-
1
-
-
0004236942
-
-
For an example of a pragmatism-driven critique of metaphysical realism (defined, roughly, as the view that the world possesses its own ultimate ontological structure which human beliefs or theories are meant to accurately represent), see Hilary Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, ed. James Conant (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 1990)
-
(1990)
Realism with a Human Face
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
5
-
-
0018952721
-
Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology
-
Jerry A. Fodor, "Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology," The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1980): 63-73
-
(1980)
The Behavioral and Brain Sciences
, vol.3
, pp. 63-73
-
-
Fodor, J.A.1
-
6
-
-
0013465728
-
-
For critical discussions, see especially Hilary Putnam, Realism and Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983)
-
(1983)
Realism and Reason
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
7
-
-
0004069098
-
-
ed. James Conant Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press
-
and Putnam, Words and Life, ed. James Conant (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 1994)
-
(1994)
Words and Life
-
-
Putnam1
-
8
-
-
61449157450
-
Two Kinds of Methodological Solipsism
-
Cf. further Sami Pihlström, "Two Kinds of Methodological Solipsism," Sats 1 (2000): 73-90
-
(2000)
Sats
, vol.1
, pp. 73-90
-
-
Pihlström, S.1
-
9
-
-
0036001730
-
Experience and Consciousness in the Shadow of Descartes
-
Olli Lagerspetz, "Experience and Consciousness in the Shadow of Descartes," Philosophical Psychology 15 (2002): 8-15
-
(2002)
Philosophical Psychology
, vol.15
, pp. 8-15
-
-
Lagerspetz, O.1
-
10
-
-
33750120220
-
-
Dordrecht: Kluwer
-
Edmund Husserl's and other phenomenologists' phenomenological method (to which I shall return below) has often been characterized as a version of methodological solipsism: see, e.g., Jaakko Hintikka, Ludwig Wittgenstein: Half-Truths and One-and-a-Half-Truths (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1996)
-
(1996)
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Half-Truths and One-and-a-Half-Truths
-
-
Hintikka, J.1
-
12
-
-
33750721817
-
Marx and Methodological Individualism
-
There is plenty of literature available. For some recent discussions, see Mark E. Warren, "Marx and Methodological Individualism," in Terrell Carver, ed., Rational Choice Marxism (University Park: Penn State University Press, 1995)
-
(1995)
Rational Choice Marxism
-
-
Warren, M.E.1
-
14
-
-
0040008668
-
Methodological Individualism in Proper Perspective
-
Todd Jones, "Methodological Individualism in Proper Perspective," Behavior and Philosophy 24 (1996): 119-28
-
(1996)
Behavior and Philosophy
, vol.24
, pp. 119-128
-
-
Jones, T.1
-
15
-
-
0040601968
-
Methodological Individualism and Vertical Integration in the Social Sciences
-
Anthony Walsh, "Methodological Individualism and Vertical Integration in the Social Sciences," Behavior and Philosophy 25 (1997): 121-36
-
(1997)
Behavior and Philosophy
, vol.25
, pp. 121-136
-
-
Walsh, A.1
-
16
-
-
84997908409
-
Situational Analysis beyond Neoclassical Economists
-
Lawrence A. Boland, "Situational Analysis beyond Neoclassical Economists," Philosophy of the Social Sciences 28 (1998): 515-21
-
(1998)
Philosophy of the Social Sciences
, vol.28
, pp. 515-521
-
-
Boland, L.A.1
-
17
-
-
79959180015
-
Moral Individualism and the Justification of Liberal Democracy
-
and Sirkku Kristiina Hellsten, "Moral Individualism and the Justification of Liberal Democracy," Ratio Juris 11 (1998): 320-45. I am not implying that these authors mean exactly the same by their use of the notion. (The same holds for most of my lists of other relevant literature in the notes below.)
-
(1998)
Ratio Juris
, vol.11
, pp. 320-345
-
-
Hellsten, S.K.1
-
18
-
-
79959064598
-
-
ed. 1960-61), especially 136, 148-49
-
See, e.g., Karl R. Popper, The Poverty of Historicism (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1957, 2nd. ed. 1960-61), especially 136, 142, 148-49
-
(1957)
The Poverty of Historicism
, pp. 142
-
-
Popper, K.R.1
-
19
-
-
61949392359
-
Meaning Things and Meaning Others
-
See, for example, C. B. Christensen, "Meaning Things and Meaning Others," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1997): 495-522, for a critical analysis of the methodologically individualist attempt to explain the conventional as derivative from the non-conventional in the Gricean program of communicative semantics
-
(1997)
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
, vol.57
, pp. 495-522
-
-
Christensen, C.B.1
-
20
-
-
33748160532
-
Individualism and Interpretation
-
see also Henry Jackman, "Individualism and Interpretation," Southwest Philosophy Review 14 (1997): 31-38, for a distinction between methodological and "ascriptional" individualism: according to the former, the meaning of one's terms is "grounded in facts about oneself," while according to the latter, the meaning of one's terms is "independent of how others use theirs." This distinction, Jackman attempts to show, allows us to reconcile "interpretational" and social accounts of linguistic meaning
-
(1997)
Southwest Philosophy Review
, vol.14
, pp. 31-38
-
-
Jackman, H.1
-
21
-
-
0003830649
-
-
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, first published
-
On Popper's ontology of the three worlds, see his joint volume with John C. Eccles, The Self and Its Brain (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983; first published 1977)
-
(1977)
The Self and Its Brain
-
-
Eccles, J.C.1
-
22
-
-
0011087968
-
The Principle of Methodological Individualism
-
Methodological holism has been defended, e.g., in J. W. N. Watkins, "The Principle of Methodological Individualism," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 3 (1952): 186-88
-
(1952)
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
, vol.3
, pp. 186-188
-
-
Watkins, J.W.N.1
-
24
-
-
70449778536
-
Ruben and the Metaphysics of the Social World
-
For a critique of Ruben
-
For a critique of Ruben, see Raimo Tuomela, "Ruben and the Metaphysics of the Social World," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (1989): 261-73
-
(1989)
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
, vol.40
, pp. 261-273
-
-
Tuomela, R.1
-
25
-
-
0040811434
-
-
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
-
Tuomela's own research, such as The Importance of Us (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1995), is informed by methodological (and ontological) individualism. (Ruben's holism is not merely methodological, either.)
-
(1995)
The Importance of Us
-
-
-
26
-
-
0005198380
-
-
However, according to Ilkka Niiniluoto, among others, methodological realism is an element of a more comprehensive doctrine of scientific realism which also contains ontological assumptions, and is thus not a "merely methodological" view at all. See Niiniluoto, Critical Scientific Realism (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), chs. 1 and 6
-
(1999)
Critical Scientific Realism
-
-
Niiniluoto1
-
27
-
-
0642354255
-
Methodological Realism and Scientific Rationality
-
Cf. also Jarrett Leplin, "Methodological Realism and Scientific Rationality," Philosophy of Science 53 (1986): 31-51
-
(1986)
Philosophy of Science
, vol.53
, pp. 31-51
-
-
Leplin, J.1
-
28
-
-
52849103542
-
Reductionism as ResourceConscious Reasoning
-
See Godehard Link, "Reductionism as ResourceConscious Reasoning," Erkenntnis 53 (2000): 173-93
-
(2000)
Erkenntnis
, vol.53
, pp. 173-193
-
-
Link, G.1
-
29
-
-
0004069749
-
-
Oxford and New York: Blackwell
-
Rejecting David Lewis's strong modal realism, as expressed, e.g., in his On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford and New York: Blackwell, 1986), more methodologically oriented modal realists may conceive of possible worlds as mere methodological postulates enabling us to investigate semantic and ontological issues better than a purely actualist scheme would allow
-
(1986)
On the Plurality of Worlds
-
-
-
30
-
-
0012302719
-
-
For a highly informative general discussion of these topics, see Michael J. Loux, Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction, rev. ed. (London and New York: Routledge, 2001; 1st. ed. 1998)
-
(1998)
Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction
-
-
Loux, M.J.1
-
31
-
-
0004160442
-
-
ed. Onora O'Neill Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See Christine M. Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity, ed. Onora O'Neill (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)
-
(1996)
The Sources of Normativity
-
-
Korsgaard, C.M.1
-
33
-
-
0003865954
-
-
2nd. ed, Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1st. ed
-
Arthur Fine, The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism, and the Quantum Theory, 2nd. ed. (Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1996; 1st. ed. 1986)
-
(1986)
The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism, and the Quantum Theory
-
-
Fine, A.1
-
35
-
-
79959044041
-
Will Cognitive Science Change Ethics?
-
Mark Timmons, "Will Cognitive Science Change Ethics?" Philosophical Psychology 10 (1997): 531-40
-
(1997)
Philosophical Psychology
, vol.10
, pp. 531-540
-
-
Timmons, M.1
-
36
-
-
33746930408
-
The Haunting of the Human Spirit
-
John A. Teske, "The Haunting of the Human Spirit," Zygon 34 (1999): 307-22
-
(1999)
Zygon
, vol.34
, pp. 307-322
-
-
Teske, J.A.1
-
37
-
-
20744451816
-
Naturalism and the A Priori
-
Paul Boghossian and Christopher Peacocke, eds. Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
and especially Penelope Maddy, "Naturalism and the A Priori," in Paul Boghossian and Christopher Peacocke, eds., New Essays on the A Priori (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000), 92-116
-
(2000)
New Essays on the A Priori
, pp. 92-116
-
-
Maddy, P.1
-
38
-
-
84870829889
-
-
Boston and Oxford: Blackwell
-
as well as Maddy, "Naturalism: Friends and Foes," in James E. Tomberlin, ed., Philosophical Perspectives, 15: Metaphysics (Boston and Oxford: Blackwell, 2001), 37-67
-
(2001)
Philosophical Perspectives
, vol.15
, pp. 37-67
-
-
Tomberlin, J.E.1
-
39
-
-
85038760008
-
-
Helsinki: The Philosophical Society of Finland, ch. 5.3
-
For a critique of both views, cf. Sami Pihlström, Structuring the World: The Issue of Realism and the Nature of Ontological Problems in Classical and Contemporary Pragmatism, Acta Philosophica Fennica, vol. 59 (Helsinki: The Philosophical Society of Finland, 1996), ch. 5.3
-
(1996)
Structuring the World: The Issue of Realism and the Nature of Ontological Problems in Classical and Contemporary Pragmatism, Acta Philosophica Fennica
, vol.59
-
-
Pihlström, S.1
-
40
-
-
2342479487
-
Post-ontological Philosophy of Mind: Rorty versus Davidson
-
Robert B. Brandom, ed. Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell
-
On the other hand, Rorty is as emphatic in his resistance to ontology as in his suspicion of methodology; pragmatic naturalists like Rorty and Davidson are more concerned with the relations between "vocabularies" than with ontological categories such as the mind or the physical world. See here Bjørn Ramberg, "Post-ontological Philosophy of Mind: Rorty versus Davidson," in Robert B. Brandom, ed., Rorty and His Critics (Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell, 2000), 351-70
-
(2000)
Rorty and His Critics
, pp. 351-370
-
-
Ramberg, B.1
-
41
-
-
84977414458
-
Naturalism: Both Metaphysical and Epistemological
-
For a defense of naturalism not as a mere methodological stance but as a metaphysically concerned enterprise, see, e.g., Hilary Kornblith, "Naturalism: Both Metaphysical and Epistemological," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1994): 39-52
-
(1994)
Midwest Studies in Philosophy
, vol.19
, pp. 39-52
-
-
Kornblith, H.1
-
42
-
-
1442353896
-
-
London and New York: Routledge
-
It should be added that several critics of naturalism also find it essentially a metaphysical position, arguing that no methodological naturalism is an interesting view unless supported by metaphysical commitments: see, for instance, several essays in William Lane Craig and J.P. Moreland, eds., Naturalism: A Critical Analysis (London and New York: Routledge, 2000)
-
(2000)
Naturalism: A Critical Analysis
-
-
Craig, W.L.1
Moreland, J.P.2
-
43
-
-
85038732660
-
Selbstorganisation und Reduktionismus
-
ed, Berlin: Duncker-Humblot
-
For the methodological vs. ontological distinction at work here, see Manfred Stockier, "Selbstorganisation und Reduktionismus," in Marie-Luise Heuser-Kessler, ed., Schelling und die Selbstorganisation (Berlin: Duncker-Humblot, 1994)
-
(1994)
Schelling und die Selbstorganisation
-
-
Stockier, M.1
-
44
-
-
85038664670
-
On Methodological Materialism
-
on materialism as a methodological position
-
on materialism as a methodological position, see A. MacC. Armstrong, "On Methodological Materialism," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 34 (1973): 62-72
-
(1973)
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
, vol.34
, pp. 62-72
-
-
Armstrong, A.1
-
45
-
-
79959117546
-
Wittgenstein and Quine: Mind, Language an Behavior
-
Severin Schroeder, ed Houndmills and New York: Palgrave
-
On methodological behaviorism as a view ascribable to Quine and to be distinguished from both metaphysical and logical forms of behaviorism, see Hans-Johann Glock, "Wittgenstein and Quine: Mind, Language an Behavior," in Severin Schroeder, ed., Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy of Mind (Houndmills and New York: Palgrave, 2001), 3-23. It should be noted that sometimes a methodological view, e.g., methodological naturalism or reductionism (or, possibly, behaviorism), is regarded as stronger (more reductive) than a "merely" ontological commitment to the physical or material basic structure of reality, which is generous enough to let all sciences employ their distinctive methods (cf. the reference to Rorty in the previous note). Thus, methodological reductionism would be seen as an addition to, not a weakening of, ontological reductionism, which, it might be assumed, virtually everyone holds. Conversely, methodological anti-reductionism would here be regarded as the safe position, which states that while we may have good reasons to be reductionists (reductive materialists) in ontological issues, this has no bearing on methodological issues. Hence, it depends on which view (reductionism or anti-reductionism) is seen as stronger, or more adventurous, whether methodological reductionism or methodological anti-reductionism is favored by a "methodologicist."
-
(2001)
Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy of Mind
, pp. 3-23
-
-
Glock, H.-J.1
-
46
-
-
79959171107
-
The Ontologization of Transcendental Questions and the Development of Phenomenology into Hermeneutics
-
For quite different critical discussions of methodological monism, see Gerhard Pasternack, "The Ontologization of Transcendental Questions and the Development of Phenomenology into Hermeneutics," in Dieter Lohmar, ed., Philosophy from an Intercultural Perspective (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1997)
-
(1997)
Philosophy from an Intercultural Perspective
-
-
Pasternack, G.1
-
47
-
-
85038725169
-
Positivism as a Method in Nursing Research
-
Edwards, ed, New York: Macmillan
-
and Steven D. Edwards, "Positivism as a Method in Nursing Research," in Edwards, ed., Philosophical Issues in Nursing (New York: Macmillan, 1998)
-
(1998)
Philosophical Issues in Nursing
-
-
Edwards, S.D.1
-
48
-
-
0022666273
-
Exemplary Reasoning: A Comment on Theory Structure in Biomedicine
-
On methodological essentialism (as opposed to "dynamic gradualism" in the philosophy of science), see Arthur L. Caplan, "Exemplary Reasoning: A Comment on Theory Structure in Biomedicine," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 11 (1986): 93-105
-
(1986)
Journal of Medicine and Philosophy
, vol.11
, pp. 93-105
-
-
Caplan, L.1
-
49
-
-
0009140529
-
Understanding Bias in Scientific Practice, Philosophy of Science 63
-
On methodological objectivism
-
On methodological objectivism, see Nancy E. Shaffer, "Understanding Bias in Scientific Practice," Philosophy of Science 63, PSA Supplement (1996): S89-S97
-
(1996)
PSA Supplement
-
-
Shaffer, N.E.1
-
50
-
-
0004239855
-
-
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
-
Methodological exclusivism has been attacked, as a narrow emphasis on some particular method (e.g., positivist causal explanation or hermeneutical understanding) in social science, by "methodological pluralists" (to whom we shall return shortly): see Paul A. Roth, Meaning and Method in the Social Sciences: A Case for Methodological Pluralism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987)
-
(1987)
Meaning and Method in the Social Sciences: A Case for Methodological Pluralism
-
-
Roth, P.A.1
-
51
-
-
79959094635
-
Beyondthe 'Erklären - Verstehen' Dichotomy
-
For relatively recent discussions in which the term is explicitly used, see A.A. van Niekerk, "Beyondthe 'Erklären - Verstehen' Dichotomy," South African Journal of Philosophy 8 (1989): 198-213
-
(1989)
South African Journal of Philosophy
, vol.8
, pp. 198-213
-
-
A.van Niekerk, A.1
-
52
-
-
43549124431
-
Game Theory, Experience, Rationality
-
and Reinhard Selten, "Game Theory, Experience, Rationality," Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 5 (1997): 9-34
-
(1997)
Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook
, vol.5
, pp. 9-34
-
-
Selten, R.1
-
53
-
-
33748354337
-
Cartesian Persons
-
For a reading of Descartes according to which his metaphysical dualism is grounded in a methodological one between theory and practice, or thought and action, see Annette C. Baier, "Cartesian Persons," Philosophia 10 (1981): 169-88
-
(1981)
Philosophia
, vol.10
, pp. 169-188
-
-
Baier, A.C.1
-
55
-
-
79959186520
-
Edmund Husserl and the Quest for a Rigorous Science of Psychology
-
Risto Vuorinen, "Edmund Husserl and the Quest for a Rigorous Science of Psychology," Ajatus 33 (1971): 64-105
-
(1971)
Ajatus
, vol.33
, pp. 64-105
-
-
Vuorinen, R.1
-
57
-
-
84974325316
-
Kuhn's Paradigms and Neoclassical Economics: Reply to Dow
-
George Argyrous, "Kuhn's Paradigms and Neoclassical Economics: Reply to Dow," Economics and Philosophy 10 (1994): 123-26
-
(1994)
Economics and Philosophy
, vol.10
, pp. 123-126
-
-
Argyrous, G.1
-
58
-
-
0028342628
-
A Methodology for Teaching Ethics in the Clinical Setting: A Clinical Handbook for Medical Ethics
-
Laurance McCullough and Carol M. Ashton, "A Methodology for Teaching Ethics in the Clinical Setting: A Clinical Handbook for Medical Ethics," Theoretical Medicine 15 (1994): 39-52
-
(1994)
Theoretical Medicine
, vol.15
, pp. 39-52
-
-
McCullough, L.1
Ashton, C.M.2
-
59
-
-
79959164918
-
Postmodern Critique: Between Relativism and Reduction
-
Horace L. Fairlamb, "Postmodern Critique: Between Relativism and Reduction," Philosophy and Literature 21 (1997): 405-13
-
(1997)
Philosophy and Literature
, vol.21
, pp. 405-413
-
-
Fairlamb, H.L.1
-
60
-
-
0031417951
-
William James and the Challenge of Methodological Pluralism
-
Stephen C. Yanchar, "William James and the Challenge of Methodological Pluralism," Journal of Mind and Behavior 18 (1997): 425-42
-
(1997)
Journal of Mind and Behavior
, vol.18
, pp. 425-442
-
-
Yanchar, S.C.1
-
61
-
-
0010961501
-
Types of Pluralism
-
Walter Watson, "Types of Pluralism," The Monist 73 (1990): 350-66
-
(1990)
The Monist
, vol.73
, pp. 350-366
-
-
Watson, W.1
-
62
-
-
84929230270
-
An Historical Sketch of Pluralism
-
Andrew J. Reck, "An Historical Sketch of Pluralism," The Monist 73 (1990): 367-87
-
(1990)
The Monist
, vol.73
, pp. 367-387
-
-
Reck, A.J.1
-
63
-
-
61149552158
-
Will the Popperian Feyerabend Please Step Forward: Pluralistic, Popperian Themes in the Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend
-
Robert P. Farrell, "Will the Popperian Feyerabend Please Step Forward: Pluralistic, Popperian Themes in the Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend," International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (2000): 257-66
-
(2000)
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science
, vol.14
, pp. 257-266
-
-
Farrell, R.P.1
-
64
-
-
0040814682
-
The Rationalitätstreit Revisited: A Note on Roth's 'Methodological Pluralism'
-
and Steven I. Miller, "The Rationalitätstreit Revisited: A Note on Roth's 'Methodological Pluralism'," Philosophy of the Social Sciences 29 (1999): 339-53
-
(1999)
Philosophy of the Social Sciences
, vol.29
, pp. 339-353
-
-
Miller, S.I.1
-
65
-
-
79959162681
-
Sociology and Epistemology
-
For critical remarks on the sociology of scientific knowledge from this point of view, see Jean Bricmont, "Sociology and Epistemology," Facta Philosophica 3 (2001): 157-76
-
(2001)
Facta Philosophica
, vol.3
, pp. 157-176
-
-
Bricmont, J.1
-
66
-
-
85038679245
-
-
e.g, Boethiana, Hamburg: Kovac, especially
-
See, e.g., Henri Lauener, Offene Transzendentalphilosophie, Boethiana, vol. 50 (Hamburg: Kovac, 2002), especially 184
-
(2002)
Offene Transzendentalphilosophie
, vol.50
, pp. 184
-
-
Lauener, H.1
-
68
-
-
84971745939
-
Jevons's Application of Utilitarian Theory to Economic Policy
-
Sandra J. Peart, "Jevons's Application of Utilitarian Theory to Economic Policy," Utilitas 2 (1990): 281-306
-
(1990)
Utilitas
, vol.2
, pp. 281-306
-
-
Peart, S.J.1
-
71
-
-
0004055786
-
-
Oxford: Blackwell
-
The label has been made well known by Nicholas Rescher; see his books, Methodological Pragmatism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1977)
-
(1977)
Methodological Pragmatism
-
-
-
73
-
-
85071117189
-
Knowledge of the Truth in Pragmatic Perspective
-
London and New York: Routledge
-
as well as Rescher's more recent formulation in his essay, "Knowledge of the Truth in Pragmatic Perspective," in James Conant and Urszula M. Zeglen (eds.), Hilary Putnam: Pragmatism and Realism (London and New York: Routledge, 2002), 66-79 (see especially 72-73)
-
(2002)
Hilary Putnam: Pragmatism and Realism
, pp. 66-79
-
-
Conant, J.1
Zeglen, U.M.2
-
74
-
-
0001223436
-
A Pragmatic Reconsideration of Anthropocentrism
-
Cf. also Eric Katz, "A Pragmatic Reconsideration of Anthropocentrism," Environmental Ethics 21 (1999): 377-90
-
(1999)
Environmental Ethics
, vol.21
, pp. 377-390
-
-
Katz, E.1
-
75
-
-
79959116532
-
my review of Rescher's Realistic Pragmatism
-
Rescher's pragmatism is, above all, realistic - or, to put it differently, his metaphysics (like Peirce's) is realistic and his methodology pragmatic. For some critical remarks on this distinction, cf. my review of Rescher's Realistic Pragmatism, in Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 36 (2000): 419-27
-
(2000)
Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society
, vol.36
, pp. 419-427
-
-
-
76
-
-
85038695511
-
-
Helsinki: WSOY
-
See further my remarks on the pragmatic method toward the end of this essay. In their Finnish book, Totuus, kieli ja käytäntö [Truth, Language, and Practice] (Helsinki: WSOY, 2001), Osmo Kivinen and Seppo Ristelä propose "methodological relationalism" as a version of Rortyan-Deweyan pragmatism
-
(2001)
Totuus, kieli ja käytäntö [Truth, Language, and Practice]
-
-
-
77
-
-
0011971527
-
T. H. Morgan, Neither an Epistemological Empiricist nor a 'Methodological' Empiricist
-
See Marga Vicedo, "T. H. Morgan, Neither an Epistemological Empiricist nor a 'Methodological' Empiricist," Biology and Philosophy 5 (1990): 293-311
-
(1990)
Biology and Philosophy
, vol.5
, pp. 293-311
-
-
Vicedo, M.1
-
78
-
-
79959138977
-
Shook ascribes methodological empiricism (as distinguished from any ontological conception of our "loyalty to things as experienced"), as well as a parallel methodological naturalism (as distinguished from ontological views), to one of the classical pragmatists, John Dewey: See Shook
-
Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press
-
John R. Shook ascribes methodological empiricism (as distinguished from any ontological conception of our "loyalty to things as experienced"), as well as a parallel methodological naturalism (as distinguished from ontological views), to one of the classical pragmatists, John Dewey: see Shook, Dewey's Empirical Theory of Knowlege and Reality (Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press, 2000), 259-61
-
(2000)
Dewey's Empirical Theory of Knowlege and Reality
, pp. 259-261
-
-
John, R.1
-
79
-
-
33751179304
-
Methodological Conservatism
-
For a debate over this view,
-
For a debate over this view, see D. Goldstick, "Methodological Conservatism," American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 186-91
-
(1971)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.8
, pp. 186-191
-
-
Goldstick, D.1
-
80
-
-
0039901099
-
Methodological Conservatism
-
Lawrence Sklar, "Methodological Conservatism," Philosophical Review 84 (1975): 374-400
-
(1975)
Philosophical Review
, vol.84
, pp. 374-400
-
-
Sklar, L.1
-
81
-
-
79959041984
-
The Virtues of Vagueness in the Languages of Science
-
Alexander Rosenberg, "The Virtues of Vagueness in the Languages of Science," Dialogue 14 (1975): 281-305
-
(1975)
Dialogue
, vol.14
, pp. 281-305
-
-
Rosenberg, A.1
-
82
-
-
34250388382
-
More on Methodological Conservation
-
Goldstick, "More on Methodological Conservation," Philosophical Studies 30 (1976): 193-95
-
(1976)
Philosophical Studies
, vol.30
, pp. 193-195
-
-
Goldstick1
-
84
-
-
34249957739
-
Merleau-Ponty's Tacit Cogito
-
The cogito approach in the phenomenological tradition (e.g., in Merleau-Ponty) is sometimes taken to be different from Descartes's cogito because of its being able to avoid methodological skepticism: see Linda L. Williams, "Merleau-Ponty's Tacit Cogito," Man and World 23 (1990): 101-11
-
(1990)
Man and World
, vol.23
, pp. 101-111
-
-
Williams, L.L.1
-
85
-
-
79959094636
-
Deflationist Views of Meaning and Content
-
Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press
-
See Hartry Field, "Deflationist Views of Meaning and Content," in Simon Blackburn and Keith Simmons (eds.), Truth (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 351-91
-
(1999)
Truth
, pp. 351-391
-
-
Field, H.1
-
86
-
-
84922155266
-
Truth and Trans-Theoretical Terms
-
and, eds, 182
-
Gary Ebbs, "Truth and Trans-Theoretical Terms," in Conant and Zeglen, eds., Hilary Putnam, 167-85 (see 182)
-
Hilary Putnam
, pp. 167-185
-
-
Ebbs, G.1
-
89
-
-
85038766048
-
Philosophical and Empirical Knowledge in the Program of Naturalism [online, 2001]
-
Mika Kiikeri and Petri Ylikoski, eds.
-
For a critique of methodological atheism as an unhelpful "naturalization" of the study of religion, cf. Sami Pihlström and Heikki J. Koskinen, "Philosophical and Empirical Knowledge in the Program of Naturalism" [online, 2001], in Mika Kiikeri and Petri Ylikoski, eds., Explanatory Connections: Essays Dedicated to Matti Sintonen's 50th. Birthday, http://www.valt.helsinki.fi/kfil/matti
-
Explanatory Connections: Essays Dedicated to Matti Sintonen's 50th. Birthday
-
-
Pihlström, S.1
Koskinen, H.J.2
-
91
-
-
84880888633
-
The Art of Christian Atheism: Faith and Philosophy in Early Heidegger
-
For an account of methodological atheism as a principle of Heidegger's thought, see James K.A. Smith, "The Art of Christian Atheism: Faith and Philosophy in Early Heidegger," Faith and Philosophy 14 (1997): 71-81
-
(1997)
Faith and Philosophy
, vol.14
, pp. 71-81
-
-
Smith, J.K.A.1
-
92
-
-
3042556144
-
Methodological Altruism as an Alternative Foundation for Individual Optimization
-
I doubt that Emmanuel Levinas himself ever used this term.
-
See Christian Arnsperger, "Methodological Altruism as an Alternative Foundation for Individual Optimization," Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3 (2000): 115-36. I doubt that Emmanuel Levinas himself ever used this term
-
(2000)
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice
, vol.3
, pp. 115-136
-
-
Arnsperger, C.1
-
93
-
-
0039440682
-
Some Varieties of Particularism
-
Cf. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, "Some Varieties of Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 1-12
-
(1999)
Metaphilosophy
, vol.30
, pp. 1-12
-
-
Cf1
Sinnott-Armstrong, W.2
-
94
-
-
85038778998
-
Offene Transzendentalphilosophie, eh
-
See Lauener, Offene Transzendentalphilosophie, eh. 11. There is, it seems to me, no established terminology here, at least not in a sense comparable to the level of establishment of, say, "methodological solipsism" or "methodological naturalism."
-
There is, it seems to me, no established terminology here, at least not in a sense comparable to the level of establishment of, say, methodological solipsism
, vol.11
-
-
Lauener1
-
101
-
-
79959164915
-
Hanna's and Kenneth Westphal's writings to be referred to toward the end of this essay, especially Hanna
-
For critical discussions, cf, Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
For critical discussions, cf. Robert Hanna's and Kenneth Westphal's writings to be referred to toward the end of this essay, especially Hanna, Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001)
-
(2001)
Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy
-
-
Robert1
-
104
-
-
85038778200
-
-
Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press
-
cf. Ricoeur, Husserl (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1957), 36
-
(1957)
Husserl
, pp. 36
-
-
cf1
Ricoeur2
-
105
-
-
79958901424
-
Reconstructing the Past: A Structural Idealist Approach
-
Cf. also Douglas Mann, "Reconstructing the Past: A Structural Idealist Approach," Clio 27 (1998): 221-49
-
(1998)
Clio
, vol.27
, pp. 221-249
-
-
Mann, D.1
-
106
-
-
85038779703
-
Two Kinds of Methodological Solipsism
-
I am here partly relying on an earlier essay of mine, cited above
-
I am here partly relying on an earlier essay of mine, "Two Kinds of Methodological Solipsism," cited above
-
-
-
-
116
-
-
0004235120
-
-
See Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Realism and Reason; Realism with a Human Face
-
(1981)
Reason, Truth and History
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
117
-
-
79959132091
-
Selbstbewusstsein und Objektbewusstsein bei Kant: Eine Studie zu den Paralogismen der reinen Vernunft
-
It has been suggested, however, that Kant's own reliance on the formal unity of apperception is an example of methodological solipsism: see Richard Schantz, "Selbstbewusstsein und Objektbewusstsein bei Kant: Eine Studie zu den Paralogismen der reinen Vernunft," Grazer Philosophische Studien 60 (2000): 151-69
-
(2000)
Grazer Philosophische Studien
, vol.60
, pp. 151-169
-
-
Schantz, R.1
-
120
-
-
60949141235
-
Freedom and Distinction between Phenomena and Noumena: Is Allison's View Methodological, Metaphysical, or Equivocal?
-
While Hanna himself is sympathetic to transcendental idealism, other recent critics of Allison, especially Kenneth Westphal, are much less sympathetic, preferring a (Hegelian) transcendentally established realism instead. Westphal believes that Kant's own "Refutation of Idealism" can be used as a transcendental argument against (transcendental) idealism and in favor of naturalistic realism. For Westphal's critique of Allison, see his essay, "Freedom and Distinction between Phenomena and Noumena: Is Allison's View Methodological, Metaphysical, or Equivocal?" Journal of Philosophical Research 26 (2001): 593-622
-
(2001)
Journal of Philosophical Research
, vol.26
, pp. 593-622
-
-
-
121
-
-
0011851610
-
Affinity, Idealism, and Naturalism: The Stability of Cinnabar and the Possibility of Experience
-
also see Kenneth R. Westphal, "Affinity, Idealism, and Naturalism: The Stability of Cinnabar and the Possibility of Experience," Kant-Studien 88 (1997): 139-89
-
(1997)
Kant-Studien
, vol.88
, pp. 139-189
-
-
Westphal, K.R.1
-
122
-
-
60949178327
-
Can Pragmatic Realists Argue Transcendentally?
-
John R. Shook, ed, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books
-
and Westphal, "Can Pragmatic Realists Argue Transcendentally?" in John R. Shook, ed., Pragmatic Naturalism and Realism (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 2003), 151-75
-
(2003)
Pragmatic Naturalism and Realism
, pp. 151-175
-
-
Westphal1
-
124
-
-
0141786516
-
Transcendental Subjectivity and Metaphysics: A Discussion of David Carr's Paradox of Subjectivity
-
especially 110-14
-
While Zahavi approves of Carr's "demythologization" of transcendental subjectivity, he attacks the latter's purely semantical and anti-metaphysical account of it; in addition to the above-cited forthcoming essay, see also Dan Zahavi, "Transcendental Subjectivity and Metaphysics: A Discussion of David Carr's Paradox of Subjectivity," Human Studies 25 (2002): 103-16 (especially 110-14)
-
(2002)
Human Studies
, vol.25
, pp. 103-116
-
-
Zahavi, D.1
-
125
-
-
0141451606
-
claim that Carr offers a monolithic reading of the transcendental tradition by ignoring important differences between Kant and Husserl (Drummond, Paradox or Contradiction?
-
For comparison, see also John J. Drummond's claim that Carr offers a monolithic reading of the transcendental tradition by ignoring important differences between Kant and Husserl (Drummond, "Paradox or Contradiction?," Human Studies 25 [2002]: 89-102)
-
(2002)
Human Studies
, vol.25
, pp. 89-102
-
-
Drummond, J.J.1
-
126
-
-
0141451589
-
Response to Drummond and Zahavi
-
as well as David Carr, "Response to Drummond and Zahavi," Human Studies 25 (2002): 117-23. In his response to Zahavi, Carr points out that he uses the notion of metaphysics in a pre-critical and pre-phenomenological sense, referring to questions and answers regarding what ultimately exists, and that Zahavi may come too close to depicting phenomenology as metaphysically relevant in this sense. Whether or not this is a correct statement of Zahavi's views, we should not premise our criticism of methodologicism in such a pre-critical manner
-
(2002)
Human Studies
, vol.25
, pp. 117-123
-
-
Carr, D.1
-
130
-
-
0009154807
-
-
New York: Milton, Balch & Company
-
John Dewey, Philosophy and Civilization (New York: Milton, Balch & Company, 1931), 39-41
-
(1931)
Philosophy and Civilization
, pp. 39-41
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
132
-
-
61149557077
-
On the Concept of Philosophical Anthropology
-
see also Sami Pihlström, "On the Concept of Philosophical Anthropology," Journal of Philosophical Research 28 (2003): 259-85
-
(2003)
Journal of Philosophical Research
, vol.28
, pp. 259-285
-
-
Pihlström, S.1
-
133
-
-
0003901582
-
-
On the notion of transcendental anthropology, see Jonathan Lear, Open Minded: Working Out the Logic of the Soul (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 1998). Lear's context is Wittgenstein scholarship
-
(1998)
Open Minded: Working Out the Logic of the Soul
-
-
Lear, J.1
|