메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 23, Issue 4, 2009, Pages 193-201

Empirical ethics and its alleged meta-ethical fallacies

Author keywords

Empirical ethics; Fact value distinction; Is ought problem; Naturalistic fallacy

Indexed keywords

ARTICLE; EMPIRICAL RESEARCH; EMPIRICISM; EPIDEMIOLOGY; ETHICAL THEORY; ETHICS; HUMAN; LOGIC; MEDICAL ETHICS; MORALITY;

EID: 63449115138     PISSN: 02699702     EISSN: 14678519     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2009.01710.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (71)

References (49)
  • 1
    • 63449116689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. D.P. Sulmasy & J. Sugarman. 2001. The Many Methods of Medical Ethics (Or, Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird). In Methods of Medical Ethics. D.P. Sulmasy & J. Sugarman, eds. Georgetown: Georgetown University Press: 3-18;
    • cf. D.P. Sulmasy & J. Sugarman. 2001. The Many Methods of Medical Ethics (Or, Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird). In Methods of Medical Ethics. D.P. Sulmasy & J. Sugarman, eds. Georgetown: Georgetown University Press: 3-18;
  • 3
    • 2942626227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is the Role of Empirical Research in Bioethical Reflection and Decision-making? An Ethical Analysis
    • P. Borry, P. Schotsmans & K. Dierickx. What is the Role of Empirical Research in Bioethical Reflection and Decision-making? An Ethical Analysis. Med Health Care Philos 2004; 7: 41-53;
    • (2004) Med Health Care Philos , vol.7 , pp. 41-53
    • Borry, P.1    Schotsmans, P.2    Dierickx, K.3
  • 4
    • 13444249994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Birth of the Empirical Turn in Bioethics
    • P. Borry, P. Schotsmans & K. Dierickx. The Birth of the Empirical Turn in Bioethics. Bioethics 2005; 19: 49-71;
    • (2005) Bioethics , vol.19 , pp. 49-71
    • Borry, P.1    Schotsmans, P.2    Dierickx, K.3
  • 5
    • 28744454605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Empirical Ethics, Context-Sensitivity, and Contextualism
    • A.W. Musschenga. Empirical Ethics, Context-Sensitivity, and Contextualism. J Med Philos 2005; 30: 467-490.
    • (2005) J Med Philos , vol.30 , pp. 467-490
    • Musschenga, A.W.1
  • 7
    • 0027378515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Borry et al. 2005, op. cit. note 1, p. 60; see also, for example, B. Brody. Assessing Empirical Research in Bioethics. Theor Med 1993; 14: 211-219;
    • Borry et al. 2005, op. cit. note 1, p. 60; see also, for example, B. Brody. Assessing Empirical Research in Bioethics. Theor Med 1993; 14: 211-219;
  • 8
    • 0029312098 scopus 로고
    • The Limitation of Empirical Research in Ethics
    • E.D. Pellegrino. The Limitation of Empirical Research in Ethics. J Clin Ethics 1995; 6: 161-162.
    • (1995) J Clin Ethics , vol.6 , pp. 161-162
    • Pellegrino, E.D.1
  • 9
    • 63449083579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The goals we distinguish are mainly based on the analyses of Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1 and Musschenga, op. cit. note 1.
    • The goals we distinguish are mainly based on the analyses of Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1 and Musschenga, op. cit. note 1.
  • 10
    • 63449119165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1
    • Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1.
  • 12
    • 0028450927 scopus 로고
    • The Role of Empirical Research in Medical Ethics: Asking Questions or Answering Them?
    • C.H. Braddock. The Role of Empirical Research in Medical Ethics: Asking Questions or Answering Them? J Clin Ethics 1994; 5: 144-147.
    • (1994) J Clin Ethics , vol.5 , pp. 144-147
    • Braddock, C.H.1
  • 13
    • 63449127818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Holm & Jonas, op. cit. note 1.
    • cf. Holm & Jonas, op. cit. note 1.
  • 15
    • 84937178046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethics and Social Science: Which Kind of Co-operation?
    • D. Birnbacher. Ethics and Social Science: Which Kind of Co-operation? Ethical Theory Moral Pract 1999; 2: 319-336.
    • (1999) Ethical Theory Moral Pract , vol.2 , pp. 319-336
    • Birnbacher, D.1
  • 16
    • 63449111135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Musschenga, op. cit. note 1
    • Cf. Musschenga, op. cit. note 1.
  • 17
    • 5744245892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflective Equilibrium as a Normative-Empirical Model in Bioethics
    • W. van der Burg & T. van Willigenburg, eds. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers
    • J.J.M. van Delden & G.J.M.W. van Thiel. 1998. Reflective Equilibrium as a Normative-Empirical Model in Bioethics. In Reflective Equilibrium. W. van der Burg & T. van Willigenburg, eds. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers: 251-259.
    • (1998) Reflective Equilibrium , pp. 251-259
    • van Delden, J.J.M.1    van Thiel, G.J.M.W.2
  • 18
    • 63449090222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. van Thiel & van Delden, op. cit. note 6
    • Cf. van Thiel & van Delden, op. cit. note 6.
  • 19
    • 63449136304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Birnbacher, op. cit. note 10
    • Birnbacher, op. cit. note 10.
  • 20
    • 85070966428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Empirical Science and Ethical Theory: The Case of Informed Consent
    • A.W. Musschenga & W.J. van der Steen, eds. Ashgate: Aldershot
    • A.W. Musschenga. 1999. Empirical Science and Ethical Theory: the Case of Informed Consent. In Reasoning in Ethics and Law. A.W. Musschenga & W.J. van der Steen, eds. Ashgate: Aldershot: 183-204.
    • (1999) Reasoning in Ethics and Law , pp. 183-204
    • Musschenga, A.W.1
  • 21
    • 63449120136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1
    • Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1.
  • 22
    • 33644976726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Accuracy of Surrogate Decision Makers. A Systematic Review
    • D.I. Shalowitz, E. Garrett-Mayer & D. Wendler. The Accuracy of Surrogate Decision Makers. A Systematic Review. Arch Intern Med 2006; 166: 493-497.
    • (2006) Arch Intern Med , vol.166 , pp. 493-497
    • Shalowitz, D.I.1    Garrett-Mayer, E.2    Wendler, D.3
  • 23
    • 63449117674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A.C. Molewijk. 2006. Risky Business. Individualised Evidence-Based Decision Support and the Ideal of Patient Autonomy. An Integrated Empirical Ethics Study. PhD Thesis Leiden University: 150-174. Other authors working in this tradition are, for example, Guy Widdershoven, Lieke van der Scheer and Annemarie Mol.
    • A.C. Molewijk. 2006. Risky Business. Individualised Evidence-Based Decision Support and the Ideal of Patient Autonomy. An Integrated Empirical Ethics Study. PhD Thesis Leiden University: 150-174. Other authors working in this tradition are, for example, Guy Widdershoven, Lieke van der Scheer and Annemarie Mol.
  • 24
    • 63449088422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See for example the quotation from Borry et al. in the introduction
    • See for example the quotation from Borry et al. in the introduction.
  • 25
    • 84974219658 scopus 로고
    • The Is/Ought Gap, the Fact/Value Distinction and the Naturalistic Fallacy
    • Cf. J. Dodd & S. Stern-Gillet. The Is/Ought Gap, the Fact/Value Distinction and the Naturalistic Fallacy. Dialogue 1995; 34: 727-745.
    • (1995) Dialogue , vol.34 , pp. 727-745
    • Dodd, C.J.1    Stern-Gillet, S.2
  • 26
    • 63449135235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Hume. 1740/1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge (1888). Second edition, revised by P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • David Hume. 1740/1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge (1888). Second edition, revised by P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • 28
    • 0347308680 scopus 로고
    • Baltimore: Penguin Books
    • P.H. Nowell-Smith. 1954. Ethics. Baltimore: Penguin Books.
    • (1954) Ethics
    • Nowell-Smith, P.H.1
  • 29
    • 63449139116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Calling the principle 'Hume's Law' might be somewhat unfortunate, given that several authors have argued that the standard interpretation cannot be correct because it is incompatible with the context of the is-ought passage (see, for example, Part One of W.D. Hudson, ed. 1969. The Is-Ought Question. London: MacMillan).
    • Calling the principle 'Hume's Law' might be somewhat unfortunate, given that several authors have argued that the standard interpretation cannot be correct because it is incompatible with the context of the is-ought passage (see, for example, Part One of W.D. Hudson, ed. 1969. The Is-Ought Question. London: MacMillan).
  • 30
    • 0001886189 scopus 로고
    • The validity of (this version of) Hume's Law has been hotly debated. Searle, for instance, pointed out that certain 'social facts', like the fact that I made a promise to do something, seem to entail normative conclusions, in this case that I ought to do what I promised to do (J. Searle. How to Derive 'Ought' from 'Is'
    • The validity of (this version of) Hume's Law has been hotly debated. Searle, for instance, pointed out that certain 'social facts', like the fact that I made a promise to do something, seem to entail normative conclusions, in this case that I ought to do what I promised to do (J. Searle. How to Derive 'Ought' from 'Is'. Philosophical Review 1964; 73:43-58).
    • (1964) Philosophical Review , vol.73 , pp. 43-58
  • 31
    • 63449137081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, MacIntyre argued that certain facts about the role and purpose of something or someone, e.g. that something is a knife or that someone is a soldier, also seem to entail normative conclusions, in this case that the object ought to be sharp or that the person ought to be brave (A. MacIntyre. 1984. After Virtue. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press). The counterargument most often brought forward against Searle and MacIntyre is that social facts and human purposes are already implicitly normative and that therefore derivations of normative conclusions from these types of 'facts' do not truly violate Hume's Law (cf. J.L. Mackie. 1980. Hume's Moral Theory. London: Routledge).
    • Similarly, MacIntyre argued that certain facts about the role and purpose of something or someone, e.g. that something is a knife or that someone is a soldier, also seem to entail normative conclusions, in this case that the object ought to be sharp or that the person ought to be brave (A. MacIntyre. 1984. After Virtue. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press). The counterargument most often brought forward against Searle and MacIntyre is that social facts and human purposes are already implicitly normative and that therefore derivations of normative conclusions from these types of 'facts' do not truly violate Hume's Law (cf. J.L. Mackie. 1980. Hume's Moral Theory. London: Routledge).
  • 32
    • 0001910666 scopus 로고
    • The Naturalistic Fallacy
    • W.K. Frankena. The Naturalistic Fallacy. Mind 1939; 48: 464-477, p. 467.
    • (1939) Mind , vol.48 , Issue.464-477 , pp. 467
    • Frankena, W.K.1
  • 33
    • 0004264902 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • G.E. Moore. 1903. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • (1903) Principia Ethica
    • Moore, G.E.1
  • 35
    • 63449115724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Frankena, op. cit. note 26
    • See, for example, Frankena, op. cit. note 26.
  • 37
    • 4143066103 scopus 로고
    • Moore's Naturalistic Fallacy
    • David Gauthier. Moore's Naturalistic Fallacy. Am Philos Q 1967; 4: 315-320.
    • (1967) Am Philos Q , vol.4 , pp. 315-320
    • Gauthier, D.1
  • 38
    • 63449099163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G.E. Moore. 1921/1993. Preface to the Second Edition. In Principia Ethica Revised edition, edited by Thomas Baldwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 2-27.
    • G.E. Moore. 1921/1993. Preface to the Second Edition. In Principia Ethica Revised edition, edited by Thomas Baldwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 2-27.
  • 40
    • 63449088750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Dodd & Stern-Gillet, op. cit. note 20;
    • Cf. Dodd & Stern-Gillet, op. cit. note 20;
  • 41
    • 84921742489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy
    • L. Bergström. Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy. Croatian J Philos 2002; 2: 117-129.
    • (2002) Croatian J Philos , vol.2 , pp. 117-129
    • Bergström, L.1
  • 42
    • 63449101284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • W. van der Steen. 1995. Facts, Values, and Methodology. Amsterdam/Atlanta: Rodopi: 15-35.
    • W. van der Steen. 1995. Facts, Values, and Methodology. Amsterdam/Atlanta: Rodopi: 15-35.
  • 43
    • 63449136764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is an important respect in which empirical ethics differs from earlier approaches to ethics that were accused of committing the is-ought fallacy. Unlike naturalistic approaches to ethics, such as evolutionary ethics, or transcendental approaches, empirical ethics does not intend to provide a general foundation of morality. As explained by Musschenga pp. cit. note 1, its main aim is to make general moral principles, whatever the origin of their justification, more context-sensitive
    • This is an important respect in which empirical ethics differs from earlier approaches to ethics that were accused of committing the is-ought fallacy. Unlike naturalistic approaches to ethics, such as evolutionary ethics, or transcendental approaches, empirical ethics does not intend to provide a general foundation of morality. As explained by Musschenga (pp. cit. note 1), its main aim is to make general moral principles, whatever the origin of their justification, more context-sensitive.
  • 44
    • 63449096892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Van Delden & van Thiel, op. cit. note 12
    • Van Delden & van Thiel, op. cit. note 12.
  • 45
    • 63449137406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To give an admittedly simplified example: the inference 'The majority of the Dutch people believe that euthanasia is not morally wrong; therefore, euthanasia is not morally wrong' violates Hume's Law. But if the premise 'Morally wrong is what the majority of the Dutch people believe to be morally wrong' is added, the problem is gone. That the extra premise is implausible or false is irrelevant. After all, to say that an argument is valid is to say that if the premises are true, the conclusion is necessarily also true; the requirement of validity does not entail anything about the actual truth of the premises.
    • To give an admittedly simplified example: the inference 'The majority of the Dutch people believe that euthanasia is not morally wrong; therefore, euthanasia is not morally wrong' violates Hume's Law. But if the premise 'Morally wrong is what the majority of the Dutch people believe to be morally wrong' is added, the problem is gone. That the extra premise is implausible or false is irrelevant. After all, to say that an argument is valid is to say that if the premises are true, the conclusion is necessarily also true; the requirement of validity does not entail anything about the actual truth of the premises.
  • 46
    • 2942627984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Empirical Data and Moral Theory. A Plea for Integrated Empirical Ethics
    • A.C. Molewijk et al. Empirical Data and Moral Theory. A Plea for Integrated Empirical Ethics. Med Health Care Philos 2004; 7: 55-69, p. 55;
    • (2004) Med Health Care Philos , vol.7 , Issue.55-69 , pp. 55
    • Molewijk, A.C.1
  • 47
    • 2942568407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also: Lieke van der Scheer & Guy Widdershoven. Integrated empirical ethics: Loss of normativity? Med Health Care Philos 2004; 7: 71-79.
    • see also: Lieke van der Scheer & Guy Widdershoven. Integrated empirical ethics: Loss of normativity? Med Health Care Philos 2004; 7: 71-79.
  • 48
    • 63449141555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Schermer, op. cit. note 9
    • Cf. Schermer, op. cit. note 9.
  • 49
    • 63449126831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Musschenga 2005, op. cit. note 1
    • Cf. Musschenga 2005, op. cit. note 1.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.