메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 1-2, 1998, Pages 3-21

Individual natures

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 62549165097     PISSN: 00483893     EISSN: 15749274     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/BF02380055     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (4)

References (28)
  • 1
    • 0002981362 scopus 로고
    • Interpretation and the Sciences of Man
    • note
    • For one influential argument to this effect (among many others) see Charles Taylor, Interpretation and the Sciences of Man, " in Human Agency and Language., vol 11, p.15-57 (Cambridge University Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Human Agency and Language , vol.11 , pp. 15-57
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 2
    • 0346468125 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Versions of this objection are found in Hampshire, Freedom of the Individual, (Harper and Row, 1965).
    • (1965) Freedom of the Individual
  • 4
    • 0012889713 scopus 로고
    • Special Sciences
    • note
    • See also J. Fodor, "Special Sciences, " in Representations (Cambridge: MIT-Bradford, 1981)
    • (1981) Representations
    • Fodor, J.1
  • 5
    • 84985362811 scopus 로고
    • Individualism and the Mental
    • See Tyler Burge, "Individualism and the Mental", Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4:73-121 (1979).
    • (1979) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.4 , pp. 73-121
    • Burge, T.1
  • 7
    • 84897941029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Another characteristic that is sometimes cited to explain the difficulty of finding laws that describe human behaviour is their complexity. But as far as I can see complexity is not a priori an obstacle to being subject to natural law. In some cases, indeed, complexity is a necessary condition of the applicability of natural law. This can be illustrated by any of the laws, such as Boyle's laws, or the laws of thermodynamics, that are in effect stable statistical consequences of large numbers of elementary events.
  • 13
    • 84897934882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This seems to be roughly the strategy followed by Kripke and Putnam.
  • 17
    • 84951396326 scopus 로고
    • The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds
    • note
    • I've gone on record elsewhere as arguing that there are no such kinds. See "The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds, " Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14:561-580 (1984).
    • (1984) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.14 , pp. 561-580
  • 18
    • 84897940099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is a separate question, about which I shall have nothing to say here, to what extent our individual nature is necessarily constant and to what extent we can have a succession of such natures. On a Parfitean view of the self, only a relatively short temporal slice of a person could strictly have a nature. On more traditional views, our nature might be precisely that which once formed could not be changed, though perhaps it could be perverted by traumatic experience.
  • 19
    • 84897939742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • How to interpret possible combination? Strictly speaking, given infinite time only that is guaranteed to happen which has non-zero probability; but in an infinite domain that is not equivalent to possibility. Pick a point on a line: the measure of the probability of picking a particular point is zero, yet picking it is not impossible. Given that we have already posited a finite number of possible combinations, however, possibility and non-zero probability can be considered equivalent, for Nietzsche's intents and purposes.
  • 21
    • 0003626641 scopus 로고
    • note
    • The set-theoretic method is essentially the traditional requirement of total evidence for statistical reasoning. See Carl G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation (New York: Free Press, 1965) pp. 397 ff.
    • (1965) Aspects of Scientific Explanation , pp. 397
    • Hempel, C.G.1
  • 22
    • 26444617654 scopus 로고
    • Causal Laws and Effective Strategies
    • note
    • Nancy Cartwright, "Causal Laws and Effective Strategies, " in Why the Laws of Physics Lie (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983)
    • (1983) Why the Laws of Physics Lie
    • Cartwright, N.1
  • 23
    • 26444617654 scopus 로고
    • Causal Laws and Effective Strategies
    • note
    • Nancy Cartwright, "Causal Laws and Effective Strategies, " in Why the Laws of Physics Lie (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983)
    • (1983) Why the Laws of Physics Lie
    • Cartwright, N.1
  • 24
    • 84897942649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We might express absolute risk R with respect to any proposition p with a number normalized between 0 and 1:R-4 prob(p) * prob (-p).
  • 25
    • 84897931462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As did an anonymous referee for an earlier version of this paper. Could individual natures be discovered by performing repeated experiments on a single individual? A more generally shared characteristic of biological organisms makes this difficult: any repeated experiment is likely to change the properties of the organism so tested. Still, some properties having essentially to do with that very fact might be explored in this way: an individual's characteristic learning or habituation curves, for example.
  • 27
    • 84897953236 scopus 로고
    • Emotions and the Conduct of Life
    • note
    • That fact gives rise to the tragedy of solidarity, which I have discussed in "Emotions and the Conduct of Life, " chap. 12 of The Rationality of Emotion (Cambridge, MA: MIT-Bradford, 1987)
    • (1987) The Rationality of Emotion
  • 28
    • 84897935305 scopus 로고
    • The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique, and discussions by 38 commentators in "open peer commentary
    • note
    • Rough and ready approaches to such knowledge are exemplified by psychoanalysis, in which the chief source of knowledge is supposed to be the clinical experience of particular cases. Such clinical experience is, of course, open to easy objections: solid knowledge about individual natures is, for the reasons I have given, impossible. But if we take the notion of individual natures seriously, we'll think somewhat differently about the issue of clinical evidence. The way it's usually discussed (see, e.g., Adolph Griinbaum, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique, and discussions by 38 commentators in "open peer commentary" in Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9:228-284, 1986) the question concerns whether it's any good to get evidence from the clinical situation. But one could profitably turn the question about and ask, is there anything in the individual case (not just in psychoanalysis but in medecine generally) that might at best show up in the clinical situation but is inevitably inaccessible otherwise'? If there are individual natures, clinical experience might be one partial and unsatisfactory method of access to properties otherwise quite unknowable.
    • (1986) Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol.9 , pp. 228-284
    • Griinbaum, A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.