메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 44, Issue 3, 2004, Pages 305-319

Moral and political prudence in Kant

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 63549097353     PISSN: 00190365     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/ipq200444326     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (22)
  • 3
    • 79956582948 scopus 로고
    • accuses Kant of a thoroughgoing renunciation of ancient practical philosophy
    • The denial of the strictly moral import of prudence is often taken to be a denial of prudence as such. Ronald Beiner, for example, accuses Kant of "a thoroughgoing renunciation of ancient practical philosophy," in particular its idea of appropriate judgment, and he criticizes Kant for lacking an adequate account of prudence understood as phronesis in his Political Judgment (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1983), pp. 63-71
    • (1983) particular its idea of appropriate judgment , pp. 63-71
    • Beiner, R.1
  • 5
    • 0003630580 scopus 로고
    • third edition, trans. J. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett
    • These are technical imperatives of skill in the Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals, where prudence or pragmatic imperatives concern the identifiable but indeterminate end of happiness or self-interest. See Immanuel Kant, Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals, third edition, trans. J. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), pp. 416-20
    • (1993) Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals , pp. 416-420
    • Kant, I.1
  • 6
    • 0004207225 scopus 로고
    • trans. L. Infield (New York: Harper and Row
    • In his Lectures on Ethics prudence has a complementary role to morality but also has more significant characteristics than in his later writings. See Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics, trans. L. Infield (New York: Harper and Row, 1963), pp. 4-5
    • (1963) Lectures on Ethics , pp. 4-5
    • Kant, I.1
  • 7
    • 0004303838 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press
    • Roger Sullivan places politics under morality but notes: "Kant, however, is not naive about political realities, and he also maintains that morality does not require us to be foolish in dealing with inconsistencies between the moral and civil law." Roger Sullivan, Immanuel Kant's Moral Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1989), p. 251. This leaves open the question of the import of being prudent in the sense of not being foolish in Kant's conception of practical life
    • (1989) Immanuel Kant's Moral Theory , pp. 251
    • Sullivan, R.1
  • 11
    • 79956575132 scopus 로고
    • For an account of the type of hypothetical imperatives called pragmatic or prudential, see Sullivan, 1989, pp. 31-36
    • (1989) Sullivan , pp. 31-36
  • 12
    • 0004291536 scopus 로고
    • trans. M. Gregor Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press
    • Immanuel Kant, Metaphysics of Morals, trans. M. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1991)
    • (1991) Metaphysics of Morals
    • Kant, I.1
  • 13
    • 79955316198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Because of the a posteriori and empirical character of the art of prudence, Kant claimed that no canon can be provided for it (A 800/B 828). On the difference between doctrine or science and art, compare my discussion of this issue in "Schleiermacher on Language, Religious Feeling, and the Ineffable," Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 8:2 (2004) 297-312
    • (2004) A Journal for the History of Philosophy , vol.8 , Issue.2 , pp. 297-312
    • Epoché1
  • 14
    • 0010006663 scopus 로고
    • trans. T. Humphrey Indianapolis: Hackett
    • The following translation is used in this paper: Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace and Other Essays, trans. T. Humphrey (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983)
    • (1983) Perpetual Peace and Other Essays
    • Kant, I.1
  • 16
    • 79956799980 scopus 로고
    • it contains only rules of prudence and morality
    • Kant
    • However, at times Kant suggested that pragmatic imperatives of prudence and technical imperatives of skill are both merely corollaries of theoretical reason (5:172). But in his ethical writings he emphasizes the conditional ought-character of pragmatic imperatives. Thus, in the Lectures on Ethics, "Practical philosophy contains no technical rules: it contains only rules of prudence and morality, and it is, therefore, pragmatic and ethical" (Kant, 1963, p. 4). In the Grounding, all imperatives express an "ought." Hypothetical imperatives of skill and prudence are thus practical in expressing a conditional "ought." Technical imperatives are even here corollaries in that they are derived from theoretical information about what is (4: 413, 415-6)
    • (1963) therefore, pragmatic and ethical , pp. 4
  • 18
    • 85038676134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such as Reflexion 1482, 15: 689
    • Reflexion , vol.1482 , Issue.15 , pp. 689
  • 19
    • 85038748811 scopus 로고
    • trans. Wood and Clark ,Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press
    • 20: 200; Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Philosophical Theology, trans. Wood and Clark (Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1978) p. 92
    • (1978) Lectures on Philosophical Theology , vol.20 , Issue.200 , pp. 92
    • Kant, I.1
  • 21


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.