메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 56, Issue 1, 2006, Pages 1-37

The "permanent deposit" of hegelian thought in dewey's theory of inquiry

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 65249114858     PISSN: 00132004     EISSN: 17415446     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1741-5446.2006.00001.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (25)

References (114)
  • 1
    • 65249158845 scopus 로고
    • The Influence of William James on John Dewey in Psychology
    • For instance, see
    • For instance, see Andrew J. Reck, "The Influence of William James on John Dewey in Psychology," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 20, no. 2 (1984): 87-117;
    • (1984) Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society , vol.20 , Issue.2 , pp. 87-117
    • Reck, A.J.1
  • 2
    • 0015139418 scopus 로고
    • James, Dewey, and the Reflex Arc
    • and D.C. Phillips, "James, Dewey, and the Reflex Arc," Journal of the History of Ideas 32, no. 4 (1971): 555-568.
    • (1971) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.32 , Issue.4 , pp. 555-568
    • Phillips, D.C.1
  • 3
    • 65249131137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Nominalism Versus Realism Debate: Toward a Philosophical Rather Than a Political Resolution
    • For instance, see
    • For instance, see Richard S. Prawat, "The Nominalism Versus Realism Debate: Toward a Philosophical Rather Than a Political Resolution," Educational Theory 53, no. 3 (2003): 275-311.
    • (2003) Educational Theory , vol.53 , Issue.3 , pp. 275-311
    • Prawat, R.S.1
  • 5
    • 65249162522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Thomas C. Dalton, Becoming John Dewey: Dilemmas of a Philosopher and Naturalist (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002). Shook explicitly mentions Andrew Reck and D.C. Phillips as stalwarts of the standard interpretation he wishes to oppose (see Dewey's Empirical Theory, n283). For a review of Dalton's book that both praises the high quality scholarship and bemoans the philosophical weaknesses, see Jim Garrison, Becoming John Dewey, by Thomas C. Dalton, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 39, no. 3 (2003): 520-524.
    • and Thomas C. Dalton, Becoming John Dewey: Dilemmas of a Philosopher and Naturalist (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002). Shook explicitly mentions Andrew Reck and D.C. Phillips as stalwarts of the standard interpretation he wishes to oppose (see Dewey's Empirical Theory, n283). For a review of Dalton's book that both praises the high quality scholarship and bemoans the philosophical weaknesses, see Jim Garrison, "Becoming John Dewey, by Thomas C. Dalton," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 39, no. 3 (2003): 520-524.
  • 6
    • 65249169601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Good's book-length manuscript
    • When this manuscript is published, I believe it will transform Deweyan scholarship. I would like to thank Jim for sharing his manuscript with me
    • Reading James A. Good's book-length manuscript, A Search for Unity in Diversity: Dewey's "Permanent Hegelian Deposit" (currently under contract), also influenced the writing of my essay. When this manuscript is published, I believe it will transform Deweyan scholarship. I would like to thank Jim for sharing his manuscript with me.
    • A Search for Unity in Diversity: Dewey's Permanent Hegelian Deposit
    • Reading James, A.1
  • 7
    • 27144520591 scopus 로고
    • The Philosophy of John Dewey
    • G.H. Mead, "The Philosophy of John Dewey," International Journal of Ethics 46, no. 1 (1935): 69.
    • (1935) International Journal of Ethics , vol.46 , Issue.1 , pp. 69
    • Mead, G.H.1
  • 8
    • 65249086483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Menand argues that Dewey's reflex arc paper is the key to his thought while insisting that it is just biologized Hegel. I agree on both counts.
    • Menand argues that Dewey's reflex arc paper "is the key to his thought" while insisting that it is just "biologized Hegel." I agree on both counts.
  • 9
    • 65249096868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2001) 328, 329.
    • See Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2001) 328, 329.
  • 10
    • 0001031614 scopus 로고
    • From Absolutism to Experimentalism
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, Nowhere in my paper has emphasis been added to citations
    • John Dewey, "From Absolutism to Experimentalism" (1929), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 5, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1984), 154. Nowhere in my paper has emphasis been added to citations.
    • (1929) John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953 , vol.5 , pp. 154
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 11
    • 65249155618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Good identifies many more similarities between Hegel and Dewey, including support for humanistic religion emphasizing moral commitment to civic community, positive freedom, rejection of values as ends in themselves, philosophy as immanent cultural criticism, and the educational concept of bildung, among many other commonalities;
    • Good identifies many more similarities between Hegel and Dewey, including support for humanistic religion emphasizing moral commitment to civic community, positive freedom, rejection of values as ends in themselves, philosophy as immanent cultural criticism, and the educational concept of bildung, among many other commonalities;
  • 12
    • 65249088708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished manuscript, I endorse Good's claims. Dewey also shared Hegel's critique of the atomistic, asocial, historically decontextualized, innately free, and rational liberal individual of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and Immanuel Kant, which is why Dewey's view of the individual and society, including his ideas about democracy, remains poorly understood
    • see Good, A Search for Unity in Diversity (unpublished manuscript). I endorse Good's claims. Dewey also shared Hegel's critique of the atomistic, asocial, historically decontextualized, innately free, and rational liberal individual of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and Immanuel Kant, which is why Dewey's view of the individual and society, including his ideas about democracy, remains poorly understood.
    • A Search for Unity in Diversity
    • see Good1
  • 13
    • 65249093957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While Enlightenment philosophers such as Kant, whom we will discuss later, considered rationality an a historical, innate given, Hegel thought it a cultural and historical creation. Since, on this view, rationality (science, or inquiry) is itself a creation, constrained by ethical considerations, Hegel, along with those whose philosophy he helped shape (such as Dewey, rejected the dualistic separation of art, science, and ethics. Dewey, like Hegel, believed that separating thought from feeling and action was an untenable dualism. See John Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (1922, in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, 14, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1983, 136-137. The crucial idea here is that of Hegelian unity in diversity or identity-in-difference, which Dewey naturalized as functional coordination by relying on biological insights
    • While Enlightenment philosophers such as Kant, whom we will discuss later, considered rationality an a historical, innate given, Hegel thought it a cultural and historical creation. Since, on this view, rationality (science, or inquiry) is itself a creation, constrained by ethical considerations, Hegel, along with those whose philosophy he helped shape (such as Dewey), rejected the dualistic separation of art, science, and ethics. Dewey, like Hegel, believed that separating thought from feeling and action was an untenable dualism. See John Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (1922), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, vol. 14, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1983), 136-137. The crucial idea here is that of Hegelian unity in diversity (or identity-in-difference), which Dewey naturalized as functional coordination by relying on biological insights.
  • 14
    • 0002955924 scopus 로고
    • Experience and Nature
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, Experience and Nature (1925), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 1, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1988), 283.
    • (1988) John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953 , vol.1 , pp. 283
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 16
    • 65249175349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jane Dewey, Biography of John Dewey (1939), in The Philosophy of John Dewey, ed. Paul A. Schilpp (Chicago: Open Court, 1989), 18. Though Jane Dewey prepared this biographical statement, she placed these passages in quotes and attributed them to John Dewey. Here, Dewey also acknowledged Hegel's influence on his theory of the social construction of the mind and self, or what he called social psychology.
    • See Jane Dewey, Biography of John Dewey (1939), in The Philosophy of John Dewey, ed. Paul A. Schilpp (Chicago: Open Court, 1989), 18. Though Jane Dewey prepared this biographical statement, she placed these passages in quotes and attributed them to John Dewey. Here, Dewey also acknowledged Hegel's influence on his theory of the social construction of the mind and self, or what he called "social psychology."
  • 18
    • 0031116194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Dewey, Hegel's Logic (1896 lecture notes), Joseph Ratner Papers and Collection of John Dewey, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois, 10. Cited in Thomas C. Dalton, Dewey's Hegelianism Reconsidered: Reclaiming the Lost Soul of Psychology, New Ideas in Psychology 15, no. 1 (1997): 8.
    • John Dewey, "Hegel's Logic" (1896 lecture notes), Joseph Ratner Papers and Collection of John Dewey, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois, 10. Cited in Thomas C. Dalton, "Dewey's Hegelianism Reconsidered: Reclaiming the Lost Soul of Psychology," New Ideas in Psychology 15, no. 1 (1997): 8.
  • 20
    • 65249154505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At this juncture, Dewey used these observations to reconstruct Hegel's notion of Being, Non-being, and Becoming in terms of selective attention, inattention, and reflection. He concluded that you get something determinate and limited [for example, a thing or a resolved problem] only when you interrupt that process to reflect [that is, inquire] upon it p. 12
    • At this juncture, Dewey used these observations to reconstruct Hegel's notion of Being, Non-being, and Becoming in terms of selective attention, inattention, and reflection. He concluded that "you get something determinate and limited [for example, a thing or a resolved problem] only when you interrupt that process to reflect [that is, inquire] upon it" (p. 12).
  • 21
    • 65249092799 scopus 로고
    • Kant and Philosophic Method
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, "Kant and Philosophic Method" (1884), in John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898, vol. 1, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967), 42.
    • (1884) John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898 , vol.1 , pp. 42
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 25
    • 0010918761 scopus 로고
    • Psychology
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, Psychology (1887), in John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898, vol. 2, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967), 177.
    • (1967) John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898 , vol.2 , pp. 177
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 26
    • 65249150449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He added that Meaning is always universal. This work will be cited as DP in the text for all subsequent references.
    • He added that "Meaning is always universal." This work will be cited as DP in the text for all subsequent references.
  • 27
    • 65249122189 scopus 로고
    • How Do Concepts Arise from Percepts?
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, "How Do Concepts Arise from Percepts?" (1891), in John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898, vol. 3, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1969), 143-144.
    • (1891) John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898 , vol.3 , pp. 143-144
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 29
    • 65249088709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This paper appeared in a pedagogical journal, and Dewey interrupted his exposition to assert that the example proves the impossibility of external or mechanical instruction 144, Today, we would call this constructivism
    • This paper appeared in a pedagogical journal, and Dewey interrupted his exposition to assert that the example proves the impossibility of "external or mechanical instruction" (144). Today, we would call this constructivism.
  • 31
    • 65249189840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the pages that follow, I will identify in Dewey a logical sense of knowledge as the completely definite and distinct end of inquiry that is compatible with an interpretation of Hegel's Absolute and that does not associate it with the metaphysical end of history
    • In the pages that follow, I will identify in Dewey a logical sense of knowledge as the completely definite and distinct end of inquiry that is compatible with an interpretation of Hegel's Absolute and that does not associate it with the metaphysical end of history.
  • 32
    • 65249186961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Dewey, induction and deduction are just phases of a single method; hence, they will be called one or the other from the aspect that predominates at any moment in the inquiry (DP, 198).
    • According to Dewey, induction and deduction are just phases of a single method; hence, they "will be called one or the other from the aspect that predominates" at any moment in the inquiry (DP, 198).
  • 33
    • 10844235721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Jon Stewart, ed, Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press
    • See, for example, Jon Stewart, ed., The Hegel Myths and Legends (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) The Hegel Myths and Legends
  • 34
    • 65249111850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I would like to thank Jim Good for helping work out connections between Hegel's Absolute and Dewey's notion of distinct and definite knowledge as the ultimate goal of inquiry, as well as many other topics. Jim is not responsible for any of my lingering confusions
    • I would like to thank Jim Good for helping work out connections between Hegel's Absolute and Dewey's notion of distinct and definite knowledge as the ultimate goal of inquiry, as well as many other topics. Jim is not responsible for any of my lingering confusions.
  • 36
    • 65249107862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I borrow the title of this section from chapter 1 of Robert B. Westbrook's John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991).
    • I borrow the title of this section from chapter 1 of Robert B. Westbrook's John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991).
  • 37
    • 0037489945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My own sense is that Dewey separated himself more from the neo-Hegelian Absolute of his contemporaries than from Hegel's notion of the Absolute as definite and distinct knowledge
    • Shook, Dewey's Empirical Theory of Knowledge and Reality, 215. My own sense is that Dewey separated himself more from the neo-Hegelian Absolute of his contemporaries than from Hegel's notion of the Absolute as definite and distinct knowledge.
    • Dewey's Empirical Theory of Knowledge and Reality , pp. 215
    • Shook1
  • 38
    • 65249181094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., chap. 3. In his manuscript, Jim Good makes much of the fact that Hegel abandoned faculty psychology and argued that the mind emerges through interaction with the environment. Good argues, convincingly I think, that this insight led Hegel to a rudimentary functional psychology that Dewey emulated from the beginning.
    • Ibid., chap. 3. In his manuscript, Jim Good makes much of the fact that Hegel abandoned faculty psychology and argued that the mind emerges through interaction with the environment. Good argues, convincingly I think, that this insight led Hegel to a rudimentary functional psychology that Dewey emulated from the beginning.
  • 39
    • 0141625556 scopus 로고
    • See Stephen Priest, ed, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See Stephen Priest, ed., Hegel's Critique of Kant (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).
    • (1987) Hegel's Critique of Kant
  • 40
    • 79958539960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatic Aspects of Hegel's Thought
    • See, Albany: SUNY Press
    • See Antje Gimmler, "Pragmatic Aspects of Hegel's Thought," in The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy (Albany: SUNY Press, 2004), 47-66.
    • (2004) The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy , pp. 47-66
    • Gimmler, A.1
  • 41
    • 65249143591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hegel developed speculative reason to reconcile the opposites found in Kant's antinomies of pure reason, especially the third antinomy. In his foreword to Phenomenology of Spirit, J.N. Findlay writes that Hegel's concern is always with the Begriff or universal notional shapes that are evinced in fact and history.a single all-inclusive universal or concept. See G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans.A.V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), vii.
    • Hegel developed speculative reason to reconcile the opposites found in Kant's antinomies of pure reason, especially the third antinomy. In his foreword to Phenomenology of Spirit, J.N. Findlay writes that Hegel's "concern is always with the Begriff or universal notional shapes that are evinced in fact and history.a single all-inclusive universal or concept." See G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans.A.V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), vii.
  • 43
    • 3042860261 scopus 로고
    • The Hegel Legend of 'Thesis-Antithesis-Synthesis'
    • See, ed, Stewart Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press
    • See G.E. Mueller, "The Hegel Legend of 'Thesis-Antithesis-Synthesis' " (1958), in The Hegel Myths and Legends, ed. Jon Stewart (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996), 301-305.
    • (1958) The Hegel Myths and Legends , pp. 301-305
    • Mueller, G.E.1
  • 44
    • 84868923590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So well known is this fact among Hegel scholars that Chalybäus is even mentioned in the entry for Hegel in The Cambridge Dictionary Of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 315.
    • So well known is this fact among Hegel scholars that Chalybäus is even mentioned in the entry for "Hegel" in The Cambridge Dictionary Of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 315.
  • 45
    • 84868924504 scopus 로고
    • Allen Wood has observed that The use of Chalybäus's terminology to expound the Hegelian dialectic is nearly always an unwitting confession that the expositor has little or no firsthand knowledge of Hegel. See, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Allen Wood has observed that "The use of Chalybäus's terminology to expound the Hegelian dialectic is nearly always an unwitting confession that the expositor has little or no firsthand knowledge of Hegel." See Allen W. Wood, Hegel's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 4.
    • (1990) Hegel's Ethical Thought , pp. 4
    • Wood, A.W.1
  • 46
    • 0011653717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hegel's Science of Logic
    • See, trans. A.V. Miller, Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press International
    • See G.W.F. Hegel, Hegel's Science of Logic, trans. A.V. Miller (1812; repr. Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press International, 1969), 775-823.
    • (1969) 1812; repr , pp. 775-823
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 47
    • 65249169598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the translator's preface, Miller mentions that he always translates Hegel's Begriff as Notion. This work will be cited as HSL in the text for all subsequent references
    • In the translator's preface, Miller mentions that he always translates Hegel's "Begriff" as "Notion." This work will be cited as HSL in the text for all subsequent references.
  • 48
    • 65249114974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more on analytic cognition, including empirical science, see 786-793
    • For more on analytic cognition, including empirical science, see 786-793.
  • 49
    • 65249170547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Hegel, even in empirical science, the problem remains the fact that every determination and connexion is something external (HSL, 790).
    • According to Hegel, even in empirical science, the problem remains the fact that "every determination and connexion is something external" (HSL, 790).
  • 51
    • 65249141899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Dewey, Contributions to Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology (1902), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, 2, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1978), 225. This work will be cited as DPP in the text for all subsequent references.
    • John Dewey, "Contributions to Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology" (1902), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, vol. 2, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1978), 225. This work will be cited as DPP in the text for all subsequent references.
  • 52
    • 65249088187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dewey referred readers to the dictionary entry under pragmatic at the start of his exposition of this position
    • Dewey referred readers to the dictionary entry under " pragmatic" at the start of his exposition of this position.
  • 53
    • 65249099242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anyone who reads Hegel's chapter on Teleology in the Science of Logic and recognizes its crucial role in the architectonic of that work will realize that converting identity-in-difference into the mean sends function is not that difficult.
    • Anyone who reads Hegel's chapter on "Teleology" in the Science of Logic and recognizes its crucial role in the architectonic of that work will realize that converting identity-in-difference into the mean sends function is not that difficult.
  • 54
    • 65249148765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, 12, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), 17. This work will be cited as LTI in the text for all subsequent references.
    • John Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 12, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), 17. This work will be cited as LTI in the text for all subsequent references.
  • 55
    • 65249175352 scopus 로고
    • eds. Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel Bloomington: Indiana University Press
    • Charles Sanders Peirce, The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings, vol. 1, eds. Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1992), 87.
    • (1992) The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings , vol.1 , pp. 87
    • Sanders Peirce, C.1
  • 56
    • 65249091661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nathan Houser's introduction to The Essential Peirce, 1, is preoccupied with the tensions between Peirce's realism and idealism, but leaves it to the reader to resolve the conflict.
    • Nathan Houser's introduction to The Essential Peirce, vol.1, is preoccupied with the tensions between Peirce's realism and idealism, but leaves it to the reader to resolve the conflict.
  • 59
    • 0003891643 scopus 로고
    • See, repr. New York: Dover, 473
    • See William James, The Principles of Psychology, vol. 1 (1890; repr. New York: Dover, 1950), 473.
    • (1890) The Principles of Psychology , vol.1
    • James, W.1
  • 60
    • 65249103620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Dewey, What Are Universals? (1938), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, 11, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1987), 112. This work will be cited as WAU in the text for all subsequent references.
    • John Dewey, "What Are Universals?" (1938), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 11, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1987), 112. This work will be cited as WAU in the text for all subsequent references.
  • 63
    • 65249177467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By contrast, the thesis that Dewey was a Scotistic realist has been advanced by Prawat in The Nominalism Versus Realism Debate.
    • By contrast, the thesis that Dewey was a Scotistic realist has been advanced by Prawat in "The Nominalism Versus Realism Debate."
  • 64
    • 26644472412 scopus 로고
    • Art as Experience
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, Art as Experience (1934), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 10, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1989), 338.
    • (1989) John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953 , vol.10 , pp. 338
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 65
    • 65249085852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Dewey, How We Think (1910), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, 6, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1980), 242. This work will be cited as HWT in the text for all subsequent references.
    • John Dewey, How We Think (1910), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, vol. 6, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1980), 242. This work will be cited as HWT in the text for all subsequent references.
  • 68
    • 0040468042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction to Essays in Experimental Logic
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, "Introduction to Essays in Experimental Logic" (1916), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, vol. 10, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1980), 242.
    • (1980) John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924 , vol.10 , pp. 242
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 69
    • 65249130238 scopus 로고
    • Characteristics and Characters: Kinds and Classes
    • ed. Boydston
    • John Dewey, "Characteristics and Characters: Kinds and Classes" (1938), in John Dewey: The Later Works, vol. 11, ed. Boydston, 97.
    • (1938) John Dewey: The Later Works , vol.11 , pp. 97
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 70
    • 65249122802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recall that Hegel considered experimental variation a part of analysis
    • Recall that Hegel considered experimental variation a part of analysis.
  • 73
    • 0008387742 scopus 로고
    • Contributions to A Cyclopedia of Education, vols. 1 and 2
    • ed, 371
    • John Dewey, "Contributions to A Cyclopedia of Education, vols. 1 and 2" (1911), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, vol. 6, ed. Boydston, 371.
    • (1911) John Dewey: The Middle Works , vol.6
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 76
    • 65249089379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many of the revisions in the later version of How We Think seem designed to allay the false impression of linear steps or a predetermined, fixed method of any kind. The formation of every individual judgment is unique, and we can only know the precise method after the fact.
    • Many of the revisions in the later version of How We Think seem designed to allay the false impression of linear steps or a predetermined, fixed method of any kind. The formation of every individual judgment is unique, and we can only know the precise method after the fact.
  • 77
    • 2442632058 scopus 로고
    • An Analysis of Reflective Thought
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, and
    • John Dewey, "An Analysis of Reflective Thought" (1922), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, vol. 13, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1988), 62 and 63.
    • (1922) John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924 , vol.13 , pp. 62-63
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 81
  • 82
    • 65249120457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Dewey's distinction between concrete, particular existential inference and abstract, universal logical implication, see LTI
    • For Dewey's distinction between concrete, particular existential inference and abstract, universal logical implication, see LTI, 60.
    • , vol.60
  • 85
    • 65249091662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This late statement is compatible with the instrumentalism Dewey first formulated fully in 1903
    • This late statement is compatible with the instrumentalism Dewey first formulated fully in 1903.
  • 87
    • 65249102480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dewey provided an aesthetic definition of inquiry that understands the conclusion of inquiry as a beautiful form expressing unity in diversity of constituent distinctions
    • Dewey provided an aesthetic definition of inquiry that understands the conclusion of inquiry as a beautiful form expressing unity in diversity (of constituent distinctions).
  • 88
    • 65249190482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a footnote Dewey did mention the operations of experimental analysis which determine qualities as traits of a definitive kind and that the point has important bearings upon the theory of induction, as pointed out later see LTI, chap. 21, Chapter 21 is the chapter on induction and deduction that we have been discussing
    • In a footnote Dewey did mention the "operations of experimental analysis which determine qualities as traits of a definitive kind" and that the "point has important bearings upon the theory of induction, as pointed out later" (see LTI, chap. 21.) Chapter 21 is the chapter on induction and deduction that we have been discussing.
  • 89
    • 0347898032 scopus 로고
    • Experience and Education
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, Experience and Education (1938), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 13, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1988), 56-57.
    • (1988) John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953 , vol.13 , pp. 56-57
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 91
    • 65249148141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Dewey, The Superstition of Necessity (1893), in John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898, 4, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1971), 29. This work will be cited as SN in the text for all subsequent references.
    • John Dewey, "The Superstition of Necessity" (1893), in John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898, vol. 4, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1971), 29. This work will be cited as SN in the text for all subsequent references.
  • 92
    • 65249139649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elsewhere in the paper, he made the now familiar observation that objects, as known, are not independent of the process of knowing, but are the content of our judgments (SN, 21).
    • Elsewhere in the paper, he made the now familiar observation that "objects, as known, are not independent of the process of knowing, but are the content of our judgments" (SN, 21).
  • 95
    • 65249167779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peirce's book review and his letters to Dewey in Charles Sanders Peirce, The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, 8, ed. Arthur W. Burks (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958), 188-190 and 239-244, respectively.
    • See Peirce's book review and his letters to Dewey in Charles Sanders Peirce, The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. 8, ed. Arthur W. Burks (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958), 188-190 and 239-244, respectively.
  • 97
    • 65249157524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Added Note as to the 'Practical
    • ed, Notice that this is a constructivist account of knowing
    • John Dewey, "An Added Note as to the 'Practical' in Essays in Experimental Logic" (1916), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, vol. 10, ed. Boydston, 368-369. Notice that this is a constructivist account of knowing.
    • Essays in Experimental Logic (1916), in John Dewey: The Middle Works , vol.10 , pp. 368-369
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 100
    • 0039626213 scopus 로고
    • The Logic of Judgments of Practice
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, "The Logic of Judgments of Practice" (1915), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, vol. 8, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1979), 37.
    • (1915) John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924 , vol.8 , pp. 37
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 101
    • 65249154506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also LTI
    • See also LTI.
  • 102
    • 65249103016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • eds. Houser and Kloesel
    • Peirce, The Essential Peirce, vol. 2, eds. Houser and Kloesel, 345.
    • The Essential Peirce , vol.2 , pp. 345
    • Peirce1
  • 103
    • 2942518095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • eds. Houser and Kloesel
    • Peirce, The Essential Peirce, vol. 1, eds. Houser and Kloesel, 139.
    • The Essential Peirce , vol.1 , pp. 139
    • Peirce1
  • 104
    • 18044367634 scopus 로고
    • The Inclusive Philosophic Idea
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, "The Inclusive Philosophic Idea" (1928), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 3, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1984), 41-54.
    • (1928) John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953 , vol.3 , pp. 41-54
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 105
    • 65249183568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Just as Jim Good helped me see how likely it is that Hegel was not telling an end of history story, conversations with Vincent Colapietro helped me see that Peirce was probably not telling an end of history story either. As with Jim, Vincent is not responsible for any of my lingering confusions
    • Just as Jim Good helped me see how likely it is that Hegel was not telling an end of history story, conversations with Vincent Colapietro helped me see that Peirce was probably not telling an end of history story either. As with Jim, Vincent is not responsible for any of my lingering confusions.
  • 106
    • 0003372408 scopus 로고
    • The Reflex Arc Concept
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, "The Reflex Arc Concept" (1896), in John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898, vol. 5, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1972), 96-109.
    • (1896) John Dewey: The Early Works, 1882-1898 , vol.5 , pp. 96-109
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 107
    • 65249089378 scopus 로고
    • The Influence of William James on John Dewey's Early Work
    • I urge those interested in the details to consult Buxton, and Backe along with the work of Shook and Dalton. See
    • I urge those interested in the details to consult Buxton, and Backe along with the work of Shook and Dalton. See Michael Buxton, "The Influence of William James on John Dewey's Early Work," Journal of the History of Ideas 45, no. 3 (1984): 451-463;
    • (1984) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.45 , Issue.3 , pp. 451-463
    • Buxton, M.1
  • 108
    • 0041062079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dewey and the Reflex Arc: The Limits of James' Influence
    • Andrew Backe, "Dewey and the Reflex Arc: The Limits of James' Influence," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 35, no. 2 (1999): 312-326;
    • (1999) Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society , vol.35 , Issue.2 , pp. 312-326
    • Backe, A.1
  • 109
    • 0035515363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Dewey and Early Chicago Functionalism
    • and Andrew Backe, "John Dewey and Early Chicago Functionalism," History of Psychology 4, no. 4 (2001): 323-340.
    • (2001) History of Psychology , vol.4 , Issue.4 , pp. 323-340
    • Backe, A.1
  • 110
    • 65249129416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dewey's Empirical Theory of Knowledge and Reality, and Dalton
    • See also
    • See also Shook, Dewey's Empirical Theory of Knowledge and Reality, and Dalton, Becoming John Dewey.
    • Becoming John Dewey
    • Shook1
  • 111
    • 65249183569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Personally, I do think reading Peirce even before 1915 was useful for Dewey, although not quite for the reasons Prawat provides or to the extent that he proclaims.
    • Personally, I do think reading Peirce even before 1915 was useful for Dewey, although not quite for the reasons Prawat provides or to the extent that he proclaims.
  • 112
    • 84868930620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prawat, The Nominalism Versus Realism Debate, 298. It seems that Prawat mistakenly attributes this passage to Dewey, when in fact it is a reference to a paper written by Hugo Mü nsterberg. Dewey actually rejected Mü nsterberg's methodology;
    • Prawat, "The Nominalism Versus Realism Debate," 298. It seems that Prawat mistakenly attributes this passage to Dewey, when in fact it is a reference to a paper written by Hugo Mü nsterberg. Dewey actually rejected Mü nsterberg's methodology;
  • 113
    • 65249115519 scopus 로고
    • Ethics
    • see, ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • see John Dewey, Ethics (1908), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, vol. 3, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1977),145-150.
    • (1977) John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924 , vol.3 , pp. 145-150
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 114
    • 65249158210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Further, a CD-ROM search of the critical edition of Dewey's Collected Works using the intersection of synthesis, analysis, and James yielded no hits. I also tried James's along with other combinations. I found nothing to indicate that Dewey even once referred directly to James's discussion of analysis and synthesis, though there are some references to analysis. On the other hand, there were multiple hits at the intersection of synthesis, analysis, and Hegel.
    • Further, a CD-ROM search of the critical edition of Dewey's Collected Works using the intersection of "synthesis," "analysis," and "James" yielded no hits. I also tried "James's" along with other combinations. I found nothing to indicate that Dewey even once referred directly to James's discussion of analysis and synthesis, though there are some references to analysis. On the other hand, there were multiple hits at the intersection of "synthesis," "analysis," and "Hegel."


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.