메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 2, 1996, Pages 127-145

Relativism and autonomy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 62949132159     PISSN: 0031806X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (2)

References (28)
  • 1
    • 0004235120 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press, chapters 5 and 7, hereafter cited as RTH
    • See, in particular, Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981), chapters 5 and 7, hereafter cited as RTH
    • (1981) Reason, Truth and History
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 2
    • 85203861971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Putnam's Realism with a human face
    • For the way Putnam and Rorty themselves understand the differences between them, see Putnam's "Realism with a human face," RHF, pp. 18-29
    • RHF , pp. 18-29
  • 3
    • 0003945869 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Conflicts of opinion too fundamental to be settled by an agreed-upon procedure on the basis of tenets and norms accepted by both sides are not confined to large scale cultural conflicts such as arose between science and religion or between the defenders of slavery and abolitionists. The same difficulty can be encountered in much less dramatic conflicts in the arts and sciences. This point was made familiar by Kuhn in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, where he described the opposition between conflicting paradigms within natural science in the following terms: When paradigms enter, as they must, into a debate about paradigm choice, their role is necessarily circular. Each group uses its own paradigm to argue in that paradigm's defence. The resulting circularity does not, of course, make the argument wrong or ineffectual. The man who premises a paradigm when arguing in its defence can nonetheless provide a clear exhibit of what scientific practice will be like for those who adopt the new view of nature. That exhibit can be immensely persuasive, often compellingly so. Yet, whatever its force, the status of the circular argument is only that of persuasion. It cannot be made logically or even probabilistically compelling for those who refuse to step into the circle. (Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd Edition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), p. 94.)
    • (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd Edition , pp. 94
    • Kuhn, T.S.1
  • 4
    • 85203858155 scopus 로고
    • Philosophers and human understanding, Why reason can't be naturalized
    • (all reprinted in Realism and Reason New York: Cambridge University Press, hereafter cited as RR
    • "Philosophers and human understanding," "Why reason can't be naturalized," "Beyond historicism" (all reprinted in Realism and Reason (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983), hereafter cited as RR
    • (1983) Beyond Historicism
  • 5
    • 0004192374 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, chapters 5 and 8
    • and Renewing Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992), chapters 5 and 8
    • (1992) Renewing Philosophy
  • 6
    • 34249925474 scopus 로고
    • What Putnam should have said: An alternative reply to Rorty
    • Sympathetic responses include Carolyn G. Hartz, "What Putnam should have said: an alternative reply to Rorty," Erkenntnis 34, 1991, pp. 287-295
    • (1991) Erkenntnis , vol.34 , pp. 287-295
    • Hartz, C.G.1
  • 7
    • 79956394233 scopus 로고
    • Cultural Imperialism or Benign Relativism? A Putnam-Rorty Debate
    • December
    • and Ronald Lee Jackson, "Cultural Imperialism or Benign Relativism? A Putnam-Rorty Debate," International Philosophical Quarterly Vol. XXVIII, No. 4 Issue No. 112 (December 1988)
    • (1988) International Philosophical Quarterly , vol.28 , Issue.4-112
    • Jackson, R.L.1
  • 8
    • 34249919457 scopus 로고
    • Making Noises in Counterpoint or Chorus: Putnam's Rejection of Relativism
    • Jeffery L. Johnson, in "Making Noises in Counterpoint or Chorus: Putnam's Rejection of Relativism," Erkenntnis 34, 1991, pp. 323-345, provides a careful and sympathetic analysis of Putnam's critique of relativism, but suggests that Putnam's arguments are not conclusive
    • (1991) Erkenntnis , vol.34 , pp. 323-345
    • Johnson, J.L.1
  • 9
    • 9744268646 scopus 로고
    • On Some Objections to Relativism
    • June
    • For a more critical analysis leading to a similar conclusion see John Preston, "On Some Objections to Relativism," Ratio 5 (1), June 1992, pp. 57-73
    • (1992) Ratio , vol.5 , Issue.1 , pp. 57-73
    • Preston, J.1
  • 10
    • 84979389184 scopus 로고
    • On Putnam's argument for the inconsistency of relativism
    • For more positive defences of relativism against Putnam's attack see Miriam Solomon: "On Putnam's argument for the inconsistency of relativism," The Southern Journal of Philosophy (1990), Vol. XX-VIII, No. 2, pp. 213-220
    • (1990) The Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.8-20 , Issue.2 , pp. 213-220
    • Solomon, M.1
  • 11
    • 79956387747 scopus 로고
    • Relativism and Error: Putnam's Lessons for the Relativist
    • June
    • and William M. Throop, "Relativism and Error: Putnam's Lessons for the Relativist," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 49, June 1989, pp. 675-678
    • (1989) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.49 , pp. 675-678
    • Throop, W.M.1
  • 12
    • 61049502183 scopus 로고
    • What Is at Stake between Putnam and Rorty?
    • Sept.
    • In addition to the articles by Hartz and Jackson cited above see, for instance, Paul D. Forster, "What Is at Stake Between Putnam and Rorty?" Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. LII, No. 3, Sept. 1992, pp. 585-603
    • (1992) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.52 , Issue.3 , pp. 585-603
    • Forster, P.D.1
  • 13
    • 0344885680 scopus 로고
    • Putnam and the Relativist Menace
    • Sept.
    • and Rorty's response, "Putnam and the Relativist Menace," Journal of Philosophy, Vol. XC, No. 9, Sept. 1993
    • (1993) Journal of Philosophy , vol.90 , Issue.9
  • 14
    • 85203850248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RTH, p. 119
    • RTH , pp. 119
  • 15
    • 33748169180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why reason can't be naturalized
    • Putnam
    • Putnam, "Why reason can't be naturalized", RR, p. 235
    • RR , pp. 235
  • 16
    • 0003900799 scopus 로고
    • Putnam,Cambridge, Mass, M.I.T. Press
    • Putnam, Representation and Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1988), p. 110
    • (1988) Representation and Reality , pp. 110
  • 17
    • 85203854618 scopus 로고
    • The Many Faces of Realism la Salle, Illinois: Open Court
    • See also The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987), Lecture III
    • (1987) Lecture
  • 18
    • 85203859059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minds and Machines
    • See "Minds and Machines," MLR, p. 373
    • MLR , pp. 373
  • 20
    • 0004097074 scopus 로고
    • Twilight of the Idols
    • The epistemological thesis does not logically entail the metaphysical thesis. One could acknowledge the impossibility of proving any standpoint to be ideal, absolute, or supremely privileged while holding onto the idea that such a standpoint exists, perhaps even that it is attainable. But just as relativists tend to presuppose some form of non-realism, so they also typically incline towards a pragmatically grounded skepticism regarding the value - even the meaningfulness - of a concept like that of an absolute standpoint, the use of which cannot be experientially justified. Their attitude is similar to that expressed by Nietzsche toward the philosopher's concept of "the true world": The true world - unattainable, indemonstrable? At any rate, unattained. And being unattained, also unknown. Consequently, not consoling, redeeming, or obligating: how could something unknown obligate us? . . . The "true" world - an idea which is no longer good for anything, not even obligating - an idea which has become useless and superfluous - consequently, a refuted idea: let us abolish it! (Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, trans. Walter Kaufmann in The Portable Nietzsche (New York: Viking Press, 1954), p. 485.) Much more could be said, of course, on the desirability of making this move; but that is a subject for a different paper
    • (1954) The Portable Nietzsche , pp. 485
    • Nietzsche, F.1
  • 21
    • 60949263499 scopus 로고
    • What the tortoise said to Achilles
    • The person being addressed must also, of course, accept the rules that define valid argumentation. That these cannot themselves be established by means of an argument is the point of Lewis Carroll's "What the tortoise said to Achilles" (Mind, 4 (1895), pp. 278-80)
    • (1895) Mind , vol.4 , pp. 278-280
    • Carroll, L.1
  • 22
    • 0003967815 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • What Kuhn says here with respect to natural science may, of course, be generalized, and not just to conflicts in other areas of theoretical activity but more widely to all conflicts between "incompatible modes of community life." This is precisely what Rorty does in Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Discussing the question of how liberal values might be justified, he writes: "a circular justification of our practices, a justification which makes one feature of our culture look good by citing still another, or comparing our culture invidiously with others by reference to our own standards, is the only sort of justification we are going to get." (Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989). p. 57.)
    • (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity , pp. 57
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 23
    • 0004892867 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Rorty describes his position as "the view that there is nothing to be said about either truth or rationality apart from the descriptions of the familiar procedures of justification which a given society - ours - uses in one or another area of enquiry." (Richard Rorty, "Solidarity or Objectivity,": Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 23. He prefers the labels "pragmatism" or "ethnocentrism" to "relativism," since he thinks the term "relativism" implies (and is often taken to denote) a positive theory of truth. What Rorty wishes to avoid is any theory that claims to identify what it is that all true beliefs have in common in virtue of which they are true. But relativism as I have characterized it here is not a theory of that sort. For it does not conceive of a statement's "truth value" as something it can have independent of the procedures by which it is justified or refuted
    • (1991) Solidarity or Objectivity, Philosophical Papers , vol.1 , pp. 23
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 24
    • 61049502183 scopus 로고
    • What is at stake between Putnam and Rorty?
    • Sept.
    • A similar point is made by Paul Foster, "What is at stake between Putnam and Rorty?," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. LII, No. 3, Sept. 1992, p. 593
    • (1992) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.52 , Issue.3 , pp. 593
    • Foster, P.1
  • 25
    • 85203854598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reply to Hartz
    • Putnam's reading of Rorty is questionable, in my opinion, because I do not think Rorty wishes to identify the concept of truth or the concept of rationality with the norms governing their employment in our present culture. Rather, he simply maintains that there is no useful notion of reason or truth that is not equivalent to some set of norms that a particular community actually employs. In his "Reply" to Hartz (Erkenntnis 34, p. 402) Putnam himself criticizes her reading of Rorty for being "uncharitable." To be fair to Hartz, though, what is at issue is not whether Rorty actually denies that we can make sense of other conceptions of rationality, but whether his relativism entails this consequence
    • Erkenntnis , vol.34 , pp. 402
  • 27
    • 85203854952 scopus 로고
    • The corroboration' of theories
    • Putnam,New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Putnam, "The "corroboration' of theories," Mathematics, Matter and Method (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1975), p. 269
    • (1975) Mathematics, Matter and Method , pp. 269


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.