-
1
-
-
0003419754
-
-
Cambridge, hereafter LS
-
Diogenes Laertius 7. 126, characterizes the Stoic ideal as φρόνιμος, αcombining comma aboveνδρειος, δί καιος, and σώφρ ων; cf. Plutarch De stoicorum repugnantiis 1034c-e [= 61C in The Hellenistic Philosophers, ed. A. A. Long and D. Sedley (Cambridge, 1987), hereafter LS];
-
(1987)
The Hellenistic Philosophers
-
-
Long, A.A.1
Sedley, D.2
-
2
-
-
84875608331
-
-
tr. W. O. Stephens, New York
-
However, Epictetus is not completely alone: as A. Long has pointed out to me, there is an affinity between Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius in the emphasis on the element of self-scrutiny in αιcombining comma aboveδώς (see below, and in Marcus, e. g. , Meditations 2. 6, 3. 6). A. O. Bonhöffer, The Ethics of the Stoic Epictetus, tr. W. O. Stephens (New York, 1996), 30-32, notes but does not really explain Epictetus' avoidance of standard Stoic virtue-terms.
-
(1996)
The Ethics of the Stoic Epictetus
, pp. 30-32
-
-
Bonhöffer, A.O.1
-
4
-
-
84880492694
-
-
On the restriction of good emotions to the wise, see the discussions in Inwood, Ethics, 173-75,
-
Ethics
, pp. 173-175
-
-
Inwood1
-
6
-
-
85163433276
-
Moral Actions and Rules in Stoic Ethics
-
ed. J. Rist California
-
On this point, see I. G. Kidd, "Moral Actions and Rules in Stoic Ethics," in The Stoics, ed. J. Rist (California, 1978), 247-58.
-
(1978)
The Stoics
, pp. 247-258
-
-
Kidd, I.G.1
-
7
-
-
67649847231
-
-
Stuttgart
-
See also Bonhöffer's argument that Nemesius cannot be describing true Stoic αιcombining comma aboveδώς, because he does not sufficiently distinguish αιcombining comma aboveδώς from αιcombining comma aboveσχύνη: both are a kind of fear of censure, attendant upon unease about one's conduct and indicative of there being something wrong with it. A. F. Bonhöffer, Epictet und die Stoa (Stuttgart, 1890), 291-93.
-
(1890)
Epictet und Die Stoa
, pp. 291-293
-
-
Bonhöffer, A.F.1
-
8
-
-
79958423763
-
-
ed. R. Sorabji
-
It is also possible that some Stoics gave αιcombining comma aboveδώς a double classification - as a passion when felt by the fool and a good emotion when felt by the sage. On double classifications, especially the double classification of εcombining comma abovéρως, see B. Inwood, "Why Do Fools Fall in Love?" forthcoming in Aristotle and After, ed. R. Sorabji.
-
Why Do Fools Fall in Love
-
-
Inwood, B.1
-
9
-
-
67649397456
-
Phantasia Kataleptike
-
ed. A. A. Long London
-
This account of cognition follows F. H. Sandbach, "Phantasia Kataleptike," in Problems in Stoicism, ed. A. A. Long (London, 1971), 9-19.
-
(1971)
Problems in Stoicism
, pp. 9-19
-
-
Sandbach, F.H.1
-
11
-
-
79958350889
-
Greek Ethics after MacIntyre
-
A. A. Long, "Greek Ethics After MacIntyre," in AncPhil 3 (1983): 184-97.
-
(1983)
AncPhil
, vol.3
, pp. 184-197
-
-
Long, A.A.1
-
12
-
-
5844382825
-
-
Michigan
-
See A. R. Dyck's A Commentary on Cicero, "De Officiis" (Michigan, 1996), introduction and comments ad loc. , for thorough discussions of the personae-doctrine in Cicero and other writers including Epictetus, as well as for a full treatment of the doctrine's Panaetian source and its anticipations in Aristo of Chios and Bion of Borysthenes. As Dyck notes, the third and fourth personae fit oddly with the first and second; for example, "the choice of career involved in the fourth persona could have been described equally well as the result of the action of the second persona within limits imposed by universal human nature (the first persona) and external circumstances (necessitas or the third persona)" Dyck argues convincingly, however, that all four personae are likely to be from Panaetius (pp. 285-86).
-
(1996)
A Commentary on Cicero, de Officiis
, pp. 285-286
-
-
Dyck, A.R.1
-
13
-
-
79958468480
-
Peace of Mind and Being Yourself
-
36. 7, esp. 4603-8
-
On the individual role, see C. Gill, "Peace of Mind and Being Yourself," ANRW 36. 7 (1994): 4599-640, esp. 4603-8.
-
(1994)
ANRW
, pp. 4599-4640
-
-
Gill, C.1
-
14
-
-
0007366731
-
Personhood and Personality: The Four-Personae Theory in Cicero de Officiis i
-
esp. 180-82
-
See also C. Gill, "Personhood and Personality: The Four-Personae Theory in Cicero De Officiis I," in OSAP 6 (1988): 169-99, esp. 180-82, on some of the different uses to which Cicero and Epictetus put the four-personae theory. I do not agree with Gill that for Cicero, the individual role is that which makes a person distinguished or successful in conventional terms, but I do not thereby accept the only alternative Gill considers, that the individual role is what distinguishes a person from others, or makes him unique. Rather, the individual role seems to me to constitute a person's "type" or particular nature - like the types in Plutarch's Lives or Theophrastus' Characters. There is no suggestion that a person's type would be unique or distinctive, but only that there are different types of people.
-
(1988)
OSAP
, vol.6
, pp. 169-199
-
-
Gill, C.1
-
15
-
-
61349201855
-
Stoic Intermediates and the End for Man
-
ed. A. A. Long (London)
-
On the value of καθήκον τα for guiding the trainee, as well as on the use of the notion of τα κατὰ φύσι ν and praecepta (rules), see I. G. Kidd, "Stoic Intermediates and the End for Man," in Problems in Stoicism, ed. A. A. Long (London, 1971), 150-72.
-
(1971)
Problems in Stoicism
, pp. 150-172
-
-
Kidd, I.G.1
-
16
-
-
61249470854
-
-
I take this translation for προαίρ εσις from R. Dobbin, "Προα ίρεσις in Epictetus "in AncPhil 11 (1991): 111-35.
-
(1991)
Epictetus in AncPhil
, vol.11
, pp. 111-135
-
-
Dobbin, R.1
-
19
-
-
79958454788
-
Self-Respect Reconsidered
-
Cambridge
-
T. Hill argues that self-respect can be a matter of having a personal standard, and not only of valuing one's moral rights as a human being. See T. Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered," in Autonomy and Self-Respect (Cambridge, 1991), 19-24.
-
(1991)
Autonomy and Self-Respect
, pp. 19-24
-
-
Hill, T.1
-
20
-
-
79958402583
-
-
Although in Epictetus, self-respect involves an assessment of oneself as better than the run-of-the-mill person, a high self-assessment is not necessary for self-respect - one could set one's standard at what any human being should expect. On this point, see Taylor, Pride, 76-84.
-
Pride
, pp. 76-84
-
-
Taylor1
-
21
-
-
79958355535
-
By the Gods, It's My One Desire to See an Actual Stoic, Epictetus' Relations with Students and Visitors in His Personal Network
-
On the identity of Epictetus' audience and the character of his interactions with them, see R. F. Hock, "'By the Gods, It's My One Desire to See an Actual Stoic': Epictetus' Relations with Students and Visitors in His Personal Network," Semeia 56 (1991): 121-42. Hock distinguishes two groups among Epictetus' Nicopolis audience: students, usually young and from an aristocratic background with worldly aspirations aplenty, and visitors, both from Nicopolis itself and Rome, also of an aristocratic background. Hock argues that Epictetus fails to compel his audience to adopt his ideal of a practical Stoicism because (1) he rebuffs most of his visitors, (2) his students want only to excel in Stoic doctrine, and are supported in this aspiration both by each other and by their families, outside audience, and others, and (3) the duration of Epictetus' contact with his audience is limited, partly due to (1) and (2). As an objective assessment of the situation in Epictetus' school this may be true, although I am skeptical about the extent to which his students' goals are strictly at cross-purposes with Epictetus (why then not attend another school and spare themselves the insults of Epictetus?). However, my interest here is in what Epictetus thought and did intentionally, not in whether or how he failed.
-
(1991)
Semeia
, vol.56
, pp. 121-142
-
-
Hock, R.F.1
-
22
-
-
0040185612
-
-
London, and 351-52
-
Cf. 2. 8. 11: ε̌χεις τι εcombining comma aboveν σεαυιωcombining dot belowcombining macron μέρος εcombining comma aboveκείνου. By the "god within" or "part of god within," Epictetus seems to mean our reason. Epictetus says that because each of us has within himself this μέρος (part) of god, each of us is an αcombining comma aboveπόσπασμ α (fragment) of god (2. 8. 11; cf. 1. 14. 6). On the "god within" in other Stoics, see E. Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics (London, 1880), 216 and 351-52.
-
(1880)
Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics
, pp. 216
-
-
Zeller, E.1
-
23
-
-
4043133851
-
-
Oxford
-
The ideas that one might be one's own judge, that shame before oneself might set standards for one's conduct and that self-approval might contribute to happiness go back at least to Democritus; see frags. 84, 174, 244, 264. On αιcombining comma aboveδώς in Democritus, see D. L. Cairns, Aidos: The Psychology and Ethics of Honour and Shame in Ancient Greek Literature (Oxford, 1993), 363-70.
-
(1993)
Aidos: The Psychology and Ethics of Honour and Shame in Ancient Greek Literature
, pp. 363-370
-
-
Cairns, D.L.1
-
24
-
-
79958366359
-
-
On the contribution of consciousness of one's character to ευcombining comma aboveθυμία (tranquility) in various Stoic and Epicurean writers, see Gill, "Peace of Mind," 4628-29.
-
Peace of Mind
, pp. 4628-4629
-
-
Gill1
-
26
-
-
79958390185
-
-
London
-
D. R. Dudley, A History of Cynicism from Diogenes to the Sixth Century A. D. (London, 1937), 5. E. g. , D. L. 6. 32, 46, 69. But notice that Diogenes the Cynic is also shown provoking people by asking them, ουcombining comma aboveκ αιcombining comma aboveσχύ νη ("are you not ashamed?") about various aspects of their behavior (D. L. 6. 65). Thanks to A. Long for calling this passage to my attention.
-
(1937)
A History of Cynicism from Diogenes to the Sixth Century A. D.
, pp. 5
-
-
Dudley, D.R.1
|