메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 34, Issue 1, 1999, Pages 163-199

Loving's legacy: The other antidiscrimination principles

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 7044241310     PISSN: 00178039     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (3)

References (157)
  • 1
    • 84889195853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 388 U.S. 1 (1967) (striking down under the Equal Protection Clause a state law prohibiting interracial marriage)
    • 388 U.S. 1 (1967) (striking down under the Equal Protection Clause a state law prohibiting interracial marriage).
  • 2
    • 84889192641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200, 217 (1995) ("Loving v. Virginia, which struck down a race-based state law, cited Korematsu for the proposition that 'the Equal Protection Clause demands that racial classifications ... be subjected to the 'most rigid scrutiny.'"); Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630, 643 (1993) (citing Loving for the proposition that classifications on the basis of race are odious to equality). Dissenting voices on the Court, however, continue to notice Loving's more revolutionary implications: "Not until Loving v. Virginia . . . could one say with security that the Constitution and this Court would abide no measure 'designed to maintain White Supremacy. '"Adarand, 515 U.S. at 272 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting).
  • 3
    • 84889193523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Virginia Code § 20-59 provided: Punishment for marriage. - If any white person intermarry with a colored person, or any colored person with a white person, he shall be guilty of a felony and shall be punished by confinement in the penitentiary for not less than one nor more than five years. Loving, 388 U.S. at 4.
  • 4
    • 84889210709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 10. Incidentally, the racially restrictive property covenant challenged in Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1 (1948), arguably raised a similar mirror-image discrimination problem: the covenant prevented both the willing (black) buyer and the willing (white) seller from engaging in the land sale, thus treating "each participant . . . the same." Loving, 388 U.S. at 10. The Court, preoccupied with the state-action question, however, simply ignored this equal treatment argument. Indeed, despite the fact that the covenant on its face was only directed at restricting the seller's freedom, the Court focused solely on the denial of rights to black homebuyers. See Shelley, 334 U.S. at 20-21
    • Id. at 10. Incidentally, the racially restrictive property covenant challenged in Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1 (1948), arguably raised a similar mirror-image discrimination problem: the covenant prevented both the willing (black) buyer and the willing (white) seller from engaging in the land sale, thus treating "each participant . . . the same." Loving, 388 U.S. at 10. The Court, preoccupied with the state-action question, however, simply ignored this equal treatment argument. Indeed, despite the fact that the covenant on its face was only directed at restricting the seller's freedom, the Court focused solely on the denial of rights to black homebuyers. See Shelley, 334 U.S. at 20-21.
  • 5
    • 84889200015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Loving, 388 U.S. at 11-12; see also id. at 13 (Stewart, J., concurring)
    • See Loving, 388 U.S. at 11-12; see also id. at 13 (Stewart, J., concurring).
  • 6
    • 84935526916 scopus 로고
    • Feminist Jurisprudence: The Difference Method Makes
    • This is precisely why the specter of the "equal opportunity sexual harasser" - the bisexual who harasses both men and women sexually-haunts the jurisprudence of sexual harassment. See, e.g., Barnes v. Costle, 561 F.2d 983, 990 n.55 (D.C. Cir. 1977) ("These situations . . . are to be distinguished from a bisexual superior who conditions the employment opportunities of a subordinate of either gender upon participation in a sexual affair. In the case of the bisexual superior, the insistence upon sexual favors would not constitute gender discrimination because it would apply to male and female employees alike."). See also, e.g., Easton v. Crossland Mortgage Corp., 905 F. Supp. 1368, 1379 (C.D. Cal. 1995) (finding a cause of action for same-sex sexual harassment and discussing the recent Ninth Circuit decision in Steiner v. Showboat Operating Co., 25 F.3d 1459 (9th Cir. 1991), in which the Ninth Circuit refused to rule out the possibility of a claim against an equal opportunity harasser); Chiapuzio v. BLT Operating Corp., 826 F. Supp. 1334, 1337 (D. Wyo. 1993) (holding that "the equal harassment of both genders does not escape the purview of Title VII" in a case where the harasser "intended to demean, and therefore harm" all of his victims because of their gender); Christine A. Littleton, Feminist Jurisprudence: The Difference Method Makes, 41 STAN. L. REV. 751, 769-70 (1989) (raising as a concern the possibility that equal oportunity harassers may be the "most resistant to liability" because of the lack of clarity in the doctrine).
    • (1989) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.41 , pp. 751
    • Littleton, C.A.1
  • 7
    • 84889224872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • That is, "neutrality" can be used in two senses. The first is that of equal application - the idea that a law "neutral" between groups does not take sides; it treats members of one group no better or worse than members of any other group. This is the sense in which neutrality is a value of procedural fairness and a conception of the antidiscrimination principle. The other sense of neutrality is that of color-blindness - the idea that a neutral law draws no race-conscious distinctions. In this conception, the neutrality principle expresses a substantive or outcomes-based value more than a procedural one (except, of course, to the extent that a decision making process infected with race-consciousness is per se unfair). This distinction is developed further infra Part I.A.
  • 8
    • 84889202575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The consistency principle condemns inconsistency in the pursuit of a particular value or goal such that its burdens are imposed only on certain parts of society while other parts : are specifically excluded even though inclusion of those parts would further the goal. This A principle is developed infra Part II.
  • 9
    • 84889176845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Loving, 388 U.S. at 8
    • See Loving, 388 U.S. at 8.
  • 10
    • 21344484319 scopus 로고
    • A History of Same-Sex Marriage
    • However, sex-based restrictions in the choice of marriage partner are constrained. Loving has thus been employed by theorists (and courts) arguing to invalidate the proscription on same-sex marriage on equal protection grounds. See, e.g., Baehr v. Lewin, 852 P.2d 44, 67-68 (Haw. 1993); William N. Eskridge, Jr., A History of Same-Sex Marriage, 79 VA. L. REV. 1419, 1504-10 (1993).
    • (1993) Va. L. Rev. , vol.79 , pp. 1419
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1
  • 11
    • 84889185948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Loving, 388 U.S. at 8. It is again to this racial double standard on marital choice, in addition to the neutrality violation, that the Court alludes when it claims: "There can be no doubt that restricting the freedom to marry solely because of racial classifications violates the central meaning of the Equal Protection Clause." Id. at 12.
  • 12
    • 84889222019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 12n.11
    • Id. at 12n.11.
  • 13
    • 84889172757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It may seem at first glance that this conception of the double standard gets the social meaning of the statute wrong, since it seems to imply that whites are the ones discriminated against by being subjected to a special penalty for intermarriage that is not imposed on nonwhites who marry (each other) interracially. The Virginia law, however, can be recharacterized, not as a penalty for those who intermarry, but as a protection for the (racist) interests of those who do not. The double standard then is one that fails to give the "racial integrity" and "racial pride" interests of nonwhites the same "protection" as that of whites.
  • 14
    • 84889208958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The impartiality principle disfavors governmental action motivated by the bare desire to disadvantage an identifiable group, or giving effect to that desire within the polity. It reflects an exercise of raw political power as apart from action motivated by public values or deliberative reason. This principle is developed further infra Part III.
  • 15
    • 84889234435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Loving, 388 U.S. at 8
    • Loving, 388 U.S. at 8.
  • 16
    • 84889226726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 7 (quoting Naim v. Naim, 87 S.E.2d 749, 756 (Va. 1955) (upholding antimiscegenation laws))
    • Id. at 7 (quoting Naim v. Naim, 87 S.E.2d 749, 756 (Va. 1955) (upholding antimiscegenation laws)).
  • 17
    • 84889209265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. at 11 ("The fact that Virginia prohibits only interracial marriages involving white persons demonstrates that the racial classifications must stand on their own justification, as measures designed to maintain White Supremacy.").
  • 18
    • 84889211009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. ("There is patently no legitimate overriding purpose independent of invidious racial discrimination which justifies this classification.").
  • 19
    • 84889180787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As discussed infra in Parts II and III, we can see the consistency and impartiality principles also guiding other groundbreaking cases like Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620 (1996), United States Department of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528 (1973), and Hunter v. Erickson, 393 U.S. 385 (1969).
  • 20
    • 84889217760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 21 Romer, 517 U.S. at 623 (quoting Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting)). See also, e.g., City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., 488 U.S. 469, 521 (1989) (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment) (quoting the same language of Justice Harlan's, beginning with the famous words "Our Constitution is color-blind").
  • 21
    • 0041161556 scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court, 1975 Term - Foreword: In Defense of the Antidiscrimination Principle
    • Paul Brest, The Supreme Court, 1975 Term - Foreword: In Defense of the Antidiscrimination Principle, 90 HARV. L. REV. 1, 1 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.90 , pp. 1
    • Brest, P.1
  • 22
    • 84889193273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 220, 221-22 (1982) (quoting Weber v. Aetna Cas. & Sur. Co., 406 U.S. 164, 175 (1972))
    • Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 220, 221-22 (1982) (quoting Weber v. Aetna Cas. & Sur. Co., 406 U.S. 164, 175 (1972)).
  • 23
    • 84889202816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coalition for Econ. Equity v. Wilson, 110 F.3d 1431, 1439 (9th Cir. 1997) (emphasis added)
    • Coalition for Econ. Equity v. Wilson, 110 F.3d 1431, 1439 (9th Cir. 1997) (emphasis added).
  • 24
    • 84889171388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 518 U.S. 515 (1996)
    • 518 U.S. 515 (1996).
  • 25
    • 84889194949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 550; see also Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 204 (1976) ("[P]roving broad sociological propositions by statistics is a dubious business, and one that inevitably is in tension with the normative philosophy that underlies the Equal Protection Clause.").
  • 26
    • 84889178364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • That is, the state's ban on interracial marriage at issue in that case used race-specific classifications while treating blacks and whites who intermarry equally. See supra notes 3-7 and accompanying text.
  • 27
    • 84889181955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. supra notes 24-26 and accompanying text
    • Cf. supra notes 24-26 and accompanying text.
  • 28
    • 84889199685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U.S. 81, 100 (1943) (upholding discriminatory curfew placed on American citizens of Japanese ancestry, however, on the ground that this consideration did have relevance "bearing on the loyalty of populations in the danger areas" potentially threatened with Japanese invasion during World War II).
  • 29
    • 84889189432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although sometimes the evidence to the contrary may be based on group-wide assumptions. See id. at 101 (alluding to "recognition of facts and circumstances which indicate that a group of one national extraction may menace [the nation's] safety more than others," among these circumstances "the fact . . . that attack on our shores was threatened by Japan rather than another enemy power").
  • 30
    • 84889216294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting)
    • See Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting).
  • 31
    • 84889190537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200, 240 (1995) (Thomas, J., concurring); see also id. at 236 (reiterating that "'[b]ecause racial characteristics so seldom provide a relevant basis for disparate treatment, and because classifications based on race are potentially so harmful to the entire body politic, it is especially important that the reasons for any such classification be clearly identified and unquestionably legitimate.'" (emphasis added) (quoting Fullilove v. Klutznick, 448 U.S. 448, 537 (1980) (Stevens, J., dissenting))).
  • 32
    • 84889170133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630, 643 (1993)
    • Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630, 643 (1993).
  • 33
    • 84889178687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Affirmative Action's Other Side: Victims
    • Editorial, Nov. 1
    • See, e.g., John C. Liu, Editorial, Affirmative Action's Other Side: Victims, SAN DIEGO UNION-TRIE., Nov. 1, 1996, at B7 ("Unfortunately, the worthy goals of affirmative action have evolved over the past 30 years to the point that the words 'equal opportunity' have been substituted with 'equal outcomes.'"); Michael Nyilis, Editorial, Affirmative Misconceptions, WASH. TIMES, July 17, 1997 at A19 ("What anti-preference supporters propose is replacing . . . equal outcomes with equal opportunity, . . . discrimination based on skin color with equality before the law.").
    • (1996) San Diego Union-trie
    • Liu, J.C.1
  • 34
    • 84889191032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Affirmative Misconceptions
    • Editorial, July 17
    • See, e.g., John C. Liu, Editorial, Affirmative Action's Other Side: Victims, SAN DIEGO UNION-TRIE., Nov. 1, 1996, at B7 ("Unfortunately, the worthy goals of affirmative action have evolved over the past 30 years to the point that the words 'equal opportunity' have been substituted with 'equal outcomes.'"); Michael Nyilis, Editorial, Affirmative Misconceptions, WASH. TIMES, July 17, 1997 at A19 ("What anti-preference supporters propose is replacing . . . equal outcomes with equal opportunity, . . . discrimination based on skin color with equality before the law.").
    • (1997) Wash. Times
    • Nyilis, M.1
  • 35
    • 84889185297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229, 239 (1976) (holding that the racially disproportionate impact of a facially neutral test does not render it unconstitutional absent a racially discriminatory purpose).
  • 36
    • 84889201105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • That is, Washington v. Davis holds that while the Constitution forbids tests adopted for the discriminatory purpose of disadvantaging a particular racial group (reflecting unequal treatment in official decision making) as well as tests that are not neutral but distinguish between candidates on the basis of race (reflecting unequal treatment in the substantive law), it nevertheless tolerates tests that have a disproportionate racial impact for other reasons (reflected in unequal outcomes). See id.
  • 37
    • 0346114679 scopus 로고
    • Antidiscrimination Law: The View from 1989
    • The antidiscrimination principle, as other commentators have noted, adopts a "perpetrator perspective" in which "fault" is a central element. See Alan Freeman, Antidiscrimination Law: The View from 1989, 64 TUL. L. REV. 1407, 1412-13 (1990).
    • (1990) Tul. L. Rev. , vol.64 , pp. 1407
    • Freeman, A.1
  • 38
    • 84889218731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The doctrinal implication that constitutional violation must be predicated on governmental responsibility is underscored by the discussion in Washington v. Davis of the plaintiff-job applicants' failure to pass Test 21, a written verbal skill level test. See 426 U.S. 229, 245-46 (1976). The Court attributes this failure solely to the applicants' own lesser abilities, see id., and is quite obviously appalled at charging the government with discrimination towards them. It is likewise this idea of lack of governmental responsibility (hence lack of governmental discrimination) to which Plessy appealed in claiming that if "the enforced separation of the two races stamps the colored race with a badge of inferiority . . . it is not by reason of anything found in the act, but solely because the colored race chooses to put that construction on it." Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 551 (1896).
  • 39
    • 84889229900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 3-18 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 3-18 and accompanying text.
  • 40
    • 84889192860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Cf Watson v. Fort Worth Bank & Trust, 487 U.S. 977, 987-88 (1988) (plurality opinion) (declaring the functional equivalence of intentional discrimination "where facially neutral job requirements necessarily operated to perpetuate the effects of [the private employer's] intentional discrimination that occurred before Title VII was enacted" (citing Griggs v. Duke Power Co., 401 U.S. 424, 426-28, 431-32 (1971))).
  • 41
    • 0003974417 scopus 로고
    • The following discussion draws heavily on the antidiscrimination analysis of abortion laws in CASS R. SUNSTEIN, THE PARTIAL CONSTITUTION 272-85 (1993) and Guido Calabresi, The Supreme Court, 1990 Term - Foreword: Antidiscrimination and Constitutional Accountability (What the Bork-Brennan Debate Ignores), 105 HARV. L. REV. 80, 91-93 (1991).
    • (1993) The Partial Constitution , pp. 272-285
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 42
    • 59649111613 scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court, 1990 Term - Foreword: Antidiscrimination and Constitutional Accountability (What the Bork-Brennan Debate Ignores)
    • The following discussion draws heavily on the antidiscrimination analysis of abortion laws in CASS R. SUNSTEIN, THE PARTIAL CONSTITUTION 272-85 (1993) and Guido Calabresi, The Supreme Court, 1990 Term - Foreword: Antidiscrimination and Constitutional Accountability (What the Bork-Brennan Debate Ignores), 105 HARV. L. REV. 80, 91-93 (1991).
    • (1991) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.105 , pp. 80
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 43
    • 84889213148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See infra notes 49-57 and accompanying text (discussing typical neutrality analysis of sex-based distinctions in pension fund plan, and contrasting it with expanded inconsistency analysis).
  • 44
    • 84889199675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., 488 U.S. 469, 493 (1989) (striking down city's plan requiring contractors to subcontract at least 30% of their contracts to "Minority Business Enterprises").
  • 45
    • 84889198020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Even VMI, in which Justice Ginsburg purported to use the less demanding intermediate scrutiny standard, employed conventional means-ends equal protection analysis to strike down long-standing sex segregation at the Virginia Military Institute, finding the exclusion of women from its "adversative training" curriculum to be based on impermissible group assumptions and stereotypes. See United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515 (1996).
  • 46
    • 84889231754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Geduldig v. Aiello, 417 U.S. 484, 496 n.20 (1974) (finding no sex-based discrimination in a medical disability policy exempting pregnancy disability because "pregnancy is an objectively identifiable condition with unique characteristics," and holding that "[t]he program divides potential recipients into two groups - pregnant women and nonpregnant persons").
  • 47
    • 0040374696 scopus 로고
    • Legislative Purpose, Rationality, and Equal Protection
    • See Note, Legislative Purpose, Rationality, and Equal Protection, 82 YALE L.J. 123, 128-132 (1972).
    • (1972) Yale L.J. , vol.82 , pp. 123
  • 48
    • 84889173247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Cf. Rostker v. Goldberg, 453 U.S. 57 (1981) (upholding the exclusion of women from compulsory registration under the Military Selective Service Act).
  • 49
    • 79955551488 scopus 로고
    • Groups and the Equal Protection Clause
    • Cf. Owen M. Fiss, Groups and the Equal Protection Clause, 5 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 107, 108-11 (1976) (arguing that equal protection analysis of racial discrimination emphasizes means-ends rationality).
    • (1976) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.5 , pp. 107
    • Fiss, O.M.1
  • 50
    • 84889222820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 435 U.S. 702 (1978) (striking down as a violation of Title VII's disparate treatment prong a city department's requirement that female employees make larger contributions to the pension fund than male employees).
  • 51
    • 84889204265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 704
    • See id. at 704.
  • 52
    • 84889180959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Indeed, discussion of these issues consumes the bulk of the majority's constitutional analysis, see id. at 707-16, as well as the dissent's, see id. at 726-28 (Burger, C.J., dissenting in part).
  • 53
    • 84889203897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The interest should be framed in terms of actuarial fairness generally, rather than just actuarial fairness between men and women. Stating the interest in terms of a gendered subject basically defines the interest in terms of the governmental means pursued, and cuts off inquiry into inconsistent treatment of the gendered aspect of the subject compared to other aspects.
  • 54
    • 84889187341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As the Court notes, there is also a substantial difference between black and white life expectancy. See Manhart at 709 n.15.
  • 55
    • 84889190061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Indeed, the city's omission of racial criteria is rendered even more suspect by the fact that it is blacks who are actuarially disadvantaged under an equal contribution policy. Thus, where men are actuarially harmed under an equal contribution policy, the city "sees" unfairness and requires women to contribute more, but where blacks are the group harmed, the city takes no action to restore actuarial fairness. This suggests that the city's policy can : be challenged as racially discriminatory too, for not pursuing racial actuarial fairness where the city has indicated that such fairness is an important governmental interest.
  • 56
    • 84889194837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Personnel Adm'r v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256, 278-81 (1979) (rejecting equal protection challenge that a veterans preference statute discriminates impermissibly on the basis of sex merely because the vastly disparate impact on women was foreseeable, because constitutional "'discriminatory purpose' . . . implies more than intent as volition or intent as awareness of consequences").
  • 57
    • 84889197891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • With ordinary social and economic legislation, "reform may take one step at a time, addressing itself to the phase of the problem which seems most acute to the legislative mind." Williamson v. Lee Optical, Inc., 348 U.S. 483, 489 (1955).
  • 58
    • 84889198533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 58 See, e.g., Washington v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 458 U.S. 457, 477 (1982); Hunter v. Erickson, 393 U.S. 385 (1969). This line of cases is discussed infra Part II., sections A.-B.
  • 59
    • 84889227959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 393 U.S. 385 (1969)
    • 393 U.S. 385 (1969).
  • 60
    • 84889184423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 387
    • See id. at 387.
  • 61
    • 84889189052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See The Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3 (1883) (holding that the Fourteenth Amendment is not intended to protect individual rights against private invasion but only against impairment by state action). But cf. Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1 (1948) (finding the requisite state action for violation of the Fourteenth Amendment in the legal enforcement of racially restrictive property covenants).
  • 62
    • 84889175190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hunter, 393 U.S. at 390
    • Hunter, 393 U.S. at 390.
  • 63
    • 84889204547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 392
    • Id. at 392.
  • 64
    • 84889220391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 389
    • Id. at 389.
  • 65
    • 84889171631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 66
    • 84889199602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 390. The Court noted that "[t]he automatic referendum system does not reach housing discrimination on sexual or political grounds, or against those with children or dogs, nor does it affect tenants seeking more heat or better maintenance from landlords, nor those seeking rent control, urban renewal, public housing, or new building codes." Id. at 391.
  • 67
    • 84889205243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • W. at 391
    • W. at 391.
  • 68
    • 84889171109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We see this reasoning again in Washington v. Seattle School District No. 1, 458 U.S. 457 (1982), a case involving a law banning busing of school children for desegregation purposes while allowing a wide variety of exceptions for other purposes - which is a post-Washington v. Davis case. Justice Blackmun reasoned that busing for integration is essentially a "racial" issue, because "desegregation of the public schools . . . at bottom inures primarily to the benefit of the minority, and is designed for that purpose." Seattle Sch. Dist. at 472. Thus, the Court held, the law "must fall because it does 'not attemp[t] to allocate governmental power on the basis of any general principle.' Instead, it uses the racial nature of an issue to define the government decision making structure, and thus imposes substantial and unique burdens on racial minorities." Id. at 470 (quoting Hunter, 393 U.S. at 395 (Harlan, J., concurring)).
  • 69
    • 84889195630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 426 U.S. 229 (1976)
    • 426 U.S. 229 (1976).
  • 70
    • 84889173172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seattle Sch. Dist., 458 U.S. at 485
    • Seattle Sch. Dist., 458 U.S. at 485.
  • 71
    • 84889172031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 474
    • Id. at 474.
  • 72
    • 0348138704 scopus 로고
    • Disproportionate Impact and Illicit Motive: Theories of Constitutional Adjudication
    • For a compelling, but ultimately too open-ended, argument about using causation as a limiting principle for disparate impact cases, see Theodore Eisenberg, Disproportionate Impact and Illicit Motive: Theories of Constitutional Adjudication, 52 N.Y.U. L. REV. 36 (1977).
    • (1977) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.52 , pp. 36
    • Eisenberg, T.1
  • 73
    • 84889177415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seattle Sch. Dist., 458 U.S. at 484 (citation omitted) (quoting Hunter, 393 U.S. at 394 (Harlan, J., concurring))
    • Seattle Sch. Dist., 458 U.S. at 484 (citation omitted) (quoting Hunter, 393 U.S. at 394 (Harlan, J., concurring)).
  • 74
    • 84889200259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 497 U.S. 547 (1990) (O'Connor, J., dissenting)
    • 497 U.S. 547 (1990) (O'Connor, J., dissenting).
  • 75
    • 84889204065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • W. at 615 (O'Connor, J., dissenting); see also J.E.B. v. Alabama, 511 U.S. 127, 140 (1994) (arguing that "[t]he community is harmed by the State's participation in the perpetuation of invidious group stereotypes" and holding that intentional discrimination on the basis of gender by state actors in the use of preemptory jury challenges violates the Equal Protection Clause).
  • 76
    • 84889227934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 458 U.S. 457 (1982)
    • 458 U.S. 457 (1982).
  • 77
    • 84889217184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 471
    • Id. at 471.
  • 78
    • 84889211294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 491 (Powell, J., dissenting)
    • Id. at 491 (Powell, J., dissenting).
  • 79
    • 84889211399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 80 See id. at 462
    • 80 See id. at 462.
  • 80
    • 84889187710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • W. at 471
    • W. at 471.
  • 81
    • 84889177035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 474-75
    • See id. at 474-75.
  • 82
    • 84889198163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 55 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 55 and accompanying text.
  • 83
    • 84889191073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Seattle Sch. Dist., 458 U.S. at 474
    • See Seattle Sch. Dist., 458 U.S. at 474.
  • 84
    • 84889221019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., United States Dep't of Agric. v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528 (1973)
    • See, e.g., United States Dep't of Agric. v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528 (1973).
  • 85
    • 84889188434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Palmore v. Sidoti, 466 U.S. 429, 433 (1984) (holding that the reality and effect of private racial biases are impermissible considerations under the Equal Protection Clause for divesting a mother of custody of her infant child because of her remarriage to a person of a different race).
  • 86
    • 84889209760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SUNSTEIN, supra note 41, at 26
    • SUNSTEIN, supra note 41, at 26.
  • 87
    • 84889194553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 25. Professor Sunstein argues that many clauses of the Constitution "appear to be united by a concern with a single underlying evil: the distribution of resources or opportunities to one group rather than to another solely on the ground that those favored here have exercised the raw political power to obtain what they want. I will call this underlying evil - a violation of the impartiality requirement - a naked preference." Id.
  • 88
    • 84889170043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 452 (1985) (Stevens, J., concurring); see also id. at 450 (using the term "irrational prejudice")
    • City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 452 (1985) (Stevens, J., concurring); see also id. at 450 (using the term "irrational prejudice").
  • 89
    • 84889179983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 413 U.S. 528 (striking down a statutory provision directed at excluding "hippies" from participating in the food stamp program)
    • 413 U.S. 528 (striking down a statutory provision directed at excluding "hippies" from participating in the food stamp program).
  • 90
    • 84889205937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 534
    • Id. at 534.
  • 91
    • 84889229290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 534-35 (citations omitted)
    • Id. at 534-35 (citations omitted).
  • 92
    • 84889220700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 533-34
    • See id. at 533-34.
  • 93
    • 84889223184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 537
    • See id. at 537.
  • 94
    • 84889185025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The plaintiffs included, for instance, a 56-year-old diabetic who was living with a woman and her children, sharing with them common living expenses and receiving care from the woman for her diabetes, and a mother of a hearing-impaired girl who was sharing an apartment with another woman in order to have the means for her daughter to go to a school for the deaf. See id. at 531-32.
  • 95
    • 84889197547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 631 (1996) (holding unconstitutional a state constitutional amendment repealing and prohibiting local antidiscrimination ordinances protecting homosexuals).
  • 96
    • 84889184646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. ("The Fourteenth Amendment's promise that no person shall be denied the equal protection of the laws must coexist with the practical necessity that most legislation classifies for one purpose or another, with resulting disadvantage to various groups or persons.").
  • 97
    • 84889230532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The Romer dissent points to exactly this feature of the anti-animus norm when criticizing it. See id. at 644 (Scalia, J., dissenting) ("Of course it is our moral heritage that one should not hate any human being or class of human beings. But I had thought that one could consider certain conduct reprehensible - murder, for example, or polygamy, or cruelty to animals - and could exhibit even 'animus' toward such conduct."). See infra notes 105-107 and accompanying text.
  • 98
    • 84889212606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The impartiality principle's prohibition against animus in decision making is, in another respect, a counterpoint to the value of individual moral entitlement associated with the conventional neutrality principle. The individual moral entitlement value condemns the use of stereotyped notions of individual merit based on group status, insisting on decision making that instead respects individual ability and dignity. Similarly, the impartiality principle attacks a like failure to attend to individuals in their own right; to give them and their interests fair and equal consideration compared with members of other groups. Both norms police procedural failures to give individuals their due respect.
  • 99
    • 84889182966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 218 n. 14 (1982). In the following sentence, the Court also connects the anti-animus norm to the moral entitlement value of treating people with due respect: "Legislation predicated on such prejudice is easily recognized as incompatible with the constitutional understanding that each person is to be judged individually and is entitled to equal justice under the law." Id.
  • 100
    • 84889181235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 101 Romer, 517 U.S. at 632
    • 101 Romer, 517 U.S. at 632.
  • 101
    • 84889231885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The consistency principle in these cases is developed supra Part II
    • The consistency principle in these cases is developed supra Part II.
  • 103
    • 84889194360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Romer, 517 U.S. at 633; see also Plyler, 457 U.S. at 227 ("Of course, a concern for the preservation of resources standing alone can hardly justify the classification used in allocating those resources. The state must do more than justify its classification with a concise expression of an intention to discriminate." (citations omitted)).
  • 104
    • 84889182954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 517 U.S. at 644 (Scalia, J., dissenting)
    • See 517 U.S. at 644 (Scalia, J., dissenting).
  • 105
    • 84889210182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (citing Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986))
    • See id. (citing Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986)).
  • 106
    • 84889216300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 641
    • Id. at 641.
  • 107
    • 84889176772 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Amendment 2 is "a status-based enactment divorced from any factual context from which we could discern a relationship to legitimate state interests; it is a classification of persons undertaken for its own sake, something that the Equal Protection Clause does not permit." Id. at 635 (emphasis added). 101 Id. at 632.
  • 108
    • 84889182141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 635
    • Id. at 635.
  • 109
    • 0043117639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Attainder and Amendment 2: Romer's Rightness
    • Cf. Akhil Reed Amar, Attainder and Amendment 2: Romer's Rightness, 95 MICH. L. REV. 203 (1996) (reasoning that the Attainder Clause prohibits state and federal legisla-tion from naming or singling out a class of persons for distinctive treatment).
    • (1996) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 203
    • Amar, A.R.1
  • 110
    • 84889178272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 90-95 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 90-95 and accompanying text.
  • 111
    • 84889187418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See United States Dep't of Agric. v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 537-38, 546 (1973)
    • See United States Dep't of Agric. v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 537-38, 546 (1973).
  • 112
    • 84889178621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 537-38 (citation omitted)
    • Id. at 537-38 (citation omitted).
  • 113
    • 84889211757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 538
    • Id. at 538.
  • 114
    • 84889218299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 546 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting)
    • Id. at 546 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting).
  • 115
    • 84889183841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See also Philips v. Perry, 106 F.3d 1420, 1429 (9th Cir. 1997) (upholding the Navy's "don't ask/don't tell" policy regarding homosexuality as rationally furthering the government's legitimate interest in "unit cohesion"). Judge Fletcher, in dissent, engaged in similar critical examination of the ambiguity hiding in the concept of "unit cohesion." After considering various alternative ways in which disclosure of homosexuality could be related to "cohesion," Judge Fletcher ultimately concluded that the term merely masked "the negative reactions of service members opposed to homosexuality." Id. at 1435 (Fletcher, J., dissenting). She reasoned: This is evident from the structure of the new prohibitions. If a service member keeps his homosexual orientation secret, then he is allowed to remain in the military. However, if a service member acknowledges that he is gay, then he is a threat to "unit cohesion" and must be discharged. The only material difference in these two situations is that information regarding the service member's homosexuality has been communicated to other service members, who might react negatively to the information and threaten unit cohesion. Id. (footnote omitted). Accommodation of this animus, however, could not, after Romer, be considered a legitimate governmental interest: "Disapproval of homosexuality on the part of heterosexual service members is an impermissible reason for discriminating against gay service members, [citing Romer] Otherwise, discrimination against an unpopular class could always be justified by reference to the moral disapproval of the majority." Id. at 1436.
  • 116
    • 84889181358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., Inc., 473 U.S. 432 (1985)
    • City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., Inc., 473 U.S. 432 (1985).
  • 117
    • 84889191842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • W. at 447
    • W. at 447.
  • 118
    • 84889178996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 448 (emphasis added)
    • Id. at 448 (emphasis added).
  • 119
    • 84889189185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 458 (Marshall, J., concurring)
    • Id. at 458 (Marshall, J., concurring).
  • 120
    • 84889207794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 448-50
    • See id. at 448-50.
  • 121
    • 84889199008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "[U]nder the traditional and most minimal version of the rational-basis test, 'reform may take one step at a time, addressing itself to the phase of the problem which seems most acute to the legislative mind."' Id. at 458 (Marshall, J., concurring) (quoting Williamson v. Lee Optical, Inc., 348 U.S. 483, 489 (1955)).
  • 122
    • 84889195166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 452 (Stevens, J., concurring)
    • Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 452 (Stevens, J., concurring).
  • 123
    • 84889180259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By "structural justice" I mean a principle that evaluates the justice of laws and social institutions according to the pattern of outcomes they produce for salient social groups, taking as the yardstick a norm of rough equality across groups in terms of things such as opportunities and resources, social rewards, power, and status. What matters is how the effects of the laws are felt by members of different groups; it is insufficient from the perspective of structural justice merely to say that the laws operated fairly on individuals in a procedural sense.
  • 124
    • 84889211283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Cal. Const, art. 1 § 31; Coalition for Econ. Equity v. Wilson, 110 F.3d 1431, 1434 (9th Cir.), op. amended and superseded on denial of reh'g, 122 F.3d 692 (9th Cir. 1997).
  • 125
    • 84889208576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1439
    • See id. at 1439.
  • 126
    • 84889185758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1435 (discussing the district court's view of Proposition 209)
    • Id. at 1435 (discussing the district court's view of Proposition 209).
  • 127
    • 84889231503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 8 (1967) ("[A]ssum[ing] the validity of [the State's] equal application theory . . . the question becomes whether there was any rational basis for a State to treat interracial marriages differently from other marriages.").
  • 128
    • 84889191735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Sections III.A-B
    • See infra Sections III.A-B.
  • 129
    • 84889231404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Coalition for Econ. Equity v. Wilson, 946 F. Supp. 1480, 1498, 1505 (N.D. Cal. 1996), rev'd, 110 F.3d 1431, 1434 (9th Cir.), op. amended and superseded on denial of reh'g, 122 F.3d 692 (9th Cir. 1997).
  • 130
    • 84889220970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. at 1504 ("[I]f an 'initiative removes the authority to address a racial problem - and only a racial problem - from the existing decision making body, in such a way as to burden minority interests,' it must be examined for equal protection purposes as if it were a racial classification." (quoting Washington v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 458 U.S. 457, 458(1982))).
  • 131
    • 84889220364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Loving, 388 U.S. at 11-12 & n.11
    • See Loving, 388 U.S. at 11-12 & n.11.
  • 132
    • 84889184913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coalition for Econ. Equity, 110 F.3d at 1434 (quoting the proponents' argument in the ballot pamphlet)
    • Coalition for Econ. Equity, 110 F.3d at 1434 (quoting the proponents' argument in the ballot pamphlet).
  • 133
    • 84889177589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1445 n.17
    • See id. at 1445 n.17.
  • 134
    • 84889200732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is presumably the implication that the district court meant to be drawn. See Coalition for Econ. Equity, 946 F. Supp. at 1505.
  • 135
    • 84889231466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 141 F.3d 344 (D.C. Cir.), reh'g en banc denied, 154 F.3d 487 (D.C. Cir. 1998)
    • 141 F.3d 344 (D.C. Cir.), reh'g en banc denied, 154 F.3d 487 (D.C. Cir. 1998).
  • 136
    • 84889203699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 125 F.3d 702 (9th Cir. 1997), reh'g en banc denied, 138 F.3d 1270 (9th Cir. 1998)
    • 125 F.3d 702 (9th Cir. 1997), reh'g en banc denied, 138 F.3d 1270 (9th Cir. 1998).
  • 137
    • 84889190974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The regulations also prohibited discrimination based on "color, religion, national origin, or sex," 141 F.3d at 346 (citing 47 C.F.R. § 73.2080(a) (1997)), although these other provisions were not specifically at issue in this part of the case. See id. at 351 n.9.
  • 138
    • 84889199729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The court described the requirements as: (1) disseminating the equal opportunity program to job applicants and employees; (2) using minority and women-specific recruiting sources; (3) evaluating the station's employment profile and job turnover against the availability of minorities and women in its recruitment area; (4) offering promotions to minorities and women in a nondiscriminatory fashion; and (5) analyzing its efforts to recruit, hire, and promote minorities and women. Id. at 346 (citing 47 C.F.R. § 73.2080(c) (1997)).
  • 139
    • 84889181792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Monterey Mechanical, 125 F.3d at 709 (citing CAL. PUB. CONT. CODE § 10115.2(a), (b) (West 1998)). If the contractors had actually hired the targeted numbers of minority business subcontractors and suppliers, then they would not have had to document their outreach efforts. See id. at 704.
  • 140
    • 84889171841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Lutheran Church, 141 F.3d at 352-53; Monterey Mechanical, 125 F.3d at 709. If the general contractor was owned by a woman, minority or disabled veteran, the share of the work that it kept for itself was counted against the target. See id. at 704. The court, however, applied the neutral classifications principle so stringently that it would apparently have stricken the statute even if it weighed equally heavily on white male and on minority general contractors. See id. at 712.
  • 141
    • 84889199683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 515 U.S. 200 (1995) (holding that all racial classifications - benign or not - by governmental actors must be analyzed under strict scrutiny).
  • 142
    • 84889194764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Lutheran Church, 141 F.3d at 351 (emphasis added). Note that in light of the court's later arguments that the FCC's review policy inevitably leads to racial preferences in hiring, this claim is really disingenuous. Judge Silberman writes: [W]e do not think it matters whether a government hiring program imposes hard quotas, soft quotas, or goals. Any one of these techniques induces an employer to hire with an eye toward meeting the numerical target. As such, they can and surely will result in individuals being granted a preference because of their race. Id. at 354. But even a policy requiring only nondiscrimination will likely be policed by special attention to stations that have suspiciously disproportionate minority employment. For that matter, merely admitting evidence of racial disproportion in court to help establish a case of racial discrimination would be unconstitutional under Judge Silberman's reasoning, on the ground that it leads in practice to employment quotas.
  • 143
    • 84889199857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Monterey Mechanical, 125 F.3d at 711
    • Monterey Mechanical, 125 F.3d at 711.
  • 144
    • 84889207995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Monterey Mechanical Co. v. Wilson, 138 F.3d 1270, 1275 (9th Cir. 1998) (Reinhardt, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc) ("It goes without saying that the statute in no way limits the giving of notice to others. The provision in question is designed to assure only that, when notices are given, minorities and women will not be excluded.").
  • 145
    • 84889204738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, recruitment budgets are not unlimited, so at the margin some tradeoff occurs. But the basic point is that information is a nondepletable good that can be shared across many users, which distinguishes it from the allocation of jobs.
  • 146
    • 84889209632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is true except to the extent that the FCC relies on the recruitment requirement in order to further the alternative goal of diversity in broadcasting, thereby attributing special racial viewpoints to different employees. To the extent that these regulations are meant to further merely nondiscrimination and workplace diversity goals, however, they involve no impermissible group-based attribution.
  • 147
    • 84889217908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 29-34
    • See supra text accompanying notes 29-34.
  • 148
    • 84889190204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Lutheran Church-Missouri Synod v. FCC, 141 F.3d 344, 351-52 (D.C. Cir. 1998). The court's analysis of this issue is cut short, however, by its ultimate rejection of the government's asserted interest in preventing employment discrimination, apparently because it was offered by the Department of Justice rather than the FCC. See id. at 354. Instead, it considers the main purpose of the regulations to be the promotion of "diversity in programming," see id. at 350, which makes the policy seem not only to rest on potentially inappropriate racial generalizations, but indeed to verge on irrationality.
  • 149
    • 84889189360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that the discrimination problem with the intent behind Proposition 209 was not that it sought to achieve (formal) racial equality - which in itself is a legitimate governmental goal - but that the means used and the inconsistencies involved cast doubt on the bona fides of this intention and suggested something more animus-related.
  • 150
    • 84889207946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Brest, supra note 23
    • See, e.g., Brest, supra note 23; see generally John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical, 14 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 223 (1985) (arguing that the liberal conception of distributive justice is grounded in procedural fairness to individuals in the political system). But see Fiss, supra note 48, at 173-77 (arguing that structural justice and outcomes-equality also have important roots in the popular conception of equality).
  • 151
    • 84935547375 scopus 로고
    • Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical
    • See, e.g., Brest, supra note 23; see generally John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical, 14 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 223 (1985) (arguing that the liberal conception of distributive justice is grounded in procedural fairness to individuals in the political system). But see Fiss, supra note 48, at 173-77 (arguing that structural justice and outcomes-equality also have important roots in the popular conception of equality).
    • (1985) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.14 , pp. 223
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 152
    • 84889191186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Fiss, supra note 48, at 173-77 (arguing that structural justice and outcomes-equality also have important roots in the popular conception of equality)
    • See, e.g., Brest, supra note 23; see generally John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical, 14 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 223 (1985) (arguing that the liberal conception of distributive justice is grounded in procedural fairness to individuals in the political system). But see Fiss, supra note 48, at 173-77 (arguing that structural justice and outcomes-equality also have important roots in the popular conception of equality).
  • 153
    • 0000356239 scopus 로고
    • The Desire for Justice and Reactions to Victims
    • Jacqueline R. Macaulay & Leonard Berkowitz eds.
    • This is especially important in light of psychological research into the prevalence of the "just world hypothesis" and the "fundamental attribution error," by which people generally exhibit a bias toward overattributing good and bad outcomes to individuals' specific traits, supporting the conclusion that these outcomes are "deserved." These cognitive errors entrench an unjust status quo by masking the extent to which its beneficiaries and losers are undeserving of their lots. See Melvin J. Lerner, The Desire for Justice and Reactions to Victims, in ALTRUISM AND HELPING BEHAVIOR 205 (Jacqueline R. Macaulay & Leonard Berkowitz eds., 1970); Kelly G. Shaver, Defensive Attribution: Effects of Severity and Relevance on the Responsibility Assigned for an Accident, 14 J. PERSONALITY & Soc. PSYCHOL. 101 (1970).
    • (1970) Altruism and Helping Behavior , pp. 205
    • Lerner, M.J.1
  • 154
    • 0001065155 scopus 로고
    • Defensive Attribution: Effects of Severity and Relevance on the Responsibility Assigned for an Accident
    • This is especially important in light of psychological research into the prevalence of the "just world hypothesis" and the "fundamental attribution error," by which people generally exhibit a bias toward overattributing good and bad outcomes to individuals' specific traits, supporting the conclusion that these outcomes are "deserved." These cognitive errors entrench an unjust status quo by masking the extent to which its beneficiaries and losers are undeserving of their lots. See Melvin J. Lerner, The Desire for Justice and Reactions to Victims, in ALTRUISM AND HELPING BEHAVIOR 205 (Jacqueline R. Macaulay & Leonard Berkowitz eds., 1970); Kelly G. Shaver, Defensive Attribution: Effects of Severity and Relevance on the Responsibility Assigned for an Accident, 14 J. PERSONALITY & Soc. PSYCHOL. 101 (1970).
    • (1970) J. Personality & Soc. Psychol. , vol.14 , pp. 101
    • Shaver, K.G.1
  • 155
    • 84889177210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fiss, supra note 48, at 175
    • Fiss, supra note 48, at 175.
  • 156
    • 84889228416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 157
    • 84889185541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214 (1944), for example, this approach to evaluating the government's means and ends for discrimination was suggested by Justice Murphy. His dissenting opinion noted that "[s]imilar disloyal activities have been engaged in by many persons of German, Italian, and even more pioneer stock in our country" - while only those of Japanese descent were relocated. Id. at 240 (Murphy, J., dissenting). This comparison places both the absolute necessity and paramount importance of the relocation policy in doubt: If the government's interest in preventing disloyal activities were sufficiently important, then the burden of forced relocation would have been imposed on a broader segment of the American public, instead of just on an (unpopular) minority group. Further, the fact that the government chose to deal with the threat posed by disloyal members from other ethnic groups in alternative ways implied that forced relocation was not, in fact, the only feasible option.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.