메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 41, Issue 3, 2003, Pages 411-449

Mathematics and the theory of multiplicities: Badiou and Deleuze revisited

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 67650799904     PISSN: 00384283     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.2041-6962.2003.tb00960.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (46)

References (116)
  • 1
    • 0004214606 scopus 로고
    • trans. Sean Hand Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • Gilles Deleuze, Foucault, trans. Sean Hand (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1886), 2. Deleuze was speaking of Virilio's relation to Foucault.
    • (1886) Foucault , pp. 2
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 2
    • 0037602283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris: Editions du Seuil
    • Alain Badiou, L'être et l'événement (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1988). An English translation of Badiou's magnum opus by Oliver Feltham is forthcoming from Continuum.
    • (1988) L'Être et l'Événement
    • Badiou, A.1
  • 3
    • 37949000372 scopus 로고
    • A Philosophical Concept
    • ed. Eduardo Cadava, Peter Connor, Jean-Luc Nancy New York: Routledge
    • Gilles Deleuze, "A Philosophical Concept," in Who Comes After the Subject, ed. Eduardo Cadava, Peter Connor, Jean-Luc Nancy (New York: Routledge, 1991), 95.
    • (1991) Who Comes after the Subject , pp. 95
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 4
    • 0347272714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Louise Burchill Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • Alain Badiou, Deleuze: The Clamor of Being, trans. Louise Burchill (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000), 4.
    • (2000) Deleuze: The Clamor of Being , pp. 4
    • Badiou, A.1
  • 6
    • 24944574830 scopus 로고
    • The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque
    • Constantin V. Boundas and Dorothea Olkowski, ed. , [New York and London: Routledge]
    • See Badiou, L'être et l'événement, 522: "the latent paradigm in Deleuze is 'natural'. . . . Mine is mathematical. " Similarly, in his review article of Deleuze's book on Leibniz, Badiou writes: "There have never been but two schemas or paradigms of the Multiple: the mathematical and the organicist. . . . This is the cross of metaphysics, and the greatness of Deleuze . . . is to choose without hesitation for the animal" (in Alain Badiou, "Gilles Deleuze, 'The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque'," in Constantin V. Boundas and Dorothea Olkowski, ed. , Gilles Deleuze and the Theater of Philosophy [New York and London: Routledge, 1994], 55).
    • (1994) Gilles Deleuze and the Theater of Philosophy , pp. 55
    • Badiou, A.1    Deleuze, G.2
  • 7
    • 79958893288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 20 May
    • This same theme is continued in Badiou's article "De la Vie comme nom de l'Être," in Rue Descartes 20 (May 1998), 27-34
    • (1998) Rue Descartes , pp. 27-34
  • 8
    • 33751376342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris: Seuil
    • which is reprinted in revised form as "L'Ontologie vitaliste de Deleuze," in Alain Badiou, Court Traité d'ontologie transitoire (Paris: Seuil, 1998), 61-72.
    • (1998) Court Traité d'Ontologie Transitoire , pp. 61-72
    • Badiou, A.1
  • 9
    • 84868474999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for instance, the articles on Badiou's book by Eric Alliez, Arnaud Villani, and José Gil, collected in Future Antérieur 43.
    • See, for instance, the articles on Badiou's book by Eric Alliez, Arnaud Villani, and José Gil, collected in Future Antérieur 43.
  • 12
    • 0004117671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Paul Patton (New York: Columbia University Press)
    • See Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994), 323, note 22: Given the irreducibility of 'problems' in his thought, Deleuze writes that "the use of the word 'problematic' as a substantive seems to us an indispensable neologism. "
    • (1994) Difference and Repetition , pp. 323
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 13
    • 84868454269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alain Badiou, "Une, multiple, multiplicité(s)," 4. This unpublished text is, to my knowledge, Badiou's only direct discussion of Deleuze's theory of multiplicities. I thank Peter Hallward for making the manuscript available to me
    • Alain Badiou, "Une, multiple, multiplicité(s)," 4. This unpublished text is, to my knowledge, Badiou's only direct discussion of Deleuze's theory of multiplicities. I thank Peter Hallward for making the manuscript available to me.
  • 14
    • 80052203558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This article has been published under the same title in Multitudes 1 Mar 2000, 195-211; my page references are to the typescript
    • This article has been published under the same title in Multitudes 1 (Mar 2000), 195-211; my page references are to the typescript.
  • 15
    • 0004254542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press)
    • See Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, trans. Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), 374: "Only royal science has at its disposal a metric power that can define a conceptual apparatus or an autonomy of science (including the autonomy of experimental science). " On page 486: "Major science has a perpetual need for the inspiration of the minor; but the minor would be nothing if it did not confront and conform to the highest scientific requirements. "
    • (1987) A Thousand Plateaus , pp. 374
    • Deleuze, G.1    Guattari, F.2
  • 18
    • 79958915095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Badiou, Deleuze, 46: I uphold that the forms of the multiple are, just like Ideas, always actual and that the virtual does not exist. Deleuze agrees with this characterization of sets: Everything is actual in a numerical multiplicity; everything is not 'realized,' but everything there is actual. There are no relationships other than those between actuals.
    • Badiou, Deleuze, 46: "I uphold that the forms of the multiple are, just like Ideas, always actual and that the virtual does not exist. " Deleuze agrees with this characterization of sets: "Everything is actual in a numerical multiplicity; everything is not 'realized,' but everything there is actual. There are no relationships other than those between actuals. "
  • 19
    • 0004207187 scopus 로고
    • trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam New York: Zone Books
    • Gilles Deleuze, Bergsonism, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (New York: Zone Books, 1988), 43.
    • (1988) Bergsonism , pp. 43
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 20
    • 0003903165 scopus 로고
    • trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane New York: Viking
    • Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus, trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane (New York: Viking, 1977), 371-2.
    • (1977) Anti-Oedipus , pp. 371-372
    • Deleuze, G.1    Guattari, F.2
  • 21
    • 84868503899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Badiou's appeal to Lautréamont, see Court Traité, 72
    • For Badiou's appeal to Lautréamont, see Court Traité, 72
  • 22
    • 85035625073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and "De la Vie comme nom de l'Être," Rue Descartes, 34.
    • Rue Descartes , pp. 34
  • 23
    • 70449838003 scopus 로고
    • Letter to a Harsh Critic
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • See Deleuze's well-known comments on his relation to the history of philosophy in "Letter to a Harsh Critic," in Negotiations, trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), 5-6.
    • (1995) Negotiations , pp. 5-6
    • Joughin, M.1
  • 24
    • 0004316316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • The best general works on the history of mathematics are Carl B. Boyer, History of Mathematics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1968)
    • (1968) History of Mathematics
    • Boyer, C.B.1
  • 26
    • 79958911416 scopus 로고
    • trans. Glenn R. Murrow Princeton, N. J, Princeton University Press
    • Proclus, Commentary of the First Book of Euclid's Elements, trans. Glenn R. Murrow (Princeton, N. J. : Princeton University Press, 1970), 63-7
    • (1970) Commentary of the First Book of Euclid's Elements , pp. 63-67
    • Proclus1
  • 29
    • 79958898237 scopus 로고
    • with Charles Stivale; ed. Constantin V. Boundas (New York: Columbia University Press)
    • and Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester, with Charles Stivale; ed. Constantin V. Boundas (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990), 54.
    • (1990) Logic of Sense , pp. 54
    • Lester, M.1
  • 30
    • 79958932330 scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • See also Deleuze's comments in The Time-Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989), 174: theorems and problems are are "two mathematical instances which constantly refer to each other, the one enveloping the second, the second sliding into the first, but both very different in spite of their union. " On the two types of deduction, see 185.
    • (1989) The Time-Image , pp. 174
    • Tomlinson, H.1    Habberjam, B.2
  • 31
    • 0004178623 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon & Schuster
    • For instance, determining a triangle the sum of whose angles is 180 degrees is theorematic, since the angles of every triangle will total 180 degrees. Constructing an equilateral triangle on a given finite straight line, by contrast, is problematic, since we could also construct a non-equilateral triangle or a non-triangular figure on the line (moreover, the construction of an equilateral triangle must first pass through the construction of two circles). Classical geometers struggled for centuries with the three great "problems" of antiquity: - trisecting an angle, constructing a cube having double the volume of a given cube, and constructing a square equal to a circle - though it would turn out that none of these problems is solvable using only a straightedge and compass. See E. T. Bell's comments in Men of Mathematics (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1937), 31-2.
    • (1937) Men of Mathematics , pp. 31-32
    • Bell, E.T.1
  • 34
    • 33645722436 scopus 로고
    • ed. John P. Leavey, Jr. and David B. Allison (Stony Brook, N. Y. : H. Hayes)
    • See also Edmund Husserl's Origin of Geometry: An Introduction, ed. John P. Leavey, Jr. and David B. Allison (Stony Brook, N. Y. : H. Hayes, 1978), which includes Jacques Derrida's important commentary. Whereas Husserl saw problematics as "proto-geometry," Deleuze sees it as a fully autonomous dimension of geometry, but one he identifies as a "minor" science; it is a "proto"-geometry only from the viewpoint of the "major" or "royal" conception of geometry, which attempts to eliminate these dynamic events or variations by subjecting them to a theorematic treatment.
    • (1978) Origin of Geometry: An Introduction
    • Husserl, E.1
  • 35
    • 0004117671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (emphasis added)
    • Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, 160 (emphasis added). Deleuze continues: "As a result [of using reductio ad absurdum proofs], however, the genetic point of view is forcibly relegated to an inferior rank: proof is given that something cannot not be, rather than that it is and why it is (hence the frequency in Euclid of negative, indirect and reductio arguments, which serve to keep geometry under the domination of the principle of identity and prevent it from becoming a geometry of sufficient reason). "
    • Difference and Repetition , pp. 160
    • Deleuze1
  • 37
    • 0007069480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boyer makes a similar point in his History of Mathematics, 141: "Greek mathematics sometimes has been described as essentially static, with little regard for the notion of variability; but Archimedes, in his study of the spiral, seems to have found the tangent to the curve through kinematic considerations akin to the differential calculus. "
    • History of Mathematics , pp. 141
  • 39
    • 84868474979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • transcripts of Deleuze's seminars, by Richard Pinhas, are available on-line at 〈http://www. webdeleuze. com/sommaire. html〉).
  • 42
    • 0004254542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 28
    • which establishes a continuity between Desargues, Monge, and Poncelet as the "founders of a modern geometry" (A Thousand Plateaus, 554, note 28).
    • A Thousand Plateaus , pp. 554
  • 43
    • 0004182892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell, New York: Columbia University Press
    • Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What is Philosophy? trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994), 128, translation modified.
    • (1994) What Is Philosophy , pp. 128
    • Deleuze, G.1    Guattari, F.2
  • 46
    • 84982991265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deleuze praises Boyer's book as "the best study of the history of the differential calculus and its modern structural interpretation" (Logic of Sense, 339).
    • Logic of Sense , pp. 339
  • 47
    • 0003781403 scopus 로고
    • Boston, Basel, and Stuttgart: Birkhäuser
    • For a discussion of the various uses of the term "intuition" in mathematics, see the chapters on "Intuition" and "Four- Dimensional Intuition" in Philip J. Davis and Reuben Hersch, The Mathematical Experience (Boston, Basel, and Stuttgart: Birkhäuser, 1981), 391-405
    • (1981) The Mathematical Experience , pp. 391-405
    • Davis, P.J.1    Hersch, R.2
  • 48
    • 0040300260 scopus 로고
    • The Crisis in Intuition
    • New York: Simon and Schuster
    • as well as Hans Hahn's classic article "The Crisis in Intuition," in J. R. Newman, ed. , The World of Mathematics (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1956), 1956-76.
    • (1956) The World of Mathematics , pp. 1956-1976
    • Newman, J.R.1
  • 49
    • 79959007012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The History of Mathematics
    • chapter 25, at 598
    • Boyer, The History of Mathematics, chapter 25, "The Arithmetization of Analysis," 598-619, at 598.
    • The Arithmetization of Analysis , pp. 598-619
    • Boyer1
  • 50
    • 53349106071 scopus 로고
    • The 'Fine Structure' of Mathematical Revolutions: Metaphysics, Legitimacy, and Rigour
    • ed. Donald Gilles Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Guilio Giorello, "The 'Fine Structure' of Mathematical Revolutions: Metaphysics, Legitimacy, and Rigour," in Revolutions in Mathematics, ed. Donald Gilles (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 135. I thank Andrew Murphie for this reference.
    • (1992) Revolutions in Mathematics , pp. 135
    • Giorello, G.1
  • 51
    • 84868454247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See his article "A Requium for Postmodernism," which is available online at 〈http://mdcm. arts. unsw. edu. au/homepage/StaffPages/ Murphie〉.
  • 52
    • 0009086524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See Penelope Maddy, Naturalism in Mathematics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 51-2, for a discussion of Cantorian "finitism. "
    • (1997) Naturalism in Mathematics , pp. 51-52
    • Maddy, P.1
  • 57
    • 0039161149 scopus 로고
    • Austin: Center for Theoretical Physics, University of Texas
    • John Wheeler, in Frontiers of Time (Austin: Center for Theoretical Physics, University of Texas, 1978), has put forward the stronger thesis that the laws of physics are themselves "mutable" (13).
    • (1978) Frontiers of Time
    • Wheeler, J.1
  • 58
  • 59
  • 60
    • 0003513971 scopus 로고
    • New York: Norton
    • Bertrand Russell makes the same point in his Principles of Mathematics (New York: Norton, 1938), 347, citing Poincaré: "The continuum thus conceived [i. e. , arithmetically or discretely] is nothing but a collection of individuals arranged in a certain order, infinite in number, it is true, but external to each other. This is not the ordinary [geometric or "natural"] conception, in which there is supposed to be, between the elements of the continuum, a sort of intimate bond which makes a whole of them, in which the point is not prior to the line, but the line to the point. Of the famous formula, the continuum is a unity in multiplicity, the multiplicity alone subsists, the unity has disappeared" (347).
    • (1938) Principles of Mathematics , pp. 347
  • 61
    • 79958985217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deleuze, seminar of 29 April 1980
    • Deleuze, seminar of 29 April 1980.
  • 62
    • 0004232766 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Abraham Robinson, Non-Standard Analysis (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1966), 83. See also 277: "With the spread of Weierstrass' ideas, arguments involving infinitesimal increments, which survived particularly in differential geometry and in several branches of applied mathematics, began to be taken automatically as a kind of shorthand for corresponding developments by means of the e, d approach. "
    • (1966) Non-Standard Analysis , pp. 83
    • Robinson, A.1
  • 63
    • 84868474975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Deleuze, Le Pli, 177: "Robinson suggested considering the Leibnizian monad as a infinite number very different from transfinites, as a unit surrounded by a zone of infinitely small [numbers] that reflect the converging series of the world. "
    • See Deleuze, Le Pli, 177: "Robinson suggested considering the Leibnizian monad as a infinite number very different from transfinites, as a unit surrounded by a zone of infinitely small [numbers] that reflect the converging series of the world. "
  • 65
    • 79959026697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Infinitesimally Yours
    • 20 May
    • For discussions of Robinson's achievement, see Jim Holt's useful review, "Infinitesimally Yours," in The New York Review of Books, 20 May 1999
    • (1999) The New York Review of Books
    • Holt, J.1
  • 66
    • 79958992716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nonstandard Analysis
    • as well as the chapter on "Nonstandard Analysis" in Davis and Hersch, The Mathematical Experience, 237-54. The latter note that "Robinson has in a sense vindicated the reckless abandon of eighteenth-century mathematics against the straight-laced rigor of the nineteenth-century, adding a new chapter in the never ending war between the finite and the infinite, the continuous and the discrete" (238).
    • The Mathematical Experience , pp. 237-254
    • Davis1    Hersch2
  • 69
    • 0347490812 scopus 로고
    • The Architecture of Mathematics
    • ed. François Le Lionnais; trans. R. A. Hall and Howard G. Bergmann (New York: Dover)
    • Nicholas Bourbaki, "The Architecture of Mathematics," in Great Currents of Mathematical Thought, ed. François Le Lionnais; trans. R. A. Hall and Howard G. Bergmann (New York: Dover, 1971), 31.
    • (1971) Great Currents of Mathematical Thought , pp. 31
    • Bourbaki, N.1
  • 70
    • 34250580445 scopus 로고
    • L'oeuvre mathématique de Weierstrass
    • Henri Poincaré, "L'oeuvre mathématique de Weierstrass," Acta mathematica 22 (1898-1899), 1-18
    • (1898) Acta Mathematica , vol.22 , pp. 1-18
    • Poincaré, H.1
  • 71
    • 3643074254 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Minuit
    • See Deleuze, Le Pli: Leibniz et le baroque (Paris: Minuit, 1988), 64: "axioms concern problems, and escape demonstration. "
    • (1988) Le Pli: Leibniz et le Baroque , pp. 64
    • Deleuze1
  • 72
    • 84868472032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This section of the "Treatise on Nomadology" (361-74) develops in detail the distinction between "major" and "minor" science
    • This section of the "Treatise on Nomadology" (361-74) develops in detail the distinction between "major" and "minor" science.
  • 73
    • 0003530823 scopus 로고
    • trans. Carolyn R. Fawcett (New York: Zone Books)
    • Deleuze is referring to the distinction between "problem" and "theory" in Georges Canguilhem, On the Normal and the Pathological, trans. Carolyn R. Fawcett (New York: Zone Books, 1978);
    • (1978) On the Normal and the Pathological
    • Canguilhem, G.1
  • 74
    • 84868506324 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Éditions d'Enseignement supérieur
    • the distinction between the "problem-element" and the "global synthesis element" in Georges Bouligand, Le déclin des absolus methmatico-logiques (Paris: Éditions d'Enseignement supérieur, 1949);
    • (1949) Le Déclin des Absolus Methmatico-logiques
    • Bouligand, G.1
  • 75
    • 79954216782 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Hermann
    • On this score, Deleuze largely follows Lautman's thesis that mathematics participates in a dialectic that points beyond itself to a meta-mathematical power - that is, to a general theory of problems and their ideal synthesis - which accounts for the genesis of mathematics itself. See Albert Lautman, Nouvelles recherches sur la structure dialectique des mathematiques (Paris: Hermann, 1939), particularly the section entitled "The Genesis of Mathematics from the Dialectic": "The order implied by the notion of genesis is no longer of the order of logical reconstruction in mathematics, in the sense that from the initial axioms of a theory flow all the propositions of the theory, for the dialectic is not a part of mathematics, and its notions have no relation to the primitive notions of a theory" (13-14). Despite his occasional appeal to Lautman, Badiou is opposed to this Lautmanian appeal to a meta-mathematical dialectic.
    • (1939) Nouvelles Recherches sur la Structure Dialectique des Mathematiques
    • Lautman, A.1
  • 77
    • 0004238520 scopus 로고
    • trans. Mabelle L. Andison (Totowa, N. J. : Littlefield, Adams & Co.)
    • Henri Bergson, The Creative Mind, trans. Mabelle L. Andison (Totowa, N. J. : Littlefield, Adams & Co. , 1975), 33. See also 191: "Metaphysics should adopt the generative idea of our mathematics [i. e. , change, or becoming] in order to extend it to all qualities, that is, to reality in general. "
    • (1975) The Creative Mind , pp. 33
    • Bergson, H.1
  • 78
    • 79958914233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Deleuze, seminar of 29 April 1980
    • See Deleuze, seminar of 29 April 1980.
  • 79
    • 79958963319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanence and Difference: Toward a Relational Ontology
    • For analyses of Deleuze's theory of multiplicities, see Robin Durie, "Immanence and Difference: Toward a Relational Ontology," in Southern Journal of Philosophy, 60 (2002), 1-29;
    • (2002) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.60 , pp. 1-29
    • Durie, R.1
  • 83
    • 0004073958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kline, Mathematical Thought, 759: "The group of an equation is a key to its solvability because the group expresses the degree of indistinguishability of the roots. It tells us what we do not know about the roots. "
    • Mathematical Thought , pp. 759
    • Kline1
  • 84
    • 84868482251 scopus 로고
    • Evariste Galois et la théorie des équations algébraiques
    • Paris: Gauthier-Villars
    • citing C. Georges Verriest, "Evariste Galois et la théorie des équations algébraiques," in Oeuvres mathématiques de Galois (Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1961), 41.
    • (1961) Oeuvres Mathématiques de Galois , pp. 41
    • Citing, C.1    Verriest, G.2
  • 85
    • 0004273459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael A Greco Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • Gilles Deleuze, Essays Critical and Clinical, trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael A Greco (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997), 149
    • (1997) Essays Critical and Clinical , pp. 149
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 86
    • 79958928787 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Fasquelle
    • citing a text by Galois in André Dalmas, Evariste Galois (Paris: Fasquelle, 1956), 132.
    • (1956) Evariste Galois , pp. 132
    • Dalmas, A.1
  • 87
    • 33749593415 scopus 로고
    • Paris: PUF
    • referring to Jules Vuillemin, La philosophie de l'algèbre (Paris: PUF, 1962). "Jules Vuillemin's book proposes a determination of structures [or multiplicities, in Deleuze's sense] in mathematics. In this regard, he insists on the importance of a theory of problems (following the mathematical Abel) and the principles of determination (reciprocal, complete, and progressive determination according to Galois). He shows how structures, in this sense, provide the only means for realizing the ambitions of a true genetic method. "
    • (1962) La Philosophie de l'Algèbre
    • Vuillemin, J.1
  • 88
    • 84870080028 scopus 로고
    • A quoi reconnait-on le structuralisme
    • ed. François Châtelet (Paris: Hachette)
    • See Gilles Deleuze, "A quoi reconnait-on le structuralisme," in Histoire de la philosophie 8, ed. François Châtelet (Paris: Hachette, 1972-73), 315.
    • (1972) Histoire de la Philosophie , vol.8 , pp. 315
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 90
    • 79958871461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although Badiou occasionally appeals to Lautman see Deleuze, 98, his own ontology seems opposed to Lautman's; moreover, Badiou never considers Deleuze's own appropriation of Lautman's theory of differential equations, even though Deleuze cites it in almost every one of his books after 1968
    • Although Badiou occasionally appeals to Lautman (see Deleuze, 98), his own ontology seems opposed to Lautman's; moreover, Badiou never considers Deleuze's own appropriation of Lautman's theory of differential equations, even though Deleuze cites it in almost every one of his books after 1968.
  • 91
    • 84868508857 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Hermann
    • Lautman, Le Problème du temps (Paris: Hermann, 1946), 41-3; and Deleuze's seminar of 29 April 1980. Such singularities are now termed "attractors": using the language of physics, attractors govern "basins of attraction" that define the trajectories of the curves that fall within their "sphere of influence. "
    • (1946) Le Problème du Temps , pp. 41-43
    • Lautman1
  • 92
    • 84969624211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this reason, Deleuze's work has been seen to anticipate certain developments in complexity theory and chaos theory. Delanda in particular has emphasized this link in, see note 78
    • For this reason, Deleuze's work has been seen to anticipate certain developments in complexity theory and chaos theory. Delanda in particular has emphasized this link in Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy (see note 78).
    • Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy
  • 94
    • 79958871460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lautman, Essai, 43: "The constitution, by Gauss and Riemann, of a differential geometry that studies the intrinsic properties of a variety, independent of any space into which this variety would be plunged, eliminates any reference to a universal container or to a center of privileged coordinates. "
    • Essai , pp. 43
    • Lautman1
  • 95
    • 79958923565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Delanda, Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy, 15 (on attractors), and chapters 2 and 3 (on symmetry-breaking cascades)
    • See Delanda, Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy, 15 (on attractors), and chapters 2 and 3 (on symmetry-breaking cascades).
  • 97
    • 84929535560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This conflation is stated most clearly in Badiou, Deleuze, 46:
    • Deleuze , pp. 46
    • Badiou1
  • 98
    • 52549133276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rights of Simulacra: Deleuze and the Univocity of Being
    • "the univocal sovereignty of the One. " For discussions of Badiou's reading of the doctrine of univocity, see Nathan Widder, "The Rights of Simulacra: Deleuze and the Univocity of Being," in Continental Philosophy Review 34 (2001): 437-53
    • (2001) Continental Philosophy Review , vol.34 , pp. 437-453
    • Widder, N.1
  • 100
    • 84868482923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for instance, Badiou, Un, Multiple, Multiplicité(s), 3: The One can be called the Whole, Substance, Life, the Body without Organs, or Chaos.
    • See, for instance, Badiou, "Un, Multiple, Multiplicité(s), " 3: The One "can be called the Whole, Substance, Life, the Body without Organs, or Chaos. "
  • 102
    • 79958967190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deleuze, seminar of 22 April 1980. See also the seminar of 29 April 1980: Everyone agrees on the irreducibility of differential signs to any mathematical reality, that is to say, to geometrical, arithmetical, and algebraic reality. The difference arises when some people think, as a consequence, that differential calculus is only a convention - a rather suspect one - and others, on the contrary, think that its artificial character in relation to mathematical reality allows it to be adequate to certain aspects of physical reality.
    • Deleuze, seminar of 22 April 1980. See also the seminar of 29 April 1980: "Everyone agrees on the irreducibility of differential signs to any mathematical reality, that is to say, to geometrical, arithmetical, and algebraic reality. The difference arises when some people think, as a consequence, that differential calculus is only a convention - a rather suspect one - and others, on the contrary, think that its artificial character in relation to mathematical reality allows it to be adequate to certain aspects of physical reality. "
  • 103
    • 84868472020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deleuze, Abécédaire, "H as in 'History of Philosophy" (overview by Charles J. Stivale available on-line at 〈http://www. langlab. wayne. edu/Romance/FreDeleuze. html〉. )
  • 105
    • 0003501498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Deleuze, Negotiations, 130: "Poincaré used to say that many mathematical theories are completely irrelevant, pointless. He didn't say they were wrong - that wouldn't have been so bad. "
    • Negotiations , pp. 130
    • Deleuze1
  • 106
    • 84868474966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deleuze, seminars of 14 March 1978 and 21 March 1978. "The abstract is lived experience. I would almost say that once you have reached lived experience, you reach the most fully living core of the abstract. . . . You can live nothing but the abstract and nobody has lived anything else but the abstract. "
    • Deleuze, seminars of 14 March 1978 and 21 March 1978. "The abstract is lived experience. I would almost say that once you have reached lived experience, you reach the most fully living core of the abstract. . . . You can live nothing but the abstract and nobody has lived anything else but the abstract. "
  • 108
    • 79958899112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chapter 3
    • Badiou's claim that Deleuze's methodology relies on intuition is discussed in Deleuze: The Clamor of Being, chapter 3, 31-40.
    • Deleuze: The Clamor of Being , pp. 31-40
  • 109
    • 0005202774 scopus 로고
    • trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Zone Books)
    • For the role of the scholia, see Gilles Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Zone Books, 1992), 342-50 (the appendix on the scholia);
    • (1992) Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza , pp. 342-350
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 110
    • 79958952129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spinoza and the Three Ethics
    • for the uniqueness of the fifth book, see "Spinoza and the Three Ethics," in Essays Critical and Clinical, esp. 149-50.
    • Essays Critical and Clinical , pp. 149-150
  • 111
    • 84868448106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • L'ontologie fermée de Spinoza
    • See Badiou's essay on Spinoza, "L'ontologie fermée de Spinoza," in Court Traité, 73-93.
    • Court Traité , pp. 73-93
  • 112
    • 79958965531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Hersh's comments on Descartes in What is Mathematics, Really? 112-13: "Euclidean certainty boldly advertised in the Method and shamelessly ditched in the Geometry. "
    • Descartes in What Is Mathematics, Really? , pp. 112-113
  • 113
    • 84868503869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deleuze, seminar of 22 February 1972: "The true axiomatic is social and not scientific. . . . The scientific axiomatic is only one of the means by which the fluxes of science, the fluxes of knowledge, are guarded and taken up by the capitalist machine. . . . All axiomatics are means of leading science to the capitalist market. All axiomatics are abstract Oedipal formations. "
    • Deleuze, seminar of 22 February 1972: "The true axiomatic is social and not scientific. . . . The scientific axiomatic is only one of the means by which the fluxes of science, the fluxes of knowledge, are guarded and taken up by the capitalist machine. . . . All axiomatics are means of leading science to the capitalist market. All axiomatics are abstract Oedipal formations. "
  • 114
    • 84868482910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And Anti-Oedipus, 255: "The theoretical opposition lies elsewhere: it is between, on the one hand the decoded flows that enter into a class axiomatic on the full body of capital, and on the other hand, the decoded flows that free themselves from this axiomatic. "
    • And Anti-Oedipus, 255: "The theoretical opposition lies elsewhere: it is between, on the one hand the decoded flows that enter into a class axiomatic on the full body of capital, and on the other hand, the decoded flows that free themselves from this axiomatic. "


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.