메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 22, Issue , 2002, Pages 253-307

Non-rational perception in the Stoics and Augustine

(1)  Brittain, Charles a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61449333709     PISSN: 02657651     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book Series    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (55)

References (37)
  • 1
    • 0004179048 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley
    • There are many studies of Augustine's views on perception and memory, but few have much to say about the scope of non-rational content. The most interesting modern discussion is G. O'Daly, Augustine's Philosophy of Mind [Mind] (Berkeley, 1987) chs. 3-5, summarized in his entry 'Anima, animus' in C. Meyer (ed.), Augustinus-Lexicon, i (Basel, 1986-94), 315-40
    • (1987) Augustine's Philosophy of Mind [Mind]
    • O'Daly, G.1
  • 2
    • 70450112754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Fathers and the Animals: The Rule of Reason
    • A. Linzey and D. Yamamoto eds. London
    • Augustine's views on how animals should be treated are not examined in this paper. Two brief and unsympathetic accounts are G. Clark, 'The Fathers and the Animals: The Rule of Reason?', in A. Linzey and D. Yamamoto (eds.), Animals on the Agenda (London, 1998), 67-79
    • (1998) Animals on the Agenda , pp. 67-79
    • Clark, G.1
  • 7
    • 79953967638 scopus 로고
    • 'Sensus interior in St. Augustine, De libera arbitrio 2. 3. 25-6. 51'
    • G. O'Daly, 'Sensus interior in St. Augustine, De libera arbitrio 2. 3. 25-6. 51', Studia Patristica, 16, Texte und Untersuchungen, 129 (1985), 528-32 (revised in Mind, 102-5), shows how the main lines of the Augustinian doctrine of 'inner sense' discussed below might be owed to Plotinus. But the scattered Plotinian passages he cites do not amount to a theory Augustine could have learnt from, although they maybe consistent, and could stem from a theory Plotinus held; and what Plotinus does say probably differs in at least one important respect from Augustine's theory - see n. 100 below
    • (1985) Studia Patristica , vol.16 , pp. 528-532
    • O'Daly, G.1
  • 8
    • 60950589805 scopus 로고
    • ' Une nouvelle source de saint Augustin: le Zêtêmata de Porphyre Sur l'union de l'âme et du corps'
    • As O' Daly, Mind, 102-5, points out, the works in which Augustine developed his views on non-rational perception are heavily influenced by Platonism. De quantitate animae, for instance, depends primarily on Porphyry's Mixed Questions - see J. Pépin,' Une nouvelle source de saint Augustin: le Zêtêmata de Porphyre "Sur l'union de l'âme et du corps'", Revue des études anciennes, 66 (1964), 53-107. It is quite possible, and also consistent with the claims of this paper, that the Stoic elements in Augustine's views were mediated by Porphyry
    • (1964) Revue des études anciennes , vol.66 , pp. 53-107
    • Pépin, J.1
  • 9
    • 84955356118 scopus 로고
    • 'De la nature phantastique des animaux chez les Stoïciens' ['Nature phantastique']
    • J. Brunschwig and M. Nussbaum (eds.),Cambridge
    • Most of the non-abilities ascribed to animals below are discussed in more detail by J.-L. Labarrière in two articles: 'De la "nature phantastique" des animaux chez les Stoïciens' ['Nature phantastique'], in J. Brunschwig and M. Nussbaum (eds.), Passions and Perceptions (Cambridge, 1993), 225-49
    • (1993) Passions and Perceptions , pp. 225-249
  • 10
    • 61949107302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Logos endiathetos et logos porphorikos'
    • B. Cassin and J.-L. Labarrière (eds.),Paris
    • and 'Logos endiathetos et logos porphorikos', in B. Cassin and J.-L. Labarrière (eds.), L'Animal dans l'antiquité (Paris, 1997), 259-79
    • (1997) L'Animal dans l'antiquité , pp. 259-279
  • 12
    • 79954065156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SVF iii. 368
    • Origen, Contra Celsum 4. 81 (SVF iii. 368)
    • Contra Celsum , vol.4 , pp. 81
    • Origen1
  • 13
    • 79954084453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [St. Eth.] 1
    • Only impression and impulse: Hierocles, Elements of Ethics [St. Eth.] 1. 31-3
    • Elements of Ethics , pp. 31-33
    • Hierocles1
  • 14
    • 79954055127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plut, 960 F, 961 E-F;
    • Plut. Soll. an. 960 F, 961 E-F
    • Soll. an
  • 15
    • 0039578270 scopus 로고
    • 'Perceptual Content in the Stoics' ['Perceptual Content']
    • denies that Sextus reports a Stoic view (311-12)
    • D.L. 7. 52 (SVF ii. 84). R. Sorabji, 'Perceptual Content in the Stoics' ['Perceptual Content'], Phronesis, 35 (1990), 307-14, denies that Sextus reports a Stoic view (311-12)
    • (1990) Phronesis , vol.35 , pp. 307-314
    • Sorabji, R.1
  • 16
    • 61249273489 scopus 로고
    • The Stoic Conception Of Reason' ['Reason']
    • K. Boudouris ed, Athens
    • See M. Frede, 'The Stoic Conception Of Reason' ['Reason'], in K. Boudouris (ed.), Hellenistic Philosophy, ii (Athens, 1994) 50-63
    • (1994) Hellenistic Philosophy , vol.2 , pp. 50-63
    • Frede, M.1
  • 17
    • 77953956812 scopus 로고
    • 'Stoics and Skeptics on Clear and Distinct Impressions' ['Stoics and Skeptics']
    • id., Berkeley, esp. 68-9; and n. 34 below
    • id., 'Stoics and Skeptics on Clear and Distinct Impressions' ['Stoics and Skeptics'], in M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition (Berkeley, 1983), 65-93, esp. 68-9; and n. 34 below
    • (1983) The Skeptical Tradition , pp. 65-93
    • Burnyeat, M.1
  • 18
    • 61449365305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Content, Cause and Stoic Impressions' ['Content']
    • G. Lesses, 'Content, Cause and Stoic Impressions' ['Content'], Phronesis, 43 (1998), 1-25
    • (1998) Phronesis , vol.43 , pp. 1-25
    • Lesses, G.1
  • 19
    • 0004091673 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass
    • Here I follow Frede, 'Reason', 53. See the texts listed in nn. 12 and 15. On this account, the Stoic criteria for concept-possession and belief are, of course, extremely rigorous in comparison with some modern views; see e.g. R. Stalnaker, Inquiry (Cambridge, Mass., 1987), 62-8
    • (1987) Inquiry , pp. 62-68
    • Stalnaker, R.1
  • 20
    • 0039578263 scopus 로고
    • Berlin
    • Aetius 4. 12. I (SVF ii. 54): ('An impression is an affection occurring in the soul, which shows in itself what made it as well. For example, when we observe something white through sight, what occurs in the soul through our vision is an affection; and on the basis of this affection we are able to say that there is a white thing moving us (and similarly [when we observe something] through touch or smell). Impressions get their name from "light", because just as light shows itself and the other things contained in it, so impressions show themselves and what made them'). The text is uncertain-see H. Diels, Doxographi Graeci (Berlin, 1879) 401, for some of the manuscript readings in Nemesius and pseudo-Plutarch - but the light analogy shows that this characterization was intended to indicate that an impression 'shows itself in some sense, as well as something else
    • (1879) Doxographi Graeci , pp. 401
    • Diels, H.1
  • 21
    • 79953995292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corpus dei papiri filosofici greci e latini, 1, i,Florence
    • Hierocles, St. Eth. 6. 1-6: The text is from A. A. Long and G. Bastianini, 'Hierocles', in Corpus dei papiri filosofici greci e latini, 1, vol. i(Florence, 1992), 334
    • (1992) 'Hierocles' , pp. 334
    • Long, A.A.1    Bastianini, G.2
  • 22
    • 34548732926 scopus 로고
    • Hierocles: Theory and Argument in the Second Century AD
    • 151-84, at
    • See Drad Inwood, 'Hierocles: Theory and Argument in the Second Century AD', OSAP 2 (1984), 151-84, at 166
    • (1984) OSAP , vol.2 , pp. 166
    • Inwood, D.1
  • 23
    • 0037806573 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • Stob. 2. 86 (SVF iii. 169): ('What moves impulse is nothing other than a hormetic impression of something immediately "appropriate"; and impulse is generically a motion of the soul towards something. The two species of impulse are the kind that occurs in rational animals and the kind in non-rational animals; but these do not have names ("desire" is not rational impulse, but a subspecies of rational impulse)'). It is unfortunate that the only evidence for this vital part of Chrysippus' theory is Stobaeus; but it is fairly clear that this was Chrysippus' theory; see B. Inwood, Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism [Ethics] (Oxford, 1985), 55-7
    • (1985) Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism [Ethics] , pp. 55-57
    • Inwood, B.1
  • 24
    • 79954386539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Labarrière, 'Nature phantastique', 235-8. It is not at all clear in the brief account in Aetius 4. 11 (SVF ii. 83) what it is about children that enables them to develop concepts out of perception, memory and experience - i.e. out of quasiconcepts, on my view. I offer one suggestion in n. 57
    • 'Nature phantastique' , pp. 235-238
    • Labarrière1
  • 25
    • 0003419754 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • This is suggested by Aetius 4. 11 fin. (SVF ii. 83): ('Conceptual objects are phantasms of the thought of a rational animal - i.e. when a phantasm occurs to a rational soul it is called a "conceptual object" (its name derives from "intellect"). So the ones that occur to non-rational animals are just phantasms; but the ones that occur to us and to the gods are generically phantasms and specifically conceptual objects'). Aetius is no doubt wrong to identify all human phantasms as 'conceptual objects', as A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge 1987), ii. 185, note. But his point is apparently that abstract thoughts in general, and specifically the rational concepts he is concerned with in 4. 11, supervene on representational images of some kind. His mistake about need not colour this claim
    • (1987) The Hellenistic Philosophers , vol.2 , pp. 185
    • Long, A.A.1    Sedley, D.N.2
  • 26
    • 79953676742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Hierocles on Oikeiosis and Self-Perception'
    • Cambridge, at 256-61
    • See A. A. Long, 'Hierocles on Oikeiosis and Self-Perception', Stoic Studies (Cambridge, 1996), 250-63 at 256-61. 'Proprioception' is the monitoring of the body which occurs in the central nervous system, in virtue of which one 'knows' e.g. where one's leg is
    • (1996) Stoic Studies , pp. 250-263
    • Long, A.A.1
  • 27
    • 79953995292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I presuppose here that animal impressions are restricted to the first stage identified in cols. 7-8, contra Long and Bastianini, 'Hierocles', 444-8, ad loc. Others concur because they think that we can rule out the possibility that animals have cataleptic impressions (the third stage above); see e.g. Labarrière, 'Nature phantas-tique', 234. But this is not clear; no doubt animals cannot have catalepsis, but that does not imply that they cannot have cataleptic impressions, only that they cannot assent to them and hence form judgements or have knowledge. Human children must be able to achieve cataleptic impressions, since their 'natural concepts' become criteria of truth when they finally appear at the age of 7 (or 14), and hence must derive from cataleptic impressions. These considerations also suggest one way to distinguish the perception of human children from animal perception: children may be conscious more often or of more of their perceptual content
    • Hierocles , pp. 444-448
    • Long1    Bastianini2
  • 28
    • 79953353894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea here is to tie the features Hierocles and Seneca mention to the known properties of cataleptic impressions. On the latter, see Frede, 'Stoics and Skeptics', 71-8
    • Stoics and Skeptics , pp. 71-78
    • Frede1
  • 29
    • 0042148329 scopus 로고
    • Kentucky
    • I think that O'Daly, Mind, wavers between (a) and the two interpretations of (b) at p. 86. But his claim that 'Augustine repeatedly stresses that sense perception is the perception of images of bodies (imagines corporum), and not of the bodies themselves' (p. 95) looks like a firm endorsement of the image variant of (b). The latter is standard; see e.g. R. Nash, The Light of the Mind: St Augustine's Theory of Knowledge (Kentucky, 1969), 54
    • (1969) The Light of the Mind: St Augustine's Theory of Knowledge , pp. 54
    • Nash, R.1
  • 30
    • 79954387771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Labarrière, 'Nature phantastique', 237 n. 21. But this depends on two mistakes: not realizing that the theory of explains only general animal behaviour patterns; and not seeing that Plut. Soll. an. 961 C - D rules out only animal possession of rational memory
    • 'Nature phantastique' , vol.237 , Issue.21
    • Labarrière1
  • 31
    • 79953984294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Posidonius on the Emotions'
    • J. Cooper, 'Posidonius on the Emotions', in J. Sihvola and T. Engberg-Pedersen (eds.), The Emotions in Hellenistic Philosophy (Dordecht, 1998), 71-111, esp. 85-90, examines the more complex, but similar, theory of 'affective motions' developed by Posidonius
    • (1998) The Emotions in Hellenistic Philosophy , pp. 71-111
    • Cooper, J.1
  • 32
    • 79954012458 scopus 로고
    • Augustine's Argument for the Existence of Other Souls
    • . 23-4
    • This is a point not made explicit by the two interesting discussions of this argument by G. Matthews, Thought's Ego in Augustine and Descartes (Ithaca, NY, 1992), ch. 9, esp. 121-3, and T. McNulty, 'Augustine's Argument for the Existence of Other Souls', The Modern Schoolman, 48 (1970), 19-24, esp. 23-4
    • (1970) The Modern Schoolman , vol.48 , pp. 19-24
    • McNulty, T.1
  • 33
    • 79954359495 scopus 로고
    • There are some interesting discussions of Augustine's views of heaven in CD 22. 29-30, most notably H, Marrou and A.-M. La Bonnardière, 'La dogme de la résurrection des corps et la théologie des valeurs humaines selon l'enseignement de saint Augustin'
    • There are some interesting discussions of Augustine's views of heaven in CD 22. 29-30, most notably H, Marrou and A.-M. La Bonnardière, 'La dogme de la résurrection des corps et la théologie des valeurs humaines selon l'enseignement de saint Augustin', Revue des études augustiniennes, 12 (1966), 111-36
    • (1966) Revue des études augustiniennes , vol.12 , pp. 111-136
  • 34
    • 79954242004 scopus 로고
    • Augustin interprète du dogme de la résurrection: Quelques aspects de son anthropologie dualiste
    • K. Börresen, 'Augustin interprète du dogme de la résurrection: Quelques aspects de son anthropologie dualiste', Studia Theologica: Scandinavian Journal of Theology, 23 (1969), 141-55
    • (1969) Studia Theologica: Scandinavian Journal of Theology , vol.23 , pp. 141-155
    • Börresen, K.1
  • 36
    • 79954248554 scopus 로고
    • The Transformation from Corpus Animale to Corpus Spirituale according to Augustine
    • and M. Alfeche, 'The Transformation from Corpus Animale to Corpus Spirituale according to Augustine', Augustiniana, 42 (1992), 239-310
    • (1992) Augustiniana , vol.42 , pp. 239-310
    • Alfeche, M.1
  • 37
    • 79954269031 scopus 로고
    • 'St. Augustine and the Vision of God'
    • F. Van Fleteren, J. Schnaubelt, and J. Reino (eds.), New York
    • see Ep. 147 and R. Teske, 'St. Augustine and the Vision of God', in F. Van Fleteren, J. Schnaubelt, and J. Reino (eds.), Collectanea Augustiniana: Augustine Mystic and Mystagogue (New York, 1994), 287-308
    • (1994) Collectanea Augustiniana: Augustine Mystic and Mystagogue , pp. 287-308
    • Teske, R.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.