메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 3, 2009, Pages 233-260

On content-independent reasons: It's not in the name

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 64049103396     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/s10982-008-9037-7     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (24)

References (60)
  • 1
    • 64049108164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He first coined the term in a discussion of promises. Hart, H.L.A., 'Legal and Moral Obligation', in A.I. Melden (ed.), Essays in Moral Philosophy (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1958), p. 102.
    • He first coined the term in a discussion of promises. Hart, H.L.A., 'Legal and Moral Obligation', in A.I. Melden (ed.), Essays in Moral Philosophy (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1958), p. 102.
  • 2
    • 0004294163 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Hart, H.L.A., Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), pp. 254-255.
    • (1982) Essays on Bentham , pp. 254-255
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 3
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • See, for example, New York: Clarendon Press
    • See, for example, Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (New York: Clarendon Press, 1986);
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom
    • Raz, J.1
  • 4
    • 0004048651 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: The Clarendon Press of Oxford University Press
    • Green, Leslie, The Authority of the State (Oxford: The Clarendon Press of Oxford University Press, 1988);
    • (1988) The Authority of the State
    • Green, L.1
  • 7
    • 0039631953 scopus 로고
    • Authority, Law, and Morality
    • Raz, 'Authority, Law, and Morality', The Monist 68 (1985): 295-324,
    • (1985) The Monist , vol.68 , pp. 295-324
    • Raz1
  • 8
    • 64049117607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • republished in Raz, Ethics and the Public Domain (New York: Oxford University Press).
    • republished in Raz, Ethics and the Public Domain (New York: Oxford University Press).
  • 9
    • 64049104473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Hart's Way Out
    • See also, ed, Postcript: Essays on the Postscript to the Concept of Law New York: Oxford University Press
    • See also Shapiro, 'On Hart's Way Out' in Jules Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postcript: Essays on the Postscript to the Concept of Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (2001) Hart's
    • Shapiro1
  • 10
    • 64049111461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart (1958), p. 102;
    • See Hart (1958), p. 102;
  • 11
    • 64049095489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart 1982, pp. 254-255;
    • Hart (1982), pp. 254-255;
  • 12
    • 64049099705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1986, pp. 35-37;
    • Raz (1986), pp. 35-37;
  • 13
    • 64049114377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green 1988, pp. 40-41
    • Green (1988), pp. 40-41,
  • 15
    • 64049085974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Labels truer to this underlying Gricean idea are natural (content-dependent) and non-natural (content-independent) reasons
    • Labels truer to this underlying Gricean idea are natural (content-dependent) and non-natural (content-independent) reasons.
  • 16
    • 84860552002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Obligation and Authority
    • Edward N. Zalta ed, Spring 2004 Edition
    • Green, Leslie, 'Legal Obligation and Authority', in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2004 Edition), http://plato.Stanford.edu/archives/spr2004/entries/legal-obligation/.
    • The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Green, L.1
  • 17
    • 64049115541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I would like to thank an anonymous referee for pressing me to clarify this point
    • I would like to thank an anonymous referee for pressing me to clarify this point.
  • 18
    • 64049087468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shapiro 2002, p. 389
    • Shapiro (2002), p. 389.
  • 19
    • 64049107360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition to the conception of content-dependent reasons quoted above, Shapiro also provides a conception of content-independent reasons: [T]hey are supposed to be reasons simply because they have been issued and not because they direct subjects to perform actions that are independently justifiable. Ibid, p. 389. Thus, Shapiro defines the class of content-independent and the class of content-dependent reasons independently of one another. This is a risky strategy because a successful account of the distinction between these two kinds of reasons must describe two mutually exclusive classes of reasons. The present example shows that Shapiro's distinction is not successful in this respect. The captain's command to swab the deck is a reason to swab the deck, both because it has been issued and because it has a certain content. Were Shapiro to abandon his independent conception of content-dependent reasons and cast the distinction as one between content-independent rea
    • In addition to the conception of content-dependent reasons quoted above, Shapiro also provides a conception of content-independent reasons: "[T]hey are supposed to be reasons simply because they have been issued and not because they direct subjects to perform actions that are independently justifiable." Ibid., p. 389. Thus, Shapiro defines the class of content-independent and the class of content-dependent reasons independently of one another. This is a risky strategy because a successful account of the distinction between these two kinds of reasons must describe two mutually exclusive classes of reasons. The present example shows that Shapiro's distinction is not successful in this respect. The captain's command to swab the deck is a reason to swab the deck, both because it has been issued and because it has a certain content. Were Shapiro to abandon his independent conception of content-dependent reasons and cast the distinction as one between content-independent reasons that are reasons because they have been issued and all other reasons, his distinction might be similar to the Gricean distinction I defend. However, like the Gricean distinction, Shapiro's distinction in this case would not be content-based. Thanks again to the anonymous referee who pressed me to clarify this point.
  • 20
    • 27744607286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law and Content-Independent Reasons
    • Markwick, 'Law and Content-Independent Reasons', Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20 (2000): 579-96.
    • (2000) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.20 , pp. 579-596
    • Markwick1
  • 21
    • 64049092519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Someone might object that this example fails to satisfy Markwick's formulation only because it does not adequately characterize the paradigmatic content-independent reason in question. On this objection, the proper characterization that satisfies Markwick's formulation is as follows: a captain acting within his legitimate authority commands it. This, however, would be a cheat because legitimate authority on the standard account is defined in terms of content-independent reasons. A is a legitimate authority with respect to S only if A provides S with content-independent reasons. See, e.g., Raz (1986),
    • Someone might object that this example fails to satisfy Markwick's formulation only because it does not adequately characterize the paradigmatic content-independent reason in question. On this objection, the proper characterization that satisfies Markwick's formulation is as follows: a captain acting within his legitimate authority commands it. This, however, would be a cheat because legitimate authority on the standard account is defined in terms of content-independent reasons. A is a legitimate authority with respect to S only if A provides S with content-independent reasons. See, e.g., Raz (1986),
  • 22
    • 64049088680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green 2004
    • Green (2004),
  • 23
    • 48349092160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Authority
    • Edward Zalta ed, Fall 2004 Edition
    • and Thomas Christiano 'Authority', in Edward Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2004 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/fall2004/entries/authority/.
    • The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Christiano, T.1
  • 24
    • 64049093965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart (1958) for an expression of this view with respect to promises.
    • See Hart (1958) for an expression of this view with respect to promises.
  • 26
    • 64049098369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I would argue that we should extend this same reasoning to egregiously immoral commands or requests
    • I would argue that we should extend this same reasoning to egregiously immoral commands or requests.
  • 27
    • 64049092715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1986, p. 35
    • Raz (1986), p. 35.
  • 28
    • 64049094734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interestingly, Raz, like Hart, suggests a Gricean rather than a content-based conception of content-independent reasons when discussing specific examples of such reasons, yet stops short of describing such reasons in terms of Gricean intentions. See, e.g., Raz's account of why requests provide content-independent reasons. But the specific quality of requests is that they are acts intended to communicate to their addressee the speaker's intention that the addressee shall regard the act of communication as a reason for a certain action.
    • Interestingly, Raz, like Hart, suggests a Gricean rather than a content-based conception of content-independent reasons when discussing specific examples of such reasons, yet stops short of describing such reasons in terms of Gricean intentions. See, e.g., Raz's account of why requests provide content-independent reasons. "But the specific quality of requests is that they are acts intended to communicate to their addressee the speaker's intention that the addressee shall regard the act of communication as a reason for a certain action."
  • 29
    • 64049098557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 37.
  • 30
    • 64049083962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might argue that Raz intends for his normal justification thesis to distinguish direct (content-dependent) reasons from indirect (content-independent) reasons. That is, a putative authority provides a subject with content-independent reason if and only if the putative authority satisfies the normal justification thesis with respect to the subject. See infra no. 32 and accompanying text for a discussion of the normal justification thesis. However, Raz cannot think this for he holds both that requests are sources of content-independent reasons and that requests characteristically do not satisfy the normal justification thesis. See, Ibid., p. 37.
    • One might argue that Raz intends for his normal justification thesis to distinguish direct (content-dependent) reasons from indirect (content-independent) reasons. That is, a putative authority provides a subject with content-independent reason if and only if the putative authority satisfies the normal justification thesis with respect to the subject. See infra no. 32 and accompanying text for a discussion of the normal justification thesis. However, Raz cannot think this for he holds both that requests are sources of content-independent reasons and that requests characteristically do not satisfy the normal justification thesis. See, Ibid., p. 37.
  • 32
    • 64049092136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1986, p. 37
    • Raz (1986), p. 37.
  • 33
    • 64049117816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This account of Grice borrows from Rovane, Carol, The Bounds of Agency Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998, p. 149
    • This account of Grice borrows from Rovane, Carol, The Bounds of Agency (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998), p. 149.
  • 34
    • 64049104047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart (1982), p. 251. Here, Hart cites to Grice's analysis of non-natural meaning.
    • See Hart (1982), p. 251. Here, Hart cites to Grice's analysis of non-natural meaning.
  • 35
    • 64049084910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 36
    • 64049100256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 254.
  • 37
    • 64049103685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz similarly makes these observations without linking them. See supra no. 17.
    • Raz similarly makes these observations without linking them. See supra no. 17.
  • 39
    • 64049096802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Given that intentions can also serve as reasons for forming yet further intentions, we could add a third category of content-independent reasons. In addition to content-independent reasons for action and belief, there are also content-independent reasons for adopting further intentions. Anything I say below about content-independent reasons for action should also apply to content-independent reason for adopting further intentions
    • Given that intentions can also serve as reasons for forming yet further intentions, we could add a third category of content-independent reasons. In addition to content-independent reasons for action and belief, there are also content-independent reasons for adopting further intentions. Anything I say below about content-independent reasons for action should also apply to content-independent reason for adopting further intentions.
  • 40
    • 64049087888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Roveane (1998), p. 149. Note also that when X and Y are one and the same, X's present intentions do not provide reasons for Y to perform the corresponding actions. Rather, X/Y performs the action with the present intention of performing the action.
    • Cf. Roveane (1998), p. 149. Note also that when X and Y are one and the same, X's present intentions do not provide reasons for Y to perform the corresponding actions. Rather, X/Y performs the action with the present intention of performing the action.
  • 41
    • 84921973045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of enablers as applied to reasons, see, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ch. 3
    • For a discussion of enablers as applied to reasons, see Dancy, Jonathan Ethics without Principles (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), ch. 3.
    • (2004) Ethics without Principles
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 42
    • 64049117037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They also enable and disable fellow enablers and disablers
    • They also enable and disable fellow enablers and disablers.
  • 43
    • 64049108163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rovane (1998), pp. 152-53.
    • See Rovane (1998), pp. 152-53.
  • 44
    • 64049101035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1986, p. 53ff
    • Raz (1986), p. 53ff.
  • 45
    • 64049091351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I assume that a consideration is a reason for believing a proposition only if it is evidence of the truth of the proposition. One might reject this assumption. For example, one might hold that one has reason to believe propositions that it is useful for one to believe irrespective of the useful proposition's truth. The reader who rejects this assumption might think that there are non-epistemic enabling conditions of content-independent reasons for belief
    • I assume that a consideration is a reason for believing a proposition only if it is evidence of the truth of the proposition. One might reject this assumption. For example, one might hold that one has reason to believe propositions that it is useful for one to believe irrespective of the useful proposition's truth. The reader who rejects this assumption might think that there are non-epistemic enabling conditions of content-independent reasons for belief.
  • 46
    • 64049119180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Authority of Democracy' (2004), Waldron, Jeremy
    • See, New York: Oxford University Press
    • See Christiano, 'The Authority of Democracy' (2004), Waldron, Jeremy Law and Disagreement (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002),
    • (2002) Law and Disagreement
    • Christiano1
  • 47
    • 0002161865 scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy
    • and, eds, New York: Basil Blackwell for arguments of this sort
    • and Cohen, Joshua, 'Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy' in Alan Hamlin and Philip Pettit (eds.), The Good Polity (New York: Basil Blackwell for arguments of this sort, 1989).
    • (1989) The Good Polity
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 48
    • 64049116861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart 1982
    • See Hart (1982).
  • 49
    • 64049100828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Raz and Green's similar conceptions of authority that hold that a legitimate authority provides its subjects with content-independent and exclusionary reasons. Raz (1986) and Green (1988).
    • Cf. Raz and Green's similar conceptions of authority that hold that a legitimate authority provides its subjects with content-independent and exclusionary reasons. Raz (1986) and Green (1988).
  • 50
    • 64049105033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1986, p. 35
    • Raz (1986), p. 35
  • 51
    • 64049114177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Hart 1958
    • and Hart (1958).
  • 52
    • 64049097370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra no. 28 and accompanying text.
    • See supra no. 28 and accompanying text.
  • 53
    • 64049083186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons's view of consent seems to be an account of the normative force of acts of consent based in a conception of the natural freedom of persons to bind themselves to obligations to others. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), p. 62ff. This logic readily extends to promises.
    • Simmons's view of consent seems to be an account of the normative force of acts of consent based in a conception of the natural freedom of persons to bind themselves to obligations to others. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), p. 62ff. This logic readily extends to promises.
  • 54
    • 64049089670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hume's A Treatise of Human Nature, bk. III, pt. II, ch. V;
    • See Hume's A Treatise of Human Nature, bk. III, pt. II, ch. V;
  • 55
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 344-350
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 344-350
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 56
    • 64049113798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Hart (1958) for conventionalist views of the normative force of promise-keeping.
    • and Hart (1958) for conventionalist views of the normative force of promise-keeping.
  • 57
    • 64049111062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz (1986), pp. 35-36
    • See Raz (1986), pp. 35-36
  • 58
    • 64049110356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Green (1988), p. 27ff.
    • and Green (1988), p. 27ff.
  • 59
    • 64049116667 scopus 로고
    • Cf. Raz (1986), pp. 35-36, 52-53
    • (1986)
    • Raz, C.1
  • 60
    • 64049116121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Green (1988), p. 27ff. They hold that advice provides only content-independent reasons for belief.
    • and Green (1988), p. 27ff. They hold that advice provides only content-independent reasons for belief.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.