-
1
-
-
63449116689
-
-
cf. D.P. Sulmasy & J. Sugarman. 2001. The Many Methods of Medical Ethics (Or, Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird). In Methods of Medical Ethics. D.P. Sulmasy & J. Sugarman, eds. Georgetown: Georgetown University Press: 3-18;
-
cf. D.P. Sulmasy & J. Sugarman. 2001. The Many Methods of Medical Ethics (Or, Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird). In Methods of Medical Ethics. D.P. Sulmasy & J. Sugarman, eds. Georgetown: Georgetown University Press: 3-18;
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
2942626227
-
What is the Role of Empirical Research in Bioethical Reflection and Decision-making? An Ethical Analysis
-
P. Borry, P. Schotsmans & K. Dierickx. What is the Role of Empirical Research in Bioethical Reflection and Decision-making? An Ethical Analysis. Med Health Care Philos 2004; 7: 41-53;
-
(2004)
Med Health Care Philos
, vol.7
, pp. 41-53
-
-
Borry, P.1
Schotsmans, P.2
Dierickx, K.3
-
4
-
-
13444249994
-
The Birth of the Empirical Turn in Bioethics
-
P. Borry, P. Schotsmans & K. Dierickx. The Birth of the Empirical Turn in Bioethics. Bioethics 2005; 19: 49-71;
-
(2005)
Bioethics
, vol.19
, pp. 49-71
-
-
Borry, P.1
Schotsmans, P.2
Dierickx, K.3
-
5
-
-
28744454605
-
Empirical Ethics, Context-Sensitivity, and Contextualism
-
A.W. Musschenga. Empirical Ethics, Context-Sensitivity, and Contextualism. J Med Philos 2005; 30: 467-490.
-
(2005)
J Med Philos
, vol.30
, pp. 467-490
-
-
Musschenga, A.W.1
-
7
-
-
0027378515
-
-
Borry et al. 2005, op. cit. note 1, p. 60; see also, for example, B. Brody. Assessing Empirical Research in Bioethics. Theor Med 1993; 14: 211-219;
-
Borry et al. 2005, op. cit. note 1, p. 60; see also, for example, B. Brody. Assessing Empirical Research in Bioethics. Theor Med 1993; 14: 211-219;
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
0029312098
-
The Limitation of Empirical Research in Ethics
-
E.D. Pellegrino. The Limitation of Empirical Research in Ethics. J Clin Ethics 1995; 6: 161-162.
-
(1995)
J Clin Ethics
, vol.6
, pp. 161-162
-
-
Pellegrino, E.D.1
-
9
-
-
63449083579
-
-
The goals we distinguish are mainly based on the analyses of Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1 and Musschenga, op. cit. note 1.
-
The goals we distinguish are mainly based on the analyses of Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1 and Musschenga, op. cit. note 1.
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
63449119165
-
-
Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1
-
Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1.
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
0028450927
-
The Role of Empirical Research in Medical Ethics: Asking Questions or Answering Them?
-
C.H. Braddock. The Role of Empirical Research in Medical Ethics: Asking Questions or Answering Them? J Clin Ethics 1994; 5: 144-147.
-
(1994)
J Clin Ethics
, vol.5
, pp. 144-147
-
-
Braddock, C.H.1
-
13
-
-
63449127818
-
-
cf. Holm & Jonas, op. cit. note 1.
-
cf. Holm & Jonas, op. cit. note 1.
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
84937178046
-
Ethics and Social Science: Which Kind of Co-operation?
-
D. Birnbacher. Ethics and Social Science: Which Kind of Co-operation? Ethical Theory Moral Pract 1999; 2: 319-336.
-
(1999)
Ethical Theory Moral Pract
, vol.2
, pp. 319-336
-
-
Birnbacher, D.1
-
16
-
-
63449111135
-
-
Cf. Musschenga, op. cit. note 1
-
Cf. Musschenga, op. cit. note 1.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
5744245892
-
Reflective Equilibrium as a Normative-Empirical Model in Bioethics
-
W. van der Burg & T. van Willigenburg, eds. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers
-
J.J.M. van Delden & G.J.M.W. van Thiel. 1998. Reflective Equilibrium as a Normative-Empirical Model in Bioethics. In Reflective Equilibrium. W. van der Burg & T. van Willigenburg, eds. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers: 251-259.
-
(1998)
Reflective Equilibrium
, pp. 251-259
-
-
van Delden, J.J.M.1
van Thiel, G.J.M.W.2
-
18
-
-
63449090222
-
-
Cf. van Thiel & van Delden, op. cit. note 6
-
Cf. van Thiel & van Delden, op. cit. note 6.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
63449136304
-
-
Birnbacher, op. cit. note 10
-
Birnbacher, op. cit. note 10.
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
85070966428
-
Empirical Science and Ethical Theory: The Case of Informed Consent
-
A.W. Musschenga & W.J. van der Steen, eds. Ashgate: Aldershot
-
A.W. Musschenga. 1999. Empirical Science and Ethical Theory: the Case of Informed Consent. In Reasoning in Ethics and Law. A.W. Musschenga & W.J. van der Steen, eds. Ashgate: Aldershot: 183-204.
-
(1999)
Reasoning in Ethics and Law
, pp. 183-204
-
-
Musschenga, A.W.1
-
21
-
-
63449120136
-
-
Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1
-
Sulmasy & Sugarman, op. cit. note 1.
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
33644976726
-
The Accuracy of Surrogate Decision Makers. A Systematic Review
-
D.I. Shalowitz, E. Garrett-Mayer & D. Wendler. The Accuracy of Surrogate Decision Makers. A Systematic Review. Arch Intern Med 2006; 166: 493-497.
-
(2006)
Arch Intern Med
, vol.166
, pp. 493-497
-
-
Shalowitz, D.I.1
Garrett-Mayer, E.2
Wendler, D.3
-
23
-
-
63449117674
-
-
A.C. Molewijk. 2006. Risky Business. Individualised Evidence-Based Decision Support and the Ideal of Patient Autonomy. An Integrated Empirical Ethics Study. PhD Thesis Leiden University: 150-174. Other authors working in this tradition are, for example, Guy Widdershoven, Lieke van der Scheer and Annemarie Mol.
-
A.C. Molewijk. 2006. Risky Business. Individualised Evidence-Based Decision Support and the Ideal of Patient Autonomy. An Integrated Empirical Ethics Study. PhD Thesis Leiden University: 150-174. Other authors working in this tradition are, for example, Guy Widdershoven, Lieke van der Scheer and Annemarie Mol.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
63449088422
-
-
See for example the quotation from Borry et al. in the introduction
-
See for example the quotation from Borry et al. in the introduction.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
84974219658
-
The Is/Ought Gap, the Fact/Value Distinction and the Naturalistic Fallacy
-
Cf. J. Dodd & S. Stern-Gillet. The Is/Ought Gap, the Fact/Value Distinction and the Naturalistic Fallacy. Dialogue 1995; 34: 727-745.
-
(1995)
Dialogue
, vol.34
, pp. 727-745
-
-
Dodd, C.J.1
Stern-Gillet, S.2
-
26
-
-
63449135235
-
-
David Hume. 1740/1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge (1888). Second edition, revised by P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
-
David Hume. 1740/1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge (1888). Second edition, revised by P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
0347308680
-
-
Baltimore: Penguin Books
-
P.H. Nowell-Smith. 1954. Ethics. Baltimore: Penguin Books.
-
(1954)
Ethics
-
-
Nowell-Smith, P.H.1
-
29
-
-
63449139116
-
-
Calling the principle 'Hume's Law' might be somewhat unfortunate, given that several authors have argued that the standard interpretation cannot be correct because it is incompatible with the context of the is-ought passage (see, for example, Part One of W.D. Hudson, ed. 1969. The Is-Ought Question. London: MacMillan).
-
Calling the principle 'Hume's Law' might be somewhat unfortunate, given that several authors have argued that the standard interpretation cannot be correct because it is incompatible with the context of the is-ought passage (see, for example, Part One of W.D. Hudson, ed. 1969. The Is-Ought Question. London: MacMillan).
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
0001886189
-
The validity of (this version of) Hume's Law has been hotly debated. Searle, for instance, pointed out that certain 'social facts', like the fact that I made a promise to do something, seem to entail normative conclusions, in this case that I ought to do what I promised to do (J. Searle. How to Derive 'Ought' from 'Is'
-
The validity of (this version of) Hume's Law has been hotly debated. Searle, for instance, pointed out that certain 'social facts', like the fact that I made a promise to do something, seem to entail normative conclusions, in this case that I ought to do what I promised to do (J. Searle. How to Derive 'Ought' from 'Is'. Philosophical Review 1964; 73:43-58).
-
(1964)
Philosophical Review
, vol.73
, pp. 43-58
-
-
-
31
-
-
63449137081
-
-
Similarly, MacIntyre argued that certain facts about the role and purpose of something or someone, e.g. that something is a knife or that someone is a soldier, also seem to entail normative conclusions, in this case that the object ought to be sharp or that the person ought to be brave (A. MacIntyre. 1984. After Virtue. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press). The counterargument most often brought forward against Searle and MacIntyre is that social facts and human purposes are already implicitly normative and that therefore derivations of normative conclusions from these types of 'facts' do not truly violate Hume's Law (cf. J.L. Mackie. 1980. Hume's Moral Theory. London: Routledge).
-
Similarly, MacIntyre argued that certain facts about the role and purpose of something or someone, e.g. that something is a knife or that someone is a soldier, also seem to entail normative conclusions, in this case that the object ought to be sharp or that the person ought to be brave (A. MacIntyre. 1984. After Virtue. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press). The counterargument most often brought forward against Searle and MacIntyre is that social facts and human purposes are already implicitly normative and that therefore derivations of normative conclusions from these types of 'facts' do not truly violate Hume's Law (cf. J.L. Mackie. 1980. Hume's Moral Theory. London: Routledge).
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
0001910666
-
The Naturalistic Fallacy
-
W.K. Frankena. The Naturalistic Fallacy. Mind 1939; 48: 464-477, p. 467.
-
(1939)
Mind
, vol.48
, Issue.464-477
, pp. 467
-
-
Frankena, W.K.1
-
33
-
-
0004264902
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
G.E. Moore. 1903. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
-
(1903)
Principia Ethica
-
-
Moore, G.E.1
-
35
-
-
63449115724
-
-
See, for example, Frankena, op. cit. note 26
-
See, for example, Frankena, op. cit. note 26.
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
4143066103
-
Moore's Naturalistic Fallacy
-
David Gauthier. Moore's Naturalistic Fallacy. Am Philos Q 1967; 4: 315-320.
-
(1967)
Am Philos Q
, vol.4
, pp. 315-320
-
-
Gauthier, D.1
-
38
-
-
63449099163
-
-
G.E. Moore. 1921/1993. Preface to the Second Edition. In Principia Ethica Revised edition, edited by Thomas Baldwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 2-27.
-
G.E. Moore. 1921/1993. Preface to the Second Edition. In Principia Ethica Revised edition, edited by Thomas Baldwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 2-27.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
63449088750
-
-
Cf. Dodd & Stern-Gillet, op. cit. note 20;
-
Cf. Dodd & Stern-Gillet, op. cit. note 20;
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
84921742489
-
Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy
-
L. Bergström. Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy. Croatian J Philos 2002; 2: 117-129.
-
(2002)
Croatian J Philos
, vol.2
, pp. 117-129
-
-
Bergström, L.1
-
42
-
-
63449101284
-
-
W. van der Steen. 1995. Facts, Values, and Methodology. Amsterdam/Atlanta: Rodopi: 15-35.
-
W. van der Steen. 1995. Facts, Values, and Methodology. Amsterdam/Atlanta: Rodopi: 15-35.
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
63449136764
-
-
This is an important respect in which empirical ethics differs from earlier approaches to ethics that were accused of committing the is-ought fallacy. Unlike naturalistic approaches to ethics, such as evolutionary ethics, or transcendental approaches, empirical ethics does not intend to provide a general foundation of morality. As explained by Musschenga pp. cit. note 1, its main aim is to make general moral principles, whatever the origin of their justification, more context-sensitive
-
This is an important respect in which empirical ethics differs from earlier approaches to ethics that were accused of committing the is-ought fallacy. Unlike naturalistic approaches to ethics, such as evolutionary ethics, or transcendental approaches, empirical ethics does not intend to provide a general foundation of morality. As explained by Musschenga (pp. cit. note 1), its main aim is to make general moral principles, whatever the origin of their justification, more context-sensitive.
-
-
-
-
44
-
-
63449096892
-
-
Van Delden & van Thiel, op. cit. note 12
-
Van Delden & van Thiel, op. cit. note 12.
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
63449137406
-
-
To give an admittedly simplified example: the inference 'The majority of the Dutch people believe that euthanasia is not morally wrong; therefore, euthanasia is not morally wrong' violates Hume's Law. But if the premise 'Morally wrong is what the majority of the Dutch people believe to be morally wrong' is added, the problem is gone. That the extra premise is implausible or false is irrelevant. After all, to say that an argument is valid is to say that if the premises are true, the conclusion is necessarily also true; the requirement of validity does not entail anything about the actual truth of the premises.
-
To give an admittedly simplified example: the inference 'The majority of the Dutch people believe that euthanasia is not morally wrong; therefore, euthanasia is not morally wrong' violates Hume's Law. But if the premise 'Morally wrong is what the majority of the Dutch people believe to be morally wrong' is added, the problem is gone. That the extra premise is implausible or false is irrelevant. After all, to say that an argument is valid is to say that if the premises are true, the conclusion is necessarily also true; the requirement of validity does not entail anything about the actual truth of the premises.
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
2942627984
-
Empirical Data and Moral Theory. A Plea for Integrated Empirical Ethics
-
A.C. Molewijk et al. Empirical Data and Moral Theory. A Plea for Integrated Empirical Ethics. Med Health Care Philos 2004; 7: 55-69, p. 55;
-
(2004)
Med Health Care Philos
, vol.7
, Issue.55-69
, pp. 55
-
-
Molewijk, A.C.1
-
47
-
-
2942568407
-
-
see also: Lieke van der Scheer & Guy Widdershoven. Integrated empirical ethics: Loss of normativity? Med Health Care Philos 2004; 7: 71-79.
-
see also: Lieke van der Scheer & Guy Widdershoven. Integrated empirical ethics: Loss of normativity? Med Health Care Philos 2004; 7: 71-79.
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
63449141555
-
-
Cf. Schermer, op. cit. note 9
-
Cf. Schermer, op. cit. note 9.
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
63449126831
-
-
Cf. Musschenga 2005, op. cit. note 1
-
Cf. Musschenga 2005, op. cit. note 1.
-
-
-
|