메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 93, Issue 2, 1998, Pages 136-160

ΑΙΔΩΣ in Epictetus

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 66649118957     PISSN: 0009837X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/449384     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (35)

References (26)
  • 1
    • 0003419754 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, hereafter LS
    • Diogenes Laertius 7. 126, characterizes the Stoic ideal as φρόνιμος, αcombining comma aboveνδρειος, δί καιος, and σώφρ ων; cf. Plutarch De stoicorum repugnantiis 1034c-e [= 61C in The Hellenistic Philosophers, ed. A. A. Long and D. Sedley (Cambridge, 1987), hereafter LS];
    • (1987) The Hellenistic Philosophers
    • Long, A.A.1    Sedley, D.2
  • 2
    • 84875608331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • tr. W. O. Stephens, New York
    • However, Epictetus is not completely alone: as A. Long has pointed out to me, there is an affinity between Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius in the emphasis on the element of self-scrutiny in αιcombining comma aboveδώς (see below, and in Marcus, e. g. , Meditations 2. 6, 3. 6). A. O. Bonhöffer, The Ethics of the Stoic Epictetus, tr. W. O. Stephens (New York, 1996), 30-32, notes but does not really explain Epictetus' avoidance of standard Stoic virtue-terms.
    • (1996) The Ethics of the Stoic Epictetus , pp. 30-32
    • Bonhöffer, A.O.1
  • 4
    • 84880492694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the restriction of good emotions to the wise, see the discussions in Inwood, Ethics, 173-75,
    • Ethics , pp. 173-175
    • Inwood1
  • 6
    • 85163433276 scopus 로고
    • Moral Actions and Rules in Stoic Ethics
    • ed. J. Rist California
    • On this point, see I. G. Kidd, "Moral Actions and Rules in Stoic Ethics," in The Stoics, ed. J. Rist (California, 1978), 247-58.
    • (1978) The Stoics , pp. 247-258
    • Kidd, I.G.1
  • 7
    • 67649847231 scopus 로고
    • Stuttgart
    • See also Bonhöffer's argument that Nemesius cannot be describing true Stoic αιcombining comma aboveδώς, because he does not sufficiently distinguish αιcombining comma aboveδώς from αιcombining comma aboveσχύνη: both are a kind of fear of censure, attendant upon unease about one's conduct and indicative of there being something wrong with it. A. F. Bonhöffer, Epictet und die Stoa (Stuttgart, 1890), 291-93.
    • (1890) Epictet und Die Stoa , pp. 291-293
    • Bonhöffer, A.F.1
  • 8
    • 79958423763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. R. Sorabji
    • It is also possible that some Stoics gave αιcombining comma aboveδώς a double classification - as a passion when felt by the fool and a good emotion when felt by the sage. On double classifications, especially the double classification of εcombining comma abovéρως, see B. Inwood, "Why Do Fools Fall in Love?" forthcoming in Aristotle and After, ed. R. Sorabji.
    • Why Do Fools Fall in Love
    • Inwood, B.1
  • 9
    • 67649397456 scopus 로고
    • Phantasia Kataleptike
    • ed. A. A. Long London
    • This account of cognition follows F. H. Sandbach, "Phantasia Kataleptike," in Problems in Stoicism, ed. A. A. Long (London, 1971), 9-19.
    • (1971) Problems in Stoicism , pp. 9-19
    • Sandbach, F.H.1
  • 11
    • 79958350889 scopus 로고
    • Greek Ethics after MacIntyre
    • A. A. Long, "Greek Ethics After MacIntyre," in AncPhil 3 (1983): 184-97.
    • (1983) AncPhil , vol.3 , pp. 184-197
    • Long, A.A.1
  • 12
    • 5844382825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michigan
    • See A. R. Dyck's A Commentary on Cicero, "De Officiis" (Michigan, 1996), introduction and comments ad loc. , for thorough discussions of the personae-doctrine in Cicero and other writers including Epictetus, as well as for a full treatment of the doctrine's Panaetian source and its anticipations in Aristo of Chios and Bion of Borysthenes. As Dyck notes, the third and fourth personae fit oddly with the first and second; for example, "the choice of career involved in the fourth persona could have been described equally well as the result of the action of the second persona within limits imposed by universal human nature (the first persona) and external circumstances (necessitas or the third persona)" Dyck argues convincingly, however, that all four personae are likely to be from Panaetius (pp. 285-86).
    • (1996) A Commentary on Cicero, de Officiis , pp. 285-286
    • Dyck, A.R.1
  • 13
    • 79958468480 scopus 로고
    • Peace of Mind and Being Yourself
    • 36. 7, esp. 4603-8
    • On the individual role, see C. Gill, "Peace of Mind and Being Yourself," ANRW 36. 7 (1994): 4599-640, esp. 4603-8.
    • (1994) ANRW , pp. 4599-4640
    • Gill, C.1
  • 14
    • 0007366731 scopus 로고
    • Personhood and Personality: The Four-Personae Theory in Cicero de Officiis i
    • esp. 180-82
    • See also C. Gill, "Personhood and Personality: The Four-Personae Theory in Cicero De Officiis I," in OSAP 6 (1988): 169-99, esp. 180-82, on some of the different uses to which Cicero and Epictetus put the four-personae theory. I do not agree with Gill that for Cicero, the individual role is that which makes a person distinguished or successful in conventional terms, but I do not thereby accept the only alternative Gill considers, that the individual role is what distinguishes a person from others, or makes him unique. Rather, the individual role seems to me to constitute a person's "type" or particular nature - like the types in Plutarch's Lives or Theophrastus' Characters. There is no suggestion that a person's type would be unique or distinctive, but only that there are different types of people.
    • (1988) OSAP , vol.6 , pp. 169-199
    • Gill, C.1
  • 15
    • 61349201855 scopus 로고
    • Stoic Intermediates and the End for Man
    • ed. A. A. Long (London)
    • On the value of καθήκον τα for guiding the trainee, as well as on the use of the notion of τα κατὰ φύσι ν and praecepta (rules), see I. G. Kidd, "Stoic Intermediates and the End for Man," in Problems in Stoicism, ed. A. A. Long (London, 1971), 150-72.
    • (1971) Problems in Stoicism , pp. 150-172
    • Kidd, I.G.1
  • 16
    • 61249470854 scopus 로고
    • I take this translation for προαίρ εσις from R. Dobbin, "Προα ίρεσις in Epictetus "in AncPhil 11 (1991): 111-35.
    • (1991) Epictetus in AncPhil , vol.11 , pp. 111-135
    • Dobbin, R.1
  • 19
    • 79958454788 scopus 로고
    • Self-Respect Reconsidered
    • Cambridge
    • T. Hill argues that self-respect can be a matter of having a personal standard, and not only of valuing one's moral rights as a human being. See T. Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered," in Autonomy and Self-Respect (Cambridge, 1991), 19-24.
    • (1991) Autonomy and Self-Respect , pp. 19-24
    • Hill, T.1
  • 20
    • 79958402583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although in Epictetus, self-respect involves an assessment of oneself as better than the run-of-the-mill person, a high self-assessment is not necessary for self-respect - one could set one's standard at what any human being should expect. On this point, see Taylor, Pride, 76-84.
    • Pride , pp. 76-84
    • Taylor1
  • 21
    • 79958355535 scopus 로고
    • By the Gods, It's My One Desire to See an Actual Stoic, Epictetus' Relations with Students and Visitors in His Personal Network
    • On the identity of Epictetus' audience and the character of his interactions with them, see R. F. Hock, "'By the Gods, It's My One Desire to See an Actual Stoic': Epictetus' Relations with Students and Visitors in His Personal Network," Semeia 56 (1991): 121-42. Hock distinguishes two groups among Epictetus' Nicopolis audience: students, usually young and from an aristocratic background with worldly aspirations aplenty, and visitors, both from Nicopolis itself and Rome, also of an aristocratic background. Hock argues that Epictetus fails to compel his audience to adopt his ideal of a practical Stoicism because (1) he rebuffs most of his visitors, (2) his students want only to excel in Stoic doctrine, and are supported in this aspiration both by each other and by their families, outside audience, and others, and (3) the duration of Epictetus' contact with his audience is limited, partly due to (1) and (2). As an objective assessment of the situation in Epictetus' school this may be true, although I am skeptical about the extent to which his students' goals are strictly at cross-purposes with Epictetus (why then not attend another school and spare themselves the insults of Epictetus?). However, my interest here is in what Epictetus thought and did intentionally, not in whether or how he failed.
    • (1991) Semeia , vol.56 , pp. 121-142
    • Hock, R.F.1
  • 22
    • 0040185612 scopus 로고
    • London, and 351-52
    • Cf. 2. 8. 11: ε̌χεις τι εcombining comma aboveν σεαυιωcombining dot belowcombining macron μέρος εcombining comma aboveκείνου. By the "god within" or "part of god within," Epictetus seems to mean our reason. Epictetus says that because each of us has within himself this μέρος (part) of god, each of us is an αcombining comma aboveπόσπασμ α (fragment) of god (2. 8. 11; cf. 1. 14. 6). On the "god within" in other Stoics, see E. Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics (London, 1880), 216 and 351-52.
    • (1880) Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics , pp. 216
    • Zeller, E.1
  • 23
    • 4043133851 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • The ideas that one might be one's own judge, that shame before oneself might set standards for one's conduct and that self-approval might contribute to happiness go back at least to Democritus; see frags. 84, 174, 244, 264. On αιcombining comma aboveδώς in Democritus, see D. L. Cairns, Aidos: The Psychology and Ethics of Honour and Shame in Ancient Greek Literature (Oxford, 1993), 363-70.
    • (1993) Aidos: The Psychology and Ethics of Honour and Shame in Ancient Greek Literature , pp. 363-370
    • Cairns, D.L.1
  • 24
    • 79958366359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the contribution of consciousness of one's character to ευcombining comma aboveθυμία (tranquility) in various Stoic and Epicurean writers, see Gill, "Peace of Mind," 4628-29.
    • Peace of Mind , pp. 4628-4629
    • Gill1
  • 26
    • 79958390185 scopus 로고
    • London
    • D. R. Dudley, A History of Cynicism from Diogenes to the Sixth Century A. D. (London, 1937), 5. E. g. , D. L. 6. 32, 46, 69. But notice that Diogenes the Cynic is also shown provoking people by asking them, ουcombining comma aboveκ αιcombining comma aboveσχύ νη ("are you not ashamed?") about various aspects of their behavior (D. L. 6. 65). Thanks to A. Long for calling this passage to my attention.
    • (1937) A History of Cynicism from Diogenes to the Sixth Century A. D. , pp. 5
    • Dudley, D.R.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.