockett, supra note 12.
    • Hockett1
  • 82
    • 70449088731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe that Matt Adler also will be presenting us with a thorough treatment of SWFs tomorrow, in the first panel of our second day's treatment of intertemporal justice.
    • I believe that Matt Adler also will be presenting us with a thorough treatment of SWFs tomorrow, in the first panel of our second day's treatment of intertemporal justice.
  • 83
    • 70449100558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Welfare social. well-beino lifetime
    • see also forthcoming manuscript on file with the author
    • see also MATTHEW D. ADLER, SOCIAL WELFARE, LIFETIME WELL-Beino, AND EQUITY: A NEW FRAMEWORK FOR POLICY ANALYSIS (forthcoming 2009, manuscript on file with the author)
    • (2009) Equity: A New Framework for Policy Analysis
    • Adler, M.D.1
  • 84
    • 33846821844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Inequality and Uncertainty: Theory and Legal Applications
    • Matthew D. Adler & Chris William Sanchirico, Inequality and Uncertainty: Theory and Legal Applications, 155 U. PA. L. REV. 279 (2006)
    • (2006) U. PA. L. Rev. , vol.155 , pp. 279
    • Adler, M.D.1    Sanchirico, C.W.2
  • 85
    • 70449132466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Well-being, Inequality, and Tune: The Time-Slice Problem and Its Policy Implications (working paper, on file with the author).
    • Matthew D. Adler, Well-being, Inequality, and Tune: The Time-Slice Problem and Its Policy Implications (2007) (working paper, on file with the author).
    • (2007)
    • Adler, M.D.1
  • 86
    • 0006639426 scopus 로고
    • Between utility and rights
    • See
    • See H. L. A. Hart, Between Utility and Rights, 79 COLUM. L. REV. 828, 830 (1979).
    • (1979) 79 Colum. L. Rev. , vol.828 , pp. 830
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 87
    • 70449091605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preferences for processes: The process/product distinction and the regulation of consumer choice
    • See
    • See Douglas A. Kysar, Preferences for Processes: The Process/Product Distinction and the Regulation of Consumer Choice, 118 HARV. L. REV. 526, 617-18 (2005)
    • (2005) 118 Harv. L. Rev. , vol.526 , pp. 617-618
    • Kysar, D.A.1
  • 88
    • 70449102475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also supra note 12.
    • see also Hockett, supra note 12.
    • Hockett1
  • 89
    • 84869665790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Those works trace many implications stemming from justice's "internality" to-or "constitutivity" of-welfare itself.
    • Those works trace many implications stemming from justice's "internality" to-or "constitutivity" of-welfare itself.
  • 91
    • 70449088732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This tale has been widely told.
    • This tale has been widely told.
  • 94
    • 70449126893 scopus 로고
    • The work, which grew from Arrow's doctoral dissertation, was first published in
    • The work, which grew from Arrow's doctoral dissertation, was first published in 1950.
    • (1950)
  • 99
    • 0001131206 scopus 로고
    • A mathematical theory of saving
    • Frank P. Ramsey, A Mathematical Theory of Saving, 38 ECON. J. 543 (1928).
    • (1928) 38 Econ. J. , vol.543
    • Ramsey, F.P.1
  • 100
    • 84869689128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theorists typically cash out the Pareto criteria in terms of individual preferences. They say that one state of the world "dominates" another in a "strongly Paretian" sense when at least one person prefers the first to the second, with no one preferring the second to the first. They say that the first state dominates the second in a "weakly Paretian" sense when everyone prefers that first state. Finally, they say that two states of the world are "Pareto indifferent" to one another when nobody prefers one to the other. When at least one person prefers one state of the world, and at least one prefers another such state, the two states are said to be Pareto noncomparable.
    • Theorists typically cash out the Pareto criteria in terms of individual preferences. They say that one state of the world "dominates" another in a "strongly Paretian" sense when at least one person prefers the first to the second, with no one preferring the second to the first. They say that the first state dominates the second in a "weakly Paretian" sense when everyone prefers that first state. Finally, they say that two states of the world are "Pareto indifferent" to one another when nobody prefers one to the other. When at least one person prefers one state of the world, and at least one prefers another such state, the two states are said to be Pareto noncomparable.
  • 101
    • 70449123424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 12.
    • See Hockett, supra note 12.
    • Hockett1
  • 102
    • 0003917729 scopus 로고
    • See where the term "unanimity" is employed.
    • See AMARTYA SEN, COLLECTIVE CHOICE AND SOCIAL WELFARE 21-28 (1970), where the term "unanimity" is employed.
    • (1970) Collective Choice and Social Welfare , pp. 21-28
    • Sen, A.1
  • 103
    • 0003571810 scopus 로고
    • see also hereinafter SEN, CHOICE, WELFARE AND MEASUREMENT
    • see also AMARTYA SEN, CHOICE, WELFARE AND MEASUREMENT 167-69 (1982) [hereinafter SEN, CHOICE, WELFARE AND MEASUREMENT].
    • (1982) Choice, Welfare and Measurement , pp. 167-169
    • Sen, A.1
  • 104
    • 70449123423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 12.
    • See Hockett, supra note 12.
    • Hockett1
  • 105
    • 70449126892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 46, at 38-39
    • See, e.g., HARROD, supra note 46, at 38-39
    • Harrod
  • 107
    • 70449129539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 45, at 381-83
    • SIDGWICK, supra note 45, at 381-83
    • Sidgwick
  • 109
    • 70449129538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 46, at 543.
    • Ramsey, supra note 46, at 543.
    • Ramsey1
  • 110
    • 70449115338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 40.
    • See supra note 40.
  • 111
    • 70449091604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 44.
    • See ARROW, supra note 44.
    • Arrow
  • 112
    • 70449094446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12, shows all forms of Pareto to be potentially at odds with any normative principle of the sort that determines a social welfare function's argument domain and aggregation rule. The results I am about to report can accordingly, along with Arrow's 1951, Sen's 1970, and other notorious impossibility theorems, be viewed as ultimately unsurprising entailments of that more general impossibility.
    • Hockett, supra note 12, shows all forms of Pareto to be potentially at odds with any normative principle of the sort that determines a social welfare function's argument domain and aggregation rule. The results I am about to report can accordingly, along with Arrow's 1951, Sen's 1970, and other notorious impossibility theorems, be viewed as ultimately unsurprising entailments of that more general impossibility.
    • Hockett1
  • 113
    • 0000263697 scopus 로고
    • The evaluation of infinite utility streams
    • See
    • See Peter C. Diamond, The Evaluation of Infinite Utility Streams, 33 ECONOMETRICA 170, 170 (1965)
    • (1965) 33 Econometrica , vol.170 , pp. 170
    • Diamond, P.C.1
  • 114
    • 0000737101 scopus 로고
    • Stationary ordinal utility and impatience
    • Tjalling C. Koopmans, Stationary Ordinal Utility and Impatience, 28 ECONOMETRICA 287, 287-88 (1960).
    • (1960) 28 Econometrica , vol.287 , pp. 287-288
    • Koopmans, T.C.1
  • 115
    • 84869680764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "infinite utility stream" idea is less intimidating than might first be assumed. In essence, the idea is simply that the SWF is to aggregate, not simply the utilities of a finite particular population, but an ongoing sequence of overlapping generations of utility-experiencing persons.
    • The "infinite utility stream" idea is less intimidating than might first be assumed. In essence, the idea is simply that the SWF is to aggregate, not simply the utilities of a finite particular population, but an ongoing sequence of overlapping generations of utility-experiencing persons.
  • 116
    • 70449130284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 54, at 306.
    • Koopmans, supra note 54, at 306.
    • Koopmans1
  • 117
    • 21344447418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An axiomatic approach to sustainable development
    • See Chichilnisky's paper also is interesting in showing that convergence criteria of the sort commonly employed to avoid the "but isn't it all infinite?" objection mentioned above-in particular the widely preferred "long-run average" and "catch-up" criteria-for their parts imply dictatorship of the future. Id. at 242-43.
    • See Graciela Chichilnisky, An Axiomatic Approach to Sustainable Development, 13 Soc. CHOICE & WELFARE 231, 242 (1996). Chichilnisky's paper also is interesting in showing that convergence criteria of the sort commonly employed to avoid the "but isn't it all infinite?" objection mentioned above-in particular the widely preferred "long-run average" and "catch-up" criteria-for their parts imply dictatorship of the future. Id. at 242-43.
    • (1996) 13 Soc. Choice & Welfare , vol.231 , pp. 242
    • Chichilnisky, G.1
  • 118
    • 0013077854 scopus 로고
    • Foundations of decision analysis: Along the way
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., Peter C. Fishburn, Foundations of Decision Analysis: Along the Way, 35 MOMT. SCI. 387, 393 (1989).
    • (1989) 35 Momt. Sci. , vol.387 , pp. 393
    • Fishburn, P.C.1
  • 119
    • 70449095671 scopus 로고
    • Burness, on the role of separability assumptions in determining impatience implications
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., H. Stuart Burness, On the Role of Separability Assumptions in Determining Impatience Implications, 44 ECONOMETRICA 67, 77-78 (1976).
    • (1976) 44 Econometrica , vol.67 , pp. 77-78
    • Stuart, H.1
  • 120
    • 0000314580 scopus 로고
    • Equity among generations
    • See
    • See Lars-Gunnar Svensson, Equity Among Generations, 48 ECONOMETRICA 1251 (1980).
    • (1980) 48 Econometrica , vol.1251
    • Svensson, L.-G.1
  • 121
    • 70449095674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The sup top is the topology of least upper bounds of all point sets. It is accordingly familiar to all who have studied introductory analysis courses in the modern mathematics curriculum.
    • The sup top is the topology of least upper bounds of all point sets. It is accordingly familiar to all who have studied introductory analysis courses in the modern mathematics curriculum.
  • 122
    • 70449093486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflective intensions: Two foundational decision-points in mathematics, law, and economics
    • See generally
    • See generally Robert Hockett, Reflective Intensions: Two Foundational Decision-Points in Mathematics, Law, and Economics, 29 CARDOZO L. REV. 1967 (2008).
    • (2008) 29 Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.1967
    • Hockett, R.1
  • 123
    • 84869689129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 60, at 1254-55. An ordering is a relation £ among objects within a defined domain x, x', x",... such that (a) for all x, x £ x; (b) for any x and x', if x £ x' and x' i x, then x = x'; (c) for any x, x and x", if x £ x' and x' £ x", then x £ x"; and (d) for any two objects x and x', either x £ x' or x' £ x. Condition (a) is typically called "reflexivity." Condition (b) is called "antisymmetry." Condition (c) is called "transitivity." And condition (d) is called "comparability." A preorder is a relation that satisfies only conditions (a) and (c)-reflexivity and transitivity. These definitions are standard, and can be found in most logic and set-theoretic texts. They also figure, under varying terminologies, in much of the social choice literature. See, e.g.. SEN, supra note 48, at 2-20.
    • See Svensson, supra note 60, at 1254-55. An ordering is a relation £ among objects within a defined domain x, x', x",... such that (a) for all x, x £ x; (b) for any x and x', if x £ x' and x' i x, then x = x'; (c) for any x, x and x", if x £ x' and x' £ x", then x £ x"; and (d) for any two objects x and x', either x £ x' or x' £ x. Condition (a) is typically called "reflexivity." Condition (b) is called "antisymmetry." Condition (c) is called "transitivity." And condition (d) is called "comparability." A preorder is a relation that satisfies only conditions (a) and (c)-reflexivity and transitivity. These definitions are standard, and can be found in most logic and set-theoretic texts. They also figure, under varying terminologies, in much of the social choice literature. See, e.g.. SEN, supra note 48, at 2-20.
    • Svensson1
  • 124
    • 84869689130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Axiom of Choice, also known (to followers of Russell and Whitehead) as the "Multiplicative Axiom," holds that for any class of classes, there is a function that selects one and only one member from each of them. See Hockett, supra note 60, at 2037-38. The link between the Axiom and Svensson's result can be seen clearly when one reflects that the Axiom, first stated explicitly by Zermelo in 1904, is equivalent to Zermelo's Well-Ordering Theorem, to the effect that there is a well-ordering for every set-i.e., that every set is well ordered, and each of its nonempty subsets has a least member.
    • The Axiom of Choice, also known (to followers of Russell and Whitehead) as the "Multiplicative Axiom," holds that for any class of classes, there is a function that selects one and only one member from each of them. See Hockett, supra note 60, at 2037-38. The link between the Axiom and Svensson's result can be seen clearly when one reflects that the Axiom, first stated explicitly by Zermelo in 1904, is equivalent to Zermelo's Well-Ordering Theorem, to the effect that there is a well-ordering for every set-i.e., that every set is well ordered, and each of its nonempty subsets has a least member.
  • 125
    • 70449107917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare id., with Svensson, supra note 60, at 1254-55. These propositions are intuitively plausible enough for the finite and denumerably infinite cases, but are a bit more difficult to make sense of in the nondenumerably infinite case.
    • Compare id., with Svensson, supra note 60, at 1254-55. These propositions are intuitively plausible enough for the finite and denumerably infinite cases, but are a bit more difficult to make sense of in the nondenumerably infinite case.
  • 126
    • 84869672299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hockett, supra note 60. The intuition that underwrites the Axiom of Choice is at work, incidentally, in the "Choice Functions" of which Sen has availed himself in many of his canonical works of the 1970s and 1980s.
    • See Hockett, supra note 60. The intuition that underwrites the Axiom of Choice is at work, incidentally, in the "Choice Functions" of which Sen has availed himself in many of his canonical works of the 1970s and 1980s.
  • 128
    • 70449093487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 60, at 2042.
    • See Hockett, supra note 60, at 2042.
    • Hockett1
  • 129
    • 0008218438 scopus 로고
    • Impossibility theorems and infinite horizon planning
    • See generalizing Diamond result to other topologies
    • See D. E. Campbell, Impossibility Theorems and Infinite Horizon Planning, 2 Soc. CHOICE & WELFARE 283 (1985) (generalizing Diamond result to other topologies).
    • (1985) 2 Soc. Choice & Welfare , vol.283
    • Campbell, D.E.1
  • 130
    • 0031483456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Continuity and equity with infinite horizons
    • generalizing Diamond result to other topologies
    • Luc Lauwers, Continuity and Equity with Infinite Horizons, 14 Soc. CHOICE & WELFARE 345, 353-54 (1997) (generalizing Diamond result to other topologies).
    • (1997) 14 Soc. Choice & Welfare , vol.345 , pp. 353-354
    • Lauwers, L.1
  • 131
    • 21944451145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equity, continuity, and myopia: A generalization of diamond's impossibility theorem
    • generalizing Diamond result to other topologies
    • Tomoichi Shinotsuka, Equity, Continuity, and Myopia: A Generalization of Diamond's Impossibility Theorem, 15 Soc CHOICE & WELFARE 21 (1998) (generalizing Diamond result to other topologies).
    • (1998) 15 Soc Choice & Welfare , vol.21
    • Shinotsuka, T.1
  • 132
    • 0042429124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intertemporal equity and extension of the ramsey criterion
    • (another pre-ordering with Szpilrajn's Lemma implying an ordering, a la Svensson).
    • Marc Fleurbaey & Phillipe Michel, Intertemporal Equity and Extension of the Ramsey Criterion, 39 J. MATH. ECON. 777 (2003) (another pre-ordering with Szpilrajn's Lemma implying an ordering, a la Svensson).
    • (2003) J. Math. Econ. , vol.39
    • Fleurbaey, M.1    Michel, P.2
  • 133
    • 2942754039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Resolving distributional conflicts between generations
    • (like Svensson, constructing a pre-ordering, then relying upon Szpilrajn's Lemma to claim existence of an ordering-in this case, a version of leximin).
    • Geir B. Asheim & Bertil Tungodden, Resolving Distributional Conflicts Between Generations, 24 ECON. THEORY 221 (2004) (like Svensson, constructing a pre-ordering, then relying upon Szpilrajn's Lemma to claim existence of an ordering-in this case, a version of leximin).
    • (2004) 24 Econ. Theory , vol.221
    • Geir, B.1    Asheim2    Tungodden, B.3
  • 134
    • 34250652552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ordering infinite utility streams
    • as with Asheim & Tungodden, supra note 68
    • Walter Bossert et al., Ordering Infinite Utility Streams, 135 J. ECON. THEORY 579 (2007) (as with Asheim & Tungodden, supra note 68).
    • (2007) 135 J. Econ. Theory , vol.579
    • Bossert, W.1
  • 135
    • 34250731242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can intergenerational equity be operationalized?
    • See
    • See William R. Zame, Can Intergenerational Equity Be Operationalized?, 2 THEORETICAL ECON. 187 (2007).
    • (2007) 2 Theoretical Econ. , vol.187
    • Zame, W.R.1
  • 136
    • 0004070712 scopus 로고
    • Logisch-kombinatorische untersuchungen iiber die erfullbarkeit oder beweisbarkeit mathematischer satze nebst einem theoreme iiber dichte mengen
    • See
    • See Thoralf Skolem, Logisch-kombinatorische Untersuchungen iiber die Erfullbarkeit oder Beweisbarkeit mathematischer Satze nebst einem Theoreme iiber dichte Mengen, 6 VIDEN-SKAPSSELSKAPET SKRIFTER, I. MATEMATISK- NATURVIDENSKABELIG KLASSE 1 (1920).
    • (1920) 6 Viden-Skapsselskapet Skrifter, I. Matematisk-Naturvidenskabelig Klasse , vol.1
    • Skolem, T.1
  • 137
    • 70449112461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Translated in logico-combinatorial investigations on the satisfiability or provability of mathematical propositions: A simplified proof of a theorem by loewenheim
    • supra note 18. As suggested in the English rendering of the title, the Skolem result generalized an earlier one derived by Lowenheim.
    • translated in Logico-Combinatorial Investigations on the Satisfiability or Provability of Mathematical Propositions: A Simplified Proof of a Theorem by Loewenheim, in FROM FREGE TO GODEL: A SOURCE BOOK IN MATHEMATICAL LOGIC, 1879-1931, supra note 18. As suggested in the English rendering of the title, the Skolem result generalized an earlier one derived by Lowenheim.
    • Frege to Godel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic , pp. 1879-1931
  • 138
  • 139
    • 70449093485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Translated in on possibilities in the calculus of relatives
    • supra note 18.
    • translated in On Possibilities in the Calculus of Relatives, in FROM FREGE TO GODEL, supra note 18.
    • From Frege to Godel
  • 140
    • 0009207917 scopus 로고
    • Sur les ensembles definissables de nombres rtels I
    • The Tarski results to which I allude are
    • The Tarski results to which I allude are A. Tarski, Sur les ensembles definissables de nombres rtels I, 17 FUNDAMENTA MATHEMATICA 210 (1931)
    • (1931) 17 Fundamenta Mathematica , vol.210
    • Tarski, A.1
  • 142
    • 70449107918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Greg Chaitin's many representation results appear over the course of many books and papers.
    • Greg Chaitin's many representation results appear over the course of many books and papers. Probably the most often read is GREGORY CHAITIN, THE UNKNOWABLE (1999).
    • (1999) Probably the Most Often Read is Gregory Chaitin, the Unknowable
  • 143
    • 84869665787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ordering Infinite Utility Streams: Completeness at the Cost of a Non-Ramsey Set, available at
    • See Luc Lauwers, Ordering Infinite Utility Streams: Completeness at the Cost of a Non-Ramsey Set, available at http://www.eea-esem.com/EEA-ESEM/2007/ Prog/viewpaper.asp?pid=1956.
    • Lauwers, S.L.1
  • 144
    • 0141922700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aggregating infinite utility streams with intergenerational equity: The impossibility of being paretian
    • See
    • See Kaushik Basu & Tapan Mitra, Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams with Intergenerational Equity: The Impossibility of Being Paretian, 71 ECONOMETRICA 1557 (2003).
    • (2003) 71 Econometrica , vol.1557
    • Basu, K.1    Mitra, T.2
  • 145
    • 77949267931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Possibility theorems for equitably aggregating infinite utility streams
    • See John E. Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds. Their paper (1) weakens Pareto and changes domain restrictions to find a way out of Diamond result
    • See Kaushik Basu & Tapan Mitra, Possibility Theorems for Equitably Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams, in, INTEROENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY (John E. Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds. 2007). Their paper (1) weakens Pareto and changes domain restrictions to find a way out of Diamond result
    • (2007) Interoenerational Equity and Sustainability
    • Basu, K.1    Mitra, T.2
  • 146
    • 84869665788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2) tries a "weak dominance" axiom, a "weak Pareto" axiom, and a "partial Pareto" axiom. There is some success with the last of these, but the authors note wryly that in reaching that success, they also show further robustness of the original Diamond result.
    • and (2) tries a "weak dominance" axiom, a "weak Pareto" axiom, and a "partial Pareto" axiom. There is some success with the last of these, but the authors note wryly that in reaching that success, they also show further robustness of the original Diamond result.
  • 147
    • 70449119741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. See generally On the Existence of Pare-tian Social Welfare Quasi-Orderings for Infinite Utility Streams with Extended Anonymity, in INTEROENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY, supra (characterizing the class of possible finite permutations of infinite utility streams consistent with Pareto and social welfare quasi-orderings).
    • See id. See generally Tapan Mitra & Kaushik Basu, On the Existence of Pare-tian Social Welfare Quasi-Orderings for Infinite Utility Streams with Extended Anonymity, in INTEROENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY, supra (characterizing the class of possible finite permutations of infinite utility streams consistent with Pareto and social welfare quasi-orderings).
    • Mitra, T.1    Basu, K.2
  • 148
    • 70449102477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Hockett, supra note 12. By a "preference-incumbent normative principle" I mean simply a normative principle that is incumbent upon-that is, which can trump-preferences. The idea is that normative principles determine which preferences ought to be satisfied, and which are to be renounced or repudiated as contrary to our ethical, social, or legal norms. Any system of norms or laws, by dint of its bestowal of distributed entitlements upon persons, inherently imports some such "trumping," hence partitions the class of all possible satisfactions that an individual might have into distributively legitimate and illegitimate such satisfactions. In-tergenerational "anonymity"-impartiality or equity-is of course such a norm. It might bear noting in this connection that, insofar as norms can trump preferences, there is a clear category error manifest in such locutions, often encountered in some economic writing, as "tastes for justice," "preferences for fairness," and the like. Most who engage in such talk are effectively collapsing normative principles, which are incumbent upon preferences, into preferences themselves. Loss of that distinction in turn is to lose the capacity to prescribe or judge normatively at all. And the incoherence to which I am attending here stems directly from that loss.
    • Hockett1
  • 149
    • 70449095672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. I shall note here as well that Professor Kysar compellingly describes a counterpart problem in cost-benefit analysis.
    • See id. I shall note here as well that Professor Kysar compellingly describes a counterpart problem in cost-benefit analysis.
  • 150
    • 79955706302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might have been: Risk, precaution and opportunity costs
    • See In case the distinction between preference on the one hand, and preference-incumbent normative principle on the other is not immediately clear to you, consider this observation: It is of course ever possible-and indeed to be hoped-that one will "prefer" to conform his actions to principles of normative propriety. But such principles underwrite ethical, legal, and other forms of prescription only inasmuch as they're taken for incumbent upon and hence bounding of preferences, not merely as objects of preferences. George Bush can "prefer" to drive sober and under 120 mph in our neighborhood, for example, and we all hope that he will, but a legal or ethical limit's being a "limit" is precisely its trumping his preference should he come to "prefer" otherwise and thus put all of us at risk.
    • See Douglas A. Kysar, It Might Have Been: Risk, Precaution and Opportunity Costs, 22 J. LAND USE & ENVTL. L. 1, 44 (2006). In case the distinction between preference on the one hand, and preference-incumbent normative principle on the other is not immediately clear to you, consider this observation: It is of course ever possible-and indeed to be hoped-that one will "prefer" to conform his actions to principles of normative propriety. But such principles underwrite ethical, legal, and other forms of prescription only inasmuch as they're taken for incumbent upon and hence bounding of preferences, not merely as objects of preferences. George Bush can "prefer" to drive sober and under 120 mph in our neighborhood, for example, and we all hope that he will, but a legal or ethical limit's being a "limit" is precisely its trumping his preference should he come to "prefer" otherwise and thus put all of us at risk.
    • (2006) 22 J. Land Use & Envtl. L. , vol.1 , pp. 44
    • Kysar, D.A.1
  • 151
    • 84869680763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Paretian "veto," see supra note 48.
    • On the Paretian "veto," see supra note 48.
  • 152
    • 84869665785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Individualist" SWFs simply are SWFs that take individual utility functions as arguments.
    • "Individualist" SWFs simply are SWFs that take individual utility functions as arguments.
  • 153
    • 70449107915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 12. The term appears to originate with Samuelson.
    • See Hockett, supra note 12. The term appears to originate with Samuelson.
    • Hockett1
  • 155
    • 0034993690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the pareto principle
    • see also Welfarism" for its part misleadingly names the untenable position that SWFs should take "only" such individual utility functions as arguments.
    • see also Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Any Non-Welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle, 109 J. POL. ECON. 281, 281 (2001). "Welfarism" for its part misleadingly names the untenable position that SWFs should take "only" such individual utility functions as arguments.
    • (2001) 109 J. Pol. Econ. , vol.281 , pp. 281
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 156
    • 70449112460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 12
    • See Hockett, supra note 12
    • Hockett1
  • 157
    • 0042671102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fairness versus welfare: Notes on the pareto principle, preferences, and distributive justice, 32
    • see also Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Fairness Versus Welfare: Notes on the Pareto Principle, Preferences, and Distributive Justice, 32 J. LEGAL STUD. 331 (2003)
    • (2003) J. Legal Stud. , vol.331
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 158
    • 0042421849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fairness versus welfare: Notes on the pareto principle, preferences, and distributive justice
    • The term "welfarism" would be better replaced by "strict welfarism," however, or better yet "strict preference-regard," since (a) most self-described "welfarists" unpack "welfare" as no more than preference-satisfaction, while (b) it is of course possible to represent social welfare as riding upon one or more variables additional to individual preference-satisfactions in any event.
    • Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Fairness Versus Welfare: Notes on the Pareto Principle, Preferences, and Distributive Justice, 114 HARV. L. REV. 961 (2001). The term "welfarism" would be better replaced by "strict welfarism," however, or better yet "strict preference-regard," since (a) most self-described "welfarists" unpack "welfare" as no more than preference-satisfaction, while (b) it is of course possible to represent social welfare as riding upon one or more variables additional to individual preference-satisfactions in any event.
    • (2001) 114 Harv. L. Rev. , vol.961
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 160
    • 0004072463 scopus 로고
    • see also This is but the tip of a vast and vexing iceberg.
    • see also JONATHAN GLOVER, WHAT SORT OF PEOPLE SHOULD THERE BE? (1984). This is but the tip of a vast and vexing iceberg.
    • (1984) What Sort of People Should There Be?
    • Glover, J.1
  • 161
    • 84869665786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DEP'T OF ECON. & Soc. AFFAIRS, UNITED NATIONS, available at
    • DEP'T OF ECON. & Soc. AFFAIRS, UNITED NATIONS, WORLD POPULATION IN 2300, at 2 (2004), available at http:7Avww.un.org/esa/populatioii/publications/ longrange2/2004worldpop2300reportfinalc.pdf.
    • (2004) World Population in 2300 , vol.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.