메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 3, 2009, Pages 253-274

Liberalism, deliberative democracy, and "reasons that all can accept"

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 68249120287     PISSN: 09638016     EISSN: 14679760     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9760.2008.00330.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (95)

References (56)
  • 1
    • 68249093231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We would like to thank Dennis Thompson, David Estlund, Leif Wenar, William Rehg, and Paul Weithman for their many helpful criticisms and suggestions. In thanking them, we do not mean to imply that they could accept the reasoning offered here.
  • 2
    • 22444454766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The coming of age of deliberative democracy
    • -43
    • James Bohman The coming of age of deliberative democracy Journal of Political Philosophy, 4 (1998 418 43
    • (1998) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.4
    • Bohman, J.1
  • 4
    • 0242440593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberative democracy: A sympathetic comment
    • Samuel Freeman Deliberative democracy: a sympathetic comment Philosophy and Public Affairs, 29 (2000 371 418.
    • (2000) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.29 , pp. 371-418
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 5
    • 0003266374 scopus 로고
    • Discourse ethics: Notes on a program of justification
    • Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
    • For the more general principle of discursive justification, see Jürgen Habermas, "Discourse ethics: notes on a program of justification," Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990), pp. 43-115.
    • (1990) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action , pp. 43-115
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 6
    • 0003576528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press) hereafter cited as BFN
    • Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996), p. 166; hereafter cited as BFN.
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms , pp. 166
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 7
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (New York: Columbia University Press) 137; hereafter cited as PL
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism, rev. edn (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), pp. li, 137; hereafter cited as PL.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism, Rev. Edn
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 8
    • 68249120908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas, BFN, p. 110
    • Habermas, BFN, p. 110.
  • 9
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press) 91; hereafter cited as JF
    • John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001), pp. 41, 91; hereafter cited as JF.
    • (2001) Justice As Fairness: A Restatement , pp. 41
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 12
    • 84972066040 scopus 로고
    • Public practical reason: An archeology
    • Gerald Postema Public practical reason: an archeology Social Philosophy and Policy, 12 (1995 43 86.
    • (1995) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.12 , pp. 43-86
    • Postema, G.1
  • 13
    • 0039031609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea of public reason revisited
    • Rawls, PL, pp. xliv, xlvi, li; cf. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press) hereafter cited as IPPR
    • Rawls, PL, pp. xliv, xlvi, li; cf. John Rawls, "The idea of public reason revisited," The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 137; hereafter cited as IPPR.
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 137
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 14
    • 68249111984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, PL, pp. 137, 139, 217; JF, pp. 41, 84, 90, 141; see also IPRR, p. 137
    • Rawls, PL, pp. 137, 139, 217; JF, pp. 41, 84, 90, 141; see also IPRR, p. 137.
  • 15
    • 68249126980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, PL, pp. 218, 226, 236
    • Rawls, PL, pp. 218, 226, 236.
  • 16
    • 68249089326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Public reason and political justification
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press) at p. 221 n.8
    • JF is based on Rawls's lecture notes from the 1980s, and hence represents material that antedated both PL and IPRR: see Samuel Freeman, "Public reason and political justification," Justice and the Social Contract: Essays on Rawlsian Political Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 215-56, at p. 221 n.8.
    • (2007) Justice and the Social Contract: Essays on Rawlsian Political Philosophy , pp. 215-56
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 17
    • 68249091460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, IPRR, p. 137
    • Rawls, IPRR, p. 137.
  • 18
    • 68249131852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This expectation-based aspect of the standard is present in Rawls's other statements of the liberal principle of legitimacy in PL, see pp. 137, 140, 217, 218, 226.
  • 19
    • 68249098500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This late use of "reasonably" to characterize the mode of acceptance required seems to sum up, in a simplifying way, the range of other formulations Rawls earlier employed: "in light of their own reason" (JF, p. 91), "in light of free public reason" (JF, p. 141), "in light of shared political values" (JF, p. 202), "in light of common reason" (JF, pp. 41, 84; PL, pp. 137, 140), and "as reasonable and rational" (PL, p. 217). In taking "reasonably" to serve this role, we follow Freeman, "Public Reason and Political Justification," p. 215.
  • 20
    • 68249120078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, PL, pp. 385-92
    • Rawls, PL, pp. 385-92.
  • 21
    • 68249120079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We here pass over certain complexities that arise from Rawls's distinction between pro tanto justification and full justification. Full justification will require each citizen to embed the candidate political view within his or her reasonable comprehensive doctrine, and that will raise further questions about what he or she can accept. About this, however, our basic position is that the grounds for reasonable hope in the possibility of such acceptance will again rest on the content of the requirements of reasonableness, now as constraining the set of comprehensive doctrines that are relevant to consider.
  • 23
    • 68249122740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We do not mean to claim that Rawls misleads us when he states his criterion of reciprocity; rather, we believe that the aspect of mutuality enters in via the publicity expected, on his view, of all justification, rather than via the way the acceptability of reasons is limited. Cf. ibid., pp. 217-220, on the connection between publicity and Rawls's account of public reason.
  • 24
    • 68249099321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul Weithman has asked us what happens if the requirements of reasonableness boil down to just this: that people be willing to offer one another RACAs. Our answer is that a theory that held this would remain irretrievably vague. Rawls's own interpretation of the requirements of reasonableness, of course, is far more substantive than this. See Freeman, "Public Reason and Political Justification."
    • Public Reason and Political Justification
    • Freeman1
  • 26
    • 68249114886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • nope
    • Indeed, the formulation could be seen as triply hypothetical: could people have converged upon reasons that each could accept, which reasons could have supported the political outcome in question?
  • 28
    • 85086971443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conflict and self-interest in deliberation
    • Habermas, BFN, p. 344. For criticisms of attempts to separate deliberation from bargaining and negotiation ed. Samantha Besson and José Luis Marti (Aldershot: Ashgate)
    • Habermas, BFN, p. 344. For criticisms of attempts to separate deliberation from bargaining and negotiation, see Jane Mansbridge, "Conflict and self-interest in deliberation," Deliberative Democracy and Its Discontents, ed. Samantha Besson and José Luis Marti (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006), pp. 107-32.
    • (2006) Deliberative Democracy and Its Discontents , pp. 107-32
    • Mansbridge, J.1
  • 29
    • 0038627887 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • See Seyla Behabib, The Claims of Culture (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 145.
    • (1992) The Claims of Culture , pp. 145
    • Behabib, S.1
  • 30
    • 0004274013 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Amartya Sen, Inequality Reexamined (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), p. 65.
    • (1993) Inequality Reexamined , pp. 65
    • Sen, A.1
  • 33
    • 38049089052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pettit slips back into the strong version of convergence when he argues for forming various sorts of commissions on just these grounds, since their decisions have to be justified on the basis of strict guidelines that have already been accepted by all sides of politics. See Pettit, "Depoliticizing democracy," p. 96. In this case actual and not hypothetical agreement plays the justifying role, and the problem of deliberation is just put back a stage. Commissions are not themselves solutions to the problem of disagreement, but rather express the results already achieved in deliberation.
    • Depoliticizing Democracy , pp. 96
    • Pettit1
  • 34
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 514
    • The quoted phrase is found in Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. edn (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 19, 514.
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice, Rev. Edn , pp. 19
    • Rawls1
  • 35
    • 68249132666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, PL, p. 13
    • Rawls, PL, p. 13.
  • 36
    • 0002658765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and democratic legitimacy
    • ed. J. Bohman and W. Rehg (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press)
    • Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and democratic legitimacy," Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, ed. J. Bohman and W. Rehg (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996), p. 75.
    • (1996) Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics , pp. 75
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 37
    • 68249129107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, PL, p. 386
    • Rawls, PL, p. 386.
  • 38
    • 68249117288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the modality of hope, see Rawls, PL, pp. 40, 172, 246, 252, 392
    • For the modality of hope, see Rawls, PL, pp. 40, 172, 246, 252, 392.
  • 39
    • 68249087511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We are grateful to an anonymous reviewer for this journal for raising this objection.
  • 40
    • 68249116908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, PL, pp. 36-7
    • Rawls, PL, pp. 36-7.
  • 41
    • 42949148252 scopus 로고
    • "incompletely theorized agreements
    • "Incompletely theorized agreements Harvard Law Review, 108 (1995 1733 72.
    • (1995) Harvard Law Review , vol.108 , pp. 1733-72
  • 44
    • 0242719845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberative toleration
    • James Bohman Deliberative toleration Political Theory, 31 (2003 757 79
    • (2003) Political Theory , vol.31 , pp. 757-79
    • Bohman, J.1
  • 45
    • 68249105647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy and the epistemic benefits of diversity
    • James Bohman Democracy and the epistemic benefits of diversity Episteme, 3 (2007 175 90.
    • (2007) Episteme , vol.3 , pp. 175-90
    • Bohman, J.1
  • 46
    • 33644924995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 93 ff
    • For a similar emphasis on sincere argument in political deliberation, coupled with some resistance to limits on admissible reasons, see Paul J. Weithman, Religion and the Obligations of Citizenship (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), pp. 93 ff.
    • (2002) Religion and the Obligations of Citizenship
    • Paul, J.1    Weithman2
  • 47
    • 0038263730 scopus 로고
    • Apparently irrational beliefs
    • ed. M. Hollis and S. Lukes (Cambridge: MIT Press)
    • The phrase is from Dan Sperber, "Apparently irrational beliefs," Rationality and Relativism, ed. M. Hollis and S. Lukes (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1982). Sperber concludes his criticism of anthropologists as follows: "In pre-relativist anthropology, Westerners thought of themselves as superior to all other people. Relativism replaced this despicable hierarchical gap by a kind of cognitive apartheid. If we cannot be superior in the same world, let each people live in its own world" (pp. 179-80).
    • (1982) Rationality and Relativism , pp. 179-80
    • Sperber, D.1
  • 48
    • 0002710712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "democratic deliberation within
    • "Democratic deliberation within Philosophy & Public Affairs, 29 (2000 79 107
    • (2000) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.29 , pp. 79-107
  • 49
    • 84869571880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On "moral compromise" as necessary in cases of deep conflict
    • James Bohman, Public Deliberation (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996), pp. 89-93
    • Deep compromise is thus defined in Richardson, Democratic Autonomy, p. 147. On "moral compromise" as necessary in cases of deep conflict, see James Bohman, Public Deliberation (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996), pp. 89-93.
    • Democratic Autonomy , pp. 147
    • Richardson1
  • 51
    • 0003442441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) ch. 3; and see Henry S. Richardson, Practical Reasoning about Final Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), pt. V
    • See, e.g., Martha Nussbaum, Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), ch. 3; and see Henry S. Richardson, Practical Reasoning about Final Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), pt. V.
    • (2000) Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 52
    • 68249120907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberative toleration
    • Iris Marion Young (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • On the importance of perspective taking, see Bohman, "Deliberative toleration," and Iris Marion Young, Inclusion and Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (2001) Inclusion and Democracy
    • Bohman1
  • 53
    • 68249102704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Cf. Rawls, PL, p. 217: "The duty of civility. also involves a willingness to listen to others and a fairmindedness in deciding when accommodations to their views should reasonably be made." Paul Weithman reminds us that a notion such as "open-mindedness" or "fairmindedness" surely cannot be analyzed without reference to complex counterfactuals. In arguing that the idea of RACAs cannot do useful work for theories of liberal democracy, however, we are not arguing that there is not hard work to be done. The requirement that one offer only RACAs in political dialogue presents an illusion of simplicity. We have not suggested replacing it by anything equally simple involving "do accept."
  • 54
    • 35148879560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press For a discussion of these standpoints in cosmopolitan democracy, see Bohman, Democracy Across Borders, ch. 3
    • For an insightful elaboration of the contrast between third-personal and second-personal normative standpoints, see Stephen Darwall, The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2006). For a discussion of these standpoints in cosmopolitan democracy, see Bohman, Democracy Across Borders, ch. 3.
    • (2006) The Second-person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability
    • Darwall, S.1
  • 55
    • 68249094233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here, too, Rawls provides us with precedent. On the necessary attitude of hopefulness, see, e.g., PL, pp. 40, 172, 246, 252, 392
    • Here, too, Rawls provides us with precedent. On the necessary attitude of hopefulness, see, e.g., PL, pp. 40, 172, 246, 252, 392.
  • 56
    • 35648980979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 5 and Richardson, Democratic Autonomy, esp. ch. 4
    • Setting out a constructive approach to democratic authority and the will of the people that does not rely on the idea of RACAs poses too many complex issues for us to take up here. For our thoughts on the issue, see Bohman, Democracy Across Borders, ch. 5 and Richardson, Democratic Autonomy, esp. ch. 4.
    • Democracy Across Borders
    • Bohman1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.