-
2
-
-
62249202633
-
-
Basel
-
2), 43: 'Die entscheidende Tatsache ist, dass zur Zeit Platons von keinem der drei Milesier mehr Schriften bekannt waren. Das darf man daraus schliessen, das Platon von ihnen überhaupt nur Thales kennt . . .'
-
(1968)
Der Ursprung der griechischen Philosophie
, pp. 43
-
-
Gigon, O.1
-
4
-
-
38649108659
-
-
Cambridge
-
M. M. McCabe, Plato and his Predecessors (Cambridge, 2000). This book does not claim to be a complete survey, for it deals only with the Theaetetus, Sophist, Statesman, and Philebus. But where the author does discuss Plato's views of his Ionian predecessors at Sophist 242c-243a, she has nothing to say about the Milesians (see esp. 64-5)
-
(2000)
Plato and his Predecessors
, pp. 64-65
-
-
McCabe, M.M.1
-
5
-
-
79956705803
-
1st der Aer des Anaximenes als eine Substanz konzipiert?
-
esp. 137-8
-
In his account of the 'way up' he omits cloud (49c2), and in his account of the 'way down' he omits wind (c4-5); but clearly wind is thicker than air, and presumably thinner than cloud. Although this point should be fairly straightforward, it is complicated by the fact that Hippol. Haer. 1.7.7 reads which Diels corrects by dropping the and changing the final two words to Much has been made of this by J. Klowski, '1st der Aer des Anaximenes als eine Substanz konzipiert?' Hermes 100 (1972), 131-42, esp. 137-8
-
(1972)
Hermes
, vol.100
, pp. 131-142
-
-
Klowski, J.1
-
6
-
-
79956705830
-
A new look at Anaximenes
-
but their interpretation starts, I believe, with a misreading of Pseudo-Plutarch Stromateis 3 = A6 DK, as I have argued elsewhere (D. W. Graham, 'A new look at Anaximenes', History of Philosophy Quarterly 20 [2003], 1-20). One would need strong reasons to abandon Theophrastus in favour of Hippolytus and Pseudo-Plutarch when the latter two depend on the first; a key move in the brief for Hippolytus and Pseudo-Plutarch is an argument from silence: no one before Theophrastus knows of Anaximenes' theory of change (as reported by Theophrastus). But at least Anaxagoras and Melissus, as well as Plato, know of it
-
(2003)
History of Philosophy Quarterly
, vol.20
, pp. 1-20
-
-
Graham, D.W.1
-
7
-
-
0009286830
-
-
New York
-
This particular term is first found in Anaxagoras as a quasi-scientific term (B12, B13, B17 DK); the last passage makes clear the image of mixing and separating in which nothing comes to be or perishes. Here Plato seems to be conflating terminology from pre-Parmenidean and post-Parmenidean theories, that is, theories of generation vs. theories of mixture (cf. C. H. Kahn, Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology [New York, 1960], 155)
-
(1960)
Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology
, pp. 155
-
-
Kahn, C.H.1
-
8
-
-
0004258497
-
-
But since he conjoins the term with 'dissolved', a term appropriate to early Ionian thought and found in the Anaximander doxography (Aetius 3.7.1 = A24 DK, with Kahn, 101), he seems unconcerned with the potential distinction. F. M. Cornford, Plato's Cosmology (London, 1937), 180 sees Anaximenes as moving towards Anaxagoras: 'Anaximenes . . . took a step towards the doctrine clearly formulated after Parmenides, that qualitative change is reducible to the bringing together or separation in space of a number of unalterable elements.' This, I take it, is precisely what he did not do; instead he made what Aristotle would later call coming to be and perishing the fundamental kinds of change, as Plato recognizes
-
(1937)
Plato's Cosmology
, pp. 180
-
-
Cornford, F.M.1
-
9
-
-
79956689286
-
Anaximenes' simile
-
See P. J. Bicknell, 'Anaximenes' simile', Apeiron 1 (1966), 17-18 for a suggested reinterpretation of the cap as a circular strip. Whatever the specific apparel referred to, the peculiar reference to felt headgear seems to guarantee that felt played a significant role in Anaximenes (cf. Kirk et al. [n. 3], 156). If the term 'felted' did subsequently become a synonym for 'compacted' in Greek cosmology, we may reasonably trace its origin to Anaximenes
-
(1966)
Apeiron
, vol.1
, pp. 17-18
-
-
Bicknell, P.J.1
-
12
-
-
84868769874
-
Qualitative change in Presocratic philosophy
-
Critics of MM as an interpretation of the pre-Socratics include W. A. Heidel, 'Qualitative change in Presocratic philosophy', Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 19 (1906), 333-79
-
(1906)
Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie
, vol.19
, pp. 333-379
-
-
Heidel, W.A.1
-
16
-
-
84868819862
-
Das Entstehen der Begriffe Substanz und Materie
-
J. Klowski, 'Das Entstehen der Begriffe Substanz und Materie', Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 48 (1966), 2-42
-
(1966)
Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie
, vol.48
, pp. 2-42
-
-
Klowski, J.1
-
23
-
-
58649107872
-
Heraclitus' criticism of Ionian philosophy
-
Against Barnes in particular see D. W. Graham, 'Heraclitus' criticism of Ionian philosophy', Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 15 (1997), 1-50 at 12-17
-
(1997)
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy
, vol.15
, Issue.1-50
, pp. 12-17
-
-
Graham, D.W.1
-
25
-
-
85038770330
-
-
Cf. Hölscher (n. 14), 268. Parmenides might be replying to Hesiod and common-sense views, but if non-philosophers are his only targets, he ignores the whole previous philosophical tradition
-
Hölscher
, Issue.14
, pp. 268
-
-
-
27
-
-
85038782058
-
-
Cf. Gigon (n. 2), 104
-
, vol.104
, Issue.2
-
-
Gigon, C.1
|