메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 19, Issue 4, 1997, Pages 375-389

Why ecology cannot be all things to all people: The "adaptive radiation" of scientific concepts

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 7044229974     PISSN: 01634275     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/enviroethics19971944     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (7)

References (45)
  • 2
    • 7044255535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Abram, The Spell of the Sensuous: Perception and Language in a More-than-Human World(New York: Pantheon, 1996). See especially the chapter, "Philosophy on the Way to Ecology," pp. 31-72.
    • Philosophy on the Way to Ecology , pp. 31-72
  • 4
    • 0000165775 scopus 로고
    • The Metaphysical Implications of Ecology
    • The speculative project is most prominent in the various forms of ecotheology and deep ecology (including, perhaps, the work of Abram), but can also be found in ecofeminism, social ecology, and environmental ethics. Regarding the last of these, see J. Baird Callicott, "The Metaphysical Implications of Ecology," Environmental Ethics 8 (1986): 301-16; this article touched off a debate regarding the validity and pertinence of "metaphysical ecology" for environmental ethics. It should be noted that there are environmental philosophers who explicitly reject the speculative project. See, for example, Bryan G. Norton, "Why I am Not a Nonanthropocentrist: Callicott and the Failure of Monistic Inherentism," Environmental Ethics 17 (1995): 341-358; it is one of the latest salvos in the debate which followed from Callicott's paper above.
    • (1986) Environmental Ethics , vol.8 , pp. 301-316
    • Callicott, J.B.1
  • 5
    • 0001459610 scopus 로고
    • Why I am Not a Nonanthropocentrist: Callicott and the Failure of Monistic Inherentism
    • The speculative project is most prominent in the various forms of ecotheology and deep ecology (including, perhaps, the work of Abram), but can also be found in ecofeminism, social ecology, and environmental ethics. Regarding the last of these, see J. Baird Callicott, "The Metaphysical Implications of Ecology," Environmental Ethics 8 (1986): 301-16; this article touched off a debate regarding the validity and pertinence of "metaphysical ecology" for environmental ethics. It should be noted that there are environmental philosophers who explicitly reject the speculative project. See, for example, Bryan G. Norton, "Why I am Not a Nonanthropocentrist: Callicott and the Failure of Monistic Inherentism," Environmental Ethics 17 (1995): 341-358; it is one of the latest salvos in the debate which followed from Callicott's paper above.
    • (1995) Environmental Ethics , vol.17 , pp. 341-358
    • Norton, B.G.1
  • 6
    • 7044244960 scopus 로고
    • Merleau-Ponty and the Voice of the Earth
    • See Abram, "Merleau-Ponty and the Voice of the Earth," Environmental Ethics 10 (1988): 106.
    • (1988) Environmental Ethics , vol.10 , pp. 106
    • Abram1
  • 7
    • 0003441579 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Donald Worster and Anna Bramwell both offer histories of "ecological ideas" along these lines. In Nature's Economy: A History of Ecological Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), Worster does distinguish between two traditions in "ecology," the arcadian and the imperial, but neither of them corresponds unambiguously or exclusively to the science called ecology; he seems to regard them as competing paradigms or ideologies of equal weight and merit. Likewise, in her otherwise excellent Ecology in the 20th Century: A History (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), Bramwell recognizes the rootedness of ecologism in the science of ecology, but gives little or no attention to the later developments of the science. Philosophical examples of this reading of the ecology/ecologism connection are legion. See, for example: Carolyn Merchant, Radical Ecology: The Search for a Livable World (New York: Routledge, 1992), p. 814.
    • (1977) Nature's Economy: A History of Ecological Ideas
    • Worster, D.1    Bramwell, A.2
  • 8
    • 0004114971 scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press
    • Donald Worster and Anna Bramwell both offer histories of "ecological ideas" along these lines. In Nature's Economy: A History of Ecological Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), Worster does distinguish between two traditions in "ecology," the arcadian and the imperial, but neither of them corresponds unambiguously or exclusively to the science called ecology; he seems to regard them as competing paradigms or ideologies of equal weight and merit. Likewise, in her otherwise excellent Ecology in the 20th Century: A History (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), Bramwell recognizes the rootedness of ecologism in the science of ecology, but gives little or no attention to the later developments of the science. Philosophical examples of this reading of the ecology/ecologism connection are legion. See, for example: Carolyn Merchant, Radical Ecology: The Search for a Livable World (New York: Routledge, 1992), p. 814.
    • (1989) Ecology in the 20th Century: A History
  • 9
    • 0003398576 scopus 로고
    • New York: Routledge
    • Donald Worster and Anna Bramwell both offer histories of "ecological ideas" along these lines. In Nature's Economy: A History of Ecological Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), Worster does distinguish between two traditions in "ecology," the arcadian and the imperial, but neither of them corresponds unambiguously or exclusively to the science called ecology; he seems to regard them as competing paradigms or ideologies of equal weight and merit. Likewise, in her otherwise excellent Ecology in the 20th Century: A History (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), Bramwell recognizes the rootedness of ecologism in the science of ecology, but gives little or no attention to the later developments of the science. Philosophical examples of this reading of the ecology/ecologism connection are legion. See, for example: Carolyn Merchant, Radical Ecology: The Search for a Livable World (New York: Routledge, 1992), p. 814.
    • (1992) Radical Ecology: The Search for a Livable World , pp. 814
    • Merchant, C.1
  • 10
    • 0001967874 scopus 로고
    • Santa Fe: Bear and Company
    • This version has its strongest telling in the "universe story" tradition, and is even extended to include evolutionary theory and physics. See Brian Swimme, The Universe is a Green Dragon: A Cosmic Creation Story (Santa Fe: Bear and Company, 1984), and Thomas Berry, The Dream of the Earth (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1988).
    • (1984) The Universe Is a Green Dragon: A Cosmic Creation Story
    • Swimme, B.1
  • 11
    • 0004111141 scopus 로고
    • San Francisco: Sierra Club Books
    • This version has its strongest telling in the "universe story" tradition, and is even extended to include evolutionary theory and physics. See Brian Swimme, The Universe is a Green Dragon: A Cosmic Creation Story (Santa Fe: Bear and Company, 1984), and Thomas Berry, The Dream of the Earth (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1988).
    • (1988) The Dream of the Earth
    • Berry, T.1
  • 12
    • 84951419547 scopus 로고
    • The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary
    • Concerning the alleged degeneracy of ecology as a science, see, for example, Arne Naess, "The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary," Inquiry 16 (1973): 99; Neil Evernden, The Natural Alien: Humankind and Environment (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1985), pp. 21, 23, and esp. 76.
    • (1973) Inquiry , vol.16 , pp. 99
    • Naess, A.1
  • 13
    • 84951419547 scopus 로고
    • Toronto: University of Toronto Press, esp. 76
    • Concerning the alleged degeneracy of ecology as a science, see, for example, Arne Naess, "The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary," Inquiry 16 (1973): 99; Neil Evernden, The Natural Alien: Humankind and Environment (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1985), pp. 21, 23, and esp. 76.
    • (1985) The Natural Alien: Humankind and Environment , pp. 21
    • Evernden, N.1
  • 14
    • 84934856984 scopus 로고
    • Fact and Value in Ecological Science
    • This clarification serves to distinguish my project from others which might seem similar at first glance. For example, in "Fact and Value in Ecological Science," Environmental Ethics 7 (1985): 99-116, Mark Sagoff seems to be concerned primarily with dictating to ecologists the best way to practice their science, while I am more interested in the practices of environmental philosophers. K. S. Shrader-Frechette and E. D. McCoy, in Method in Ecology: Strategies for Conservation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), are likewise concerned with the proper way to do ecology, especially in relation to the solution of conservation and policy problems; the speculative concerns of environmental philosophers receive only a passing mention in the first chapter (p. 2).
    • (1985) Environmental Ethics , vol.7 , pp. 99-116
  • 15
    • 0003808102 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • This clarification serves to distinguish my project from others which might seem similar at first glance. For example, in "Fact and Value in Ecological Science," Environmental Ethics 7 (1985): 99-116, Mark Sagoff seems to be concerned primarily with dictating to ecologists the best way to practice their science, while I am more interested in the practices of environmental philosophers. K. S. Shrader-Frechette and E. D. McCoy, in Method in Ecology: Strategies for Conservation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), are likewise concerned with the proper way to do ecology, especially in relation to the solution of conservation and policy problems; the speculative concerns of environmental philosophers receive only a passing mention in the first chapter (p. 2).
    • (1993) Method in Ecology: Strategies for Conservation
    • Shrader-Frechette, K.S.1    McCoy, E.D.2
  • 16
    • 0004090203 scopus 로고
    • Paris: J. Vrin
    • Inspirations for this model come from a number of sources, not least among which are Gaston Bachelard, La formation de l'esprit scientifique (Paris: J. Vrin, 1993); Georges Canguilhem, Idéologie et rationalité dans l'histoire des sciences de la vie (Paris: J. Vrin, 1993); and the debate concerning Kuhn's theory of "paradigm shifts" recorded in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970). It is beyond the scope of this paper to address the exceedingly complex problem of how "testing against experience" is to be carried out - or even whether it is possible. While some understanding of the relationship of theory to experience is needed for any philosophy of science, it should be understood that the model I am proposing for the development of scientific concepts need not presuppose any particular version of confirmation or falsification. In particular, I insist that I should not be construed as defending any sort of naive empiricism against the speculation of some environmental thinkers.
    • (1993) La Formation de l'Esprit Scientifique
    • Bachelard, G.1
  • 17
    • 0004300964 scopus 로고
    • Paris: J. Vrin
    • Inspirations for this model come from a number of sources, not least among which are Gaston Bachelard, La formation de l'esprit scientifique (Paris: J. Vrin, 1993); Georges Canguilhem, Idéologie et rationalité dans l'histoire des sciences de la vie (Paris: J. Vrin, 1993); and the debate concerning Kuhn's theory of "paradigm shifts" recorded in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970). It is beyond the scope of this paper to address the exceedingly complex problem of how "testing against experience" is to be carried out - or even whether it is possible. While some understanding of the relationship of theory to experience is needed for any philosophy of science, it should be understood that the model I am proposing for the development of scientific concepts need not presuppose any particular version of confirmation or falsification. In particular, I insist that I should not be construed as defending any sort of naive empiricism against the speculation of some environmental thinkers.
    • (1993) Idéologie et Rationalité dans l'Histoire des Sciences de la Vie
    • Canguilhem, G.1
  • 18
    • 0003454816 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Inspirations for this model come from a number of sources, not least among which are Gaston Bachelard, La formation de l'esprit scientifique (Paris: J. Vrin, 1993); Georges Canguilhem, Idéologie et rationalité dans l'histoire des sciences de la vie (Paris: J. Vrin, 1993); and the debate concerning Kuhn's theory of "paradigm shifts" recorded in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970). It is beyond the scope of this paper to address the exceedingly complex problem of how "testing against experience" is to be carried out - or even whether it is possible. While some understanding of the relationship of theory to experience is needed for any philosophy of science, it should be understood that the model I am proposing for the development of scientific concepts need not presuppose any particular version of confirmation or falsification. In particular, I insist that I should not be construed as defending any sort of naive empiricism against the speculation of some environmental thinkers.
    • (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge
    • Lakatos, I.1    Musgrave, A.2
  • 19
    • 7044278449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This analogy is limited, however, in that concepts which are taken from one medium to another can remain viable, but only to the extent that they can be adapted to fit the new context. This involves the development of a new set of meanings which diverge from the old.
  • 20
    • 7044257653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regarding confusions over the concepts "community" and "stability" in ecology, see, Shrader-Frechette and McCoy, Method, pp. 11-67. For a broader discussion of metaphors in global ecology, see Daniel B. Botkin, Discordant Harmonies: A New Ecology for the Twenty-First Century (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990).
    • Method , pp. 11-67
    • Shrader-Frechette1    McCoy2
  • 21
    • 0003949874 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Regarding confusions over the concepts "community" and "stability" in ecology, see, Shrader-Frechette and McCoy, Method, pp. 11-67. For a broader discussion of metaphors in global ecology, see Daniel B. Botkin, Discordant Harmonies: A New Ecology for the Twenty-First Century (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990).
    • (1990) Discordant Harmonies: A New Ecology for the Twenty-First Century
    • Botkin, D.B.1
  • 23
    • 7044275977 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Bordas, original translation
    • François Dagognet, Le vivant (Paris: Bordas, 1988), p. 99 (original translation).
    • (1988) Le Vivant , pp. 99
    • Dagognet, F.1
  • 24
    • 0038089860 scopus 로고
    • Paris: PUF
    • Pascal Acot writes of the "secularization" of Linnaeus' concept of "the economy of nature" as a precondition for the emergence of ecology as a science. While Linnaeus offered a general cosmology rooted in natural theology, the first ecologists (e.g., Forbes) studied local systems (e.g., lakes) in the terms offered them by physiology. Histoire de l'écologie (Paris: PUF, 1988), pp. 14-16.
    • (1988) Histoire de l'Écologie , pp. 14-16
    • Acot, P.1
  • 25
    • 0003647523 scopus 로고
    • Lincoln, Nebraska: University Publishing Company
    • Frederick Clements, Research Methods in Ecology (Lincoln, Nebraska: University Publishing Company, 1905), p. 199.
    • (1905) Research Methods in Ecology , pp. 199
    • Clements, F.1
  • 28
    • 0000853578 scopus 로고
    • The Use and Abuse of Vegetational Concepts and Terms
    • A. G. Tansley, "The Use and Abuse of Vegetational Concepts and Terms," Ecology 16 (1935): 285.
    • (1935) Ecology , vol.16 , pp. 285
    • Tansley, A.G.1
  • 29
    • 0001921913 scopus 로고
    • The Individualistic Concept of the Plant Association
    • H.A. Gleason, "The Individualistic Concept of the Plant Association," Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club 53 (1926): 8-9.
    • (1926) Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club , vol.53 , pp. 8-9
    • Gleason, H.A.1
  • 35
    • 0023499369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 144, and also Robert McIntosh, "Pluralism in Ecology," Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 18 (1987): 322.
    • Entangled Dank , pp. 144
  • 38
    • 0002611741 scopus 로고
    • The City: Suggestions for the Investigation of Human Behavior in the Urban Environment
    • Robert E. Park, Ernest W. Burgess, and Roderick D. McKenzie, Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Robert E. Park, "The City: Suggestions for the Investigation of Human Behavior in the Urban Environment," in Robert E. Park, Ernest W. Burgess, and Roderick D. McKenzie, The City (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1925), p. I.
    • (1925) The City
    • Park, R.E.1
  • 39
    • 0005486098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ecological Approach to the Study of Human Community
    • Park et al.
    • Roderick D. McKenzie, "The Ecological Approach to the Study of Human Community," in Park et al., The City, pp. 63-65.
    • The City , pp. 63-65
    • McKenzie, R.D.1
  • 40
    • 79956818494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also note on p. 63
    • Ibid., p. 68; see also note on p. 63.
    • The City , pp. 68
  • 43
  • 44
    • 7044267943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid, pp. 84-85. Abram goes on to argue that alphabetic writing is an important culprit in environmental degradation, in that it stultifies the power of language to evoke the underlying interrelatedness between the speaker and the surrounding world.
    • Spell , pp. 84-85
  • 45
    • 0004271507 scopus 로고
    • trans. Walter Kaufman New York: Vintage
    • Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufman (New York: Vintage, 1974), pp. 167-69.
    • (1974) The Gay Science , pp. 167-169
    • Nietzsche, F.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.