-
1
-
-
84868164246
-
-
Counter-reformers may well claim that perceptual experience is not capable of correctness either: it is not in the business of either truth or falsity, and so 'infallible' is a tendentious label. Whether this position is plausible is briefly discussed in §III.
-
Counter-reformers may well claim that perceptual experience is not capable of correctness either: it is not in the business of either truth or falsity, and so 'infallible' is a tendentious label. Whether this position is plausible is briefly discussed in §III
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
75949099262
-
-
Searle later argues (pp. 47-8) that the content of an experience is reflexive, concerning the experience itself
-
Searle later argues (pp. 47-8) that the content of an experience is reflexive, concerning the experience itself
-
-
-
-
6
-
-
79957111591
-
-
For some other statements of (CV), C. McGinn, Mental Content (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989), p. 58;
-
For some other statements of (CV), see C. McGinn, Mental Content (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989), p. 58
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
0001447287
-
The Intrinsic Quality of Experience
-
at p
-
G. Harman, 'The Intrinsic Quality of Experience', Philosophical Perspectives, 4 (1990), pp. 31-52, at p. 34
-
(1990)
Philosophical Perspectives
, vol.4
-
-
Harman, G.1
-
8
-
-
0001737759
-
Individualism and Perceptual Content
-
at p
-
M. Davies, 'Individualism and Perceptual Content', Mind, 100 (1991), pp. 461-84, at p. 462
-
(1991)
Mind
, vol.100
-
-
Davies, M.1
-
10
-
-
31144444655
-
Mind and Illusion
-
P. Ludlow, Y. Nagasawa and D. Stoljar eds, MIT Press, at p
-
F. Jackson, 'Mind and Illusion', in P. Ludlow, Y. Nagasawa and D. Stoljar (eds), There's Something about Mary (MIT Press, 2004), pp. 421-32, at p. 428
-
(2004)
There's Something about Mary
-
-
Jackson, F.1
-
11
-
-
79951932857
-
Do Visual Experiences Have Contents?
-
B. Nanay ed, Oxford UP, forthcoming
-
S. Siegel, 'Do Visual Experiences Have Contents?', in B. Nanay (ed.), Perceiving the World (Oxford UP, forthcoming)
-
Perceiving the World
-
-
Siegel, S.1
-
12
-
-
0000742372
-
Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind
-
at §§16-17, on 'experiences as containing propositional claims,
-
See also W. Sellars, 'Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind', Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1 (1956), pp. 253-329, at §§16-17, on 'experiences as containing propositional claims'
-
(1956)
Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science
, vol.1
, pp. 253-329
-
-
Sellars, W.1
-
13
-
-
84921616285
-
-
§II elaborates on A. Byrne and H. Logue, 'Either/Or', in A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge (Oxford UP, 2008), pp. 57-94, at pp. 82-3.
-
§II elaborates on A. Byrne and H. Logue, 'Either/Or', in A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge (Oxford UP, 2008), pp. 57-94, at pp. 82-3
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
85184678970
-
-
A. Byrne, 'Intentionalism Defended', Philosophical Review, no (2001), pp. 119-240, at p. 203;
-
A. Byrne, 'Intentionalism Defended', Philosophical Review, no (2001), pp. 119-240, at p. 203
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
60949512220
-
On Being Alienated
-
T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne eds, Oxford UP, at p
-
M.G.F. Martin, 'On Being Alienated', in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds), Perceptual Experience (Oxford UP, 2006), pp. 354-410, at p. 354
-
(2006)
Perceptual Experience
-
-
Martin, M.G.F.1
-
21
-
-
75949118909
-
-
Siegel, 'Which Properties Are Represented in Perception?', also in Perceptual Experience, pp. 481-503, at p. 484.
-
Siegel, 'Which Properties Are Represented in Perception?', also in Perceptual Experience, pp. 481-503, at p. 484
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
79957058785
-
-
Sometimes philosophers use 'event' extraordinarily broadly, so that if an object o is F at t it supposedly follows that there is an 'event' of o's being F occurring at t. Hence there is an 'event' of this pen's being straight, etc.; J. Bennett, Events and their Names (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988), p. 6. It is safe to say that almost none of the philosophers referred to above has such an elastic use in mind.
-
Sometimes philosophers use 'event' extraordinarily broadly, so that if an object o is F at t it supposedly follows that there is an 'event' of o's being F occurring at t. Hence there is an 'event' of this pen's being straight, etc.; cf. J. Bennett, Events and their Names (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988), p. 6. It is safe to say that almost none of the philosophers referred to above has such an elastic use in mind
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
75949099778
-
-
Lycan is quoting from, and disagreeing with, Dretske's paper 'How Do You Know You are Not a Zombie?' in the same
-
Lycan is quoting from, and disagreeing with, Dretske's paper 'How Do You Know You are Not a Zombie?' in the same volume
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
75949105379
-
-
On some views (e.g., Bennett, Events and their Names) events are property instances. Be that as it may, the point is simply that the existence of events (elections, weddings, etc.) is less controversial than the existence of property instances.
-
On some views (e.g., Bennett, Events and their Names) events are property instances. Be that as it may, the point is simply that the existence of events (elections, weddings, etc.) is less controversial than the existence of property instances
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
75949114870
-
-
As Hinton points out (Experiences, pt. I), this paraphrase is not perfect, since having the experience of doing such and such suggests some sort of awareness on the subject's part. If one somehow managed to swim the Bosphorus while fast asleep it would be at least odd to say one had the experience of swimming the Bosphorus.
-
As Hinton points out (Experiences, pt. I), this paraphrase is not perfect, since having the experience of doing such and such suggests some sort of awareness on the subject's part. If one somehow managed to swim the Bosphorus while fast asleep it would be at least odd to say one had the experience of swimming the Bosphorus
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
0742315497
-
also B. Farrell, 'Experience'
-
also B. Farrell, 'Experience', Mind, 59 (1950), pp. 170-98
-
(1950)
Mind
, vol.59
, pp. 170-198
-
-
-
32
-
-
0001121033
-
Contrast, for example, 'I deliberately chased ...'/'I was chasing ...' and 'I deliberately saw ...'/'I was seeing ...'. See Z. Vendler, 'Verbs and Times'
-
esp. pp. 155-6
-
Contrast, for example, 'I deliberately chased ...'/'I was chasing ...' and 'I deliberately saw ...'/'I was seeing ...'. See Z. Vendler, 'Verbs and Times', Philosophical Review, 66 (1957), pp. 143-60, esp. pp. 155-6
-
(1957)
Philosophical Review
, vol.66
, pp. 143-160
-
-
-
33
-
-
36448965830
-
The Silence of the Senses
-
at p
-
C. Travis, 'The Silence of the Senses', Mind, 113 (2004), pp. 57-94, at p. 57
-
(2004)
Mind
, vol.113
-
-
Travis, C.1
-
34
-
-
0001726721
-
The Refutation of Idealism
-
G.E. Moore, 'The Refutation of Idealism', Mind, 7 (1903), pp. 1-30
-
(1903)
Mind
, vol.7
, pp. 1-30
-
-
Moore, G.E.1
-
37
-
-
0004045957
-
-
in particular, Oxford UP
-
See, in particular, G. Evans, The Varieties of Reference (Oxford UP, 1982), pp. 227-31
-
(1982)
The Varieties of Reference
, pp. 227-231
-
-
Evans, G.1
-
39
-
-
75949084193
-
-
Tye only offers a paraphrase sufficient for the truth of 'I had n F-experiences today', not one which is necessary and sufficient. 'I had a single experience today that represented n F-things' would be false if I had a nap at lunchtime after fewer than n F-things had been represented, yet 'I had n F-experiences today' might well be true.
-
Tye only offers a paraphrase sufficient for the truth of 'I had n F-experiences today', not one which is necessary and sufficient. 'I had a single experience today that represented n F-things' would be false if I had a nap at lunchtime after fewer than n F-things had been represented, yet 'I had n F-experiences today' might well be true
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
75949097680
-
-
In vision science, visual illusions' include 'philosophical' hallucinations. The Hermann Grid illusion, for instance, is arguably an example: one 'sees' non-existent grey spots
-
In vision science, 'visual illusions' include 'philosophical' hallucinations. The Hermann Grid illusion, for instance, is arguably an example: one 'sees' non-existent grey spots
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
79957269929
-
-
Martin, 'On Being Alienated'.
-
See Martin, 'On Being Alienated'
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
79957278474
-
-
Further, one may that the lemon is yellow even if one does not the lemon .
-
Further, one may see that the lemon is yellow even if one does not see the lemon
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
33750460965
-
Memory Modulates Color Appearance
-
Largely encapsulated: if one believes that the lemon before one is white but cleverly illuminated by a yellow spotlight, it will still look yellow. But only largely: for instance, knowledge of the colours of lemons seems to have a slight effect on colour appearance.
-
Largely encapsulated: if one believes that the lemon before one is white but cleverly illuminated by a yellow spotlight, it will still look yellow. But only largely: for instance, knowledge of the colours of lemons seems to have a slight effect on colour appearance. See T. Hansen et al., 'Memory Modulates Color Appearance', Nature Neuroscience, 9 (2006), pp. 1367-8
-
(2006)
Nature Neuroscience
, vol.9
, pp. 1367-1368
-
-
Hansen, T.1
-
44
-
-
75949096892
-
-
M. Johnston, 'Postscript: Visual Experience', in A. Byrne and D. R. Hilbert (eds), Readings on Color, 1: The Philosophy of Color (MIT Press, 1997), pp. 172-6;
-
M. Johnston, 'Postscript: Visual Experience', in A. Byrne and D. R. Hilbert (eds), Readings on Color, Vol. 1: The Philosophy of Color (MIT Press, 1997), pp. 172-6
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
75949123339
-
-
R. Millikan, On Clear and Confused Ideas (Cambridge UP, 2000), p. 111. Johnston actually characterizes the view as identifying 'visual experience' and the 'sui generis propositional attitude'. But that stronger claim is not needed.
-
R. Millikan, On Clear and Confused Ideas (Cambridge UP, 2000), p. 111. Johnston actually characterizes the view as identifying 'visual experience' and the 'sui generis propositional attitude'. But that stronger claim is not needed
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
79957387138
-
-
They are also sometimes unconvincing. For instance, Searle (pp. 41-2) notes that 'sees that the F is G' is intensional, whereas 'sees the F' is extensional, and claims that the 'most obvious explanation of this distinction is that the that form reports the intentional content of the perception'. But of course that cannot be the explanation, because 'sees that the stock market has crashed' is also intensional, and the explanation can hardly have anything to do with the content of perception. In any case, although 'sees o' has a distinctively visual sense, 'sees that p' arguably does not.
-
They are also sometimes unconvincing. For instance, Searle (pp. 41-2) notes that 'sees that the F is G' is intensional, whereas 'sees the F' is extensional, and claims that the 'most obvious explanation of this distinction is that the "see that" form reports the intentional content of the perception'. But of course that cannot be the explanation, because 'sees that the stock market has crashed' is also intensional, and the explanation can hardly have anything to do with the content of perception. In any case, although 'sees o' has a distinctively visual sense, 'sees that p' arguably does not
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
60949495896
-
-
R. Price, 'Content Ascriptions and the Reversibility Constraint', Philosophical Perspectives, 19 (2005), pp. 353-74, at pp. 357-8.
-
Cf. R. Price, 'Content Ascriptions and the Reversibility Constraint', Philosophical Perspectives, 19 (2005), pp. 353-74, at pp. 357-8
-
-
-
-
50
-
-
79957030555
-
-
e.g., R. Stalnaker, Inquiry (MIT Press, 1984), ch. 1. In the course of explaining why the relevant sense of 'represent' has nothing to do with indication (pp. 58-9), Travis actually mentions one of the standard examples used to suggest the opposite, namely, tree rings.
-
See, e.g., R. Stalnaker, Inquiry (MIT Press, 1984), ch. 1. In the course of explaining why the relevant sense of 'represent' has nothing to do with indication (pp. 58-9), Travis actually mentions one of the standard examples used to suggest the opposite, namely, tree rings
-
-
-
-
52
-
-
79957078719
-
-
Perception, pp. 37-48. There is a comparative construction that with only mild straining can be read as equivalent to the phenomenal/non-comparative use of 'looks red', namely, 'looks like a stereotypically red object'. But this is not the hoped-for analysis, since in order to get the equivalence the intended interpretation of 'stereotypically red object' has to be explained in terms of the phenomenal/non-comparative use: a stereotypically red object is one that would look red. (Merely being red is insufficient.) This point applies equally to the examples of 'looks centurian', 'looks old', and the like, discussed below.
-
See Perception, pp. 37-48. There is a comparative construction that with only mild straining can be read as equivalent to the phenomenal/non-comparative use of 'looks red', namely, 'looks like a stereotypically red object'. But this is not the hoped-for analysis, since in order to get the equivalence the intended interpretation of 'stereotypically red object' has to be explained in terms of the phenomenal/non-comparative use: a stereotypically red object is one that would look red. (Merely being red is insufficient.) This point applies equally to the examples of 'looks centurian', 'looks old', and the like, discussed below
-
-
-
-
53
-
-
75949113481
-
-
Jackson's example (Perception, p. 33) is 'The dog looks dangerous'.
-
Jackson's example (Perception, p. 33) is 'The dog looks dangerous'
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
0036854720
-
-
In fact, naked mole rats are exceptionally long-lived: P.W. Sherman and J.U.M. Jarvis, Extraordinary Life Spans of Naked Mole-Rats (Heterocephalus Glaber, Journal of Zoology, 258 2002, pp. 307-11
-
In fact, naked mole rats are exceptionally long-lived: see P.W. Sherman and J.U.M. Jarvis, 'Extraordinary Life Spans of Naked Mole-Rats (Heterocephalus Glaber)', Journal of Zoology, 258 (2002), pp. 307-11
-
-
-
-
55
-
-
61149416968
-
On the Ways Things Appear
-
For a related view, Gendler and Hawthorne eds
-
For a related view, see S. Shoemaker, 'On the Ways Things Appear', in Gendler and Hawthorne (eds), Perceptual Experience, pp. 461-80
-
Perceptual Experience
, pp. 461-480
-
-
Shoemaker, S.1
-
57
-
-
79957127236
-
-
fn. 5
-
See also Travis, 'The Silence', p. 64, fn. 5
-
The Silence
, pp. 64
-
-
Travis1
-
59
-
-
79957434826
-
-
This also poses a problem for the similar account of illusion in Brewer, Perception and Content, Another quite different counter-reformation account of illusion is that developed in the work of M.G.F. Martin e.g, On Being Alienated, Martin's constitutive account of the illusion just mentioned in the text is roughly this: one sees the grey surface, but cannot tell by introspection alone that one is not veridically perceiving a surface tinged with green. For references to the main discussions of Martin's view, Byrne and Logue, Either/Or, p. 74, fn. 31
-
This also poses a problem for the similar account of illusion in Brewer, 'Perception and Content'. Another quite different counter-reformation account of illusion is that developed in the work of M.G.F. Martin (e.g., 'On Being Alienated'). Martin's constitutive account of the illusion just mentioned in the text is roughly this: one sees the grey surface, but cannot tell by introspection alone that one is not veridically perceiving a surface tinged with green. For references to the main discussions of Martin's view, see Byrne and Logue, 'Either/Or', p. 74, fn. 31
-
-
-
-
60
-
-
53249093956
-
The Theory of Appearing Defended
-
87 1,7, pp
-
H. Langsam, 'The Theory of Appearing Defended', Philosophical Studies, 87 (1,7), pp. 33-59
-
Philosophical Studies
, pp. 33-59
-
-
Langsam, H.1
-
61
-
-
67650726710
-
Back to the Theory of Appearing
-
W.P. Alston, 'Back to the Theory of Appearing', Philosophical Perspectives, 13 (1999), pp. 181-203
-
(1999)
Philosophical Perspectives
, vol.13
, pp. 181-203
-
-
Alston, W.P.1
-
63
-
-
79957395771
-
-
Byrne and Logue, 'Either/Or', pp. 89-90.
-
See Byrne and Logue, 'Either/Or', pp. 89-90
-
-
-
-
66
-
-
75949101633
-
-
Causation, though, is an especially tricky case - locus classicus: A. Michotte, The Perception of Causality (London: Methuen, 1963);
-
Causation, though, is an especially tricky case - locus classicus: A. Michotte, The Perception of Causality (London: Methuen, 1963)
-
-
-
-
67
-
-
75949110793
-
The Visual Experience of Causation
-
59 2009, this issue, pp
-
see also S. Siegel, 'The Visual Experience of Causation', The Philosophical Quarterly, 59 (2009) (this issue), pp. 519-40
-
The Philosophical Quarterly
, pp. 519-540
-
-
Siegel, S.1
-
69
-
-
1642283358
-
Perception and Belief
-
It is important to note that the claim that perception constitutively involves belief (in particular, that exing is believing) does not imply that perception can be reduced to belief.
-
see also A.D. Smith, 'Perception and Belief, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62 (2001), pp. 283-309. It is important to note that the claim that perception constitutively involves belief (in particular, that exing is believing) does not imply that perception can be reduced to belief
-
(2001)
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
, vol.62
, pp. 283-309
-
-
Smith, A.D.1
-
70
-
-
75949120094
-
-
For advice and assistance which greatly improved this paper, thanks to David Chalmers, James Genone, Jeff King, Heather Logue, Fiona Macpherson, Adam Pautz, Susanna Rinard, Susanna Siegel, Charles Travis, Michael Tye, an anonymous referee, and audiences at the Australian National University and the University of Glasgow
-
For advice and assistance which greatly improved this paper, thanks to David Chalmers, James Genone, Jeff King, Heather Logue, Fiona Macpherson, Adam Pautz, Susanna Rinard, Susanna Siegel, Charles Travis, Michael Tye, an anonymous referee, and audiences at the Australian National University and the University of Glasgow
-
-
-
|