-
2
-
-
79958576110
-
-
col. 570.28-624.11
-
For a review see K. Reinhardt, RE 22, 1 col. 570.28-624.11;
-
RE
, vol.22
, pp. 1
-
-
Reinhardt, K.1
-
4
-
-
0038199041
-
-
(London
-
As in Laffranque (op. cit.) or A. Long, Hellenistic Philosophy (London, 1974), pp. 216-22.
-
(1974)
Hellenistic Philosophy
, pp. 216-222
-
-
Long, A.1
-
5
-
-
79958540611
-
-
L. Edelstein and I. Kidd (Cambridge, 1972)
-
For the fragments I refer to the collection by L. Edelstein and I. Kidd (Cambridge, 1972).
-
-
-
-
6
-
-
84868750228
-
Beiträge zur Geschichte des antiken Platonismus: II. Poseidonios über die Weltseele in Platons Timaios
-
As in Ph. Merlan, 'Beiträge zur Geschichte des antiken Platonismus: II. Poseidonios über die Weltseele in Platons Timaios', Philologus 89 (1934), 197-214;
-
(1934)
Philologus
, vol.89
, pp. 197-214
-
-
Merlan, Ph.1
-
7
-
-
65849506189
-
-
The Hague
-
From Platonism to Neoplatonism (The Hague, 1953), who focuses on the mathematical definitions of soul and the ontological status of mathematics in general.
-
(1953)
From Platonism to Neoplatonism
-
-
-
9
-
-
79958515203
-
-
Ti. 45B-46C
-
In the commentary on F85 (Sext. Emp. Math. 7, 93), which deals with a theory of sense perception based on the principle of 'like known by like', cf. Ti. 45B-46C;
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
79958494106
-
-
Posidonius F193; Etym. Magn. 'sight', F194, Aet. 4, 13, 3
-
see also Posidonius F193; Etym. Magn. 'sight', F194, Aet. 4, 13, 3.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
79958644345
-
Abrégé inédit du Commentaire de Posidonius au Timée de Platon (PGen inv. 203)
-
(Firenze
-
The Sextus Empiricus fragment contains the following statement: . . ., F. Lasserre, 'Abrégé inédit du Commentaire de Posidonius au Timée de Platon (PGen inv. 203)', Accademia Toscana diScienze e Lettere, Studi 83 (Firenze, 1986), 71-127, claims to have found a summary of Posidonius' 'commentary' in the manuscript tradition.
-
(1986)
Accademia Toscana DiScienze e Lettere, Studi
, vol.83
, pp. 71-127
-
-
Lasserre, F.1
-
13
-
-
79958495285
-
-
De Piacitis 4,258.19-23. Zeno did study with Polemo
-
De Piacitis 4,258.19-23. Zeno did study with Polemo.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
79958680515
-
-
(Edelstein and Kidd F4; D.L. 7, 143) and a living, ensouled and rational being (Edelstein and Kidd F99a; D.L. 7, 142-3)
-
Along the lines of the Early Stoics and the Timaeus, Posidonius considers the universe a unity (Edelstein and Kidd F4; D.L. 7, 143) and a living, ensouled and rational being (Edelstein and Kidd F99a; D.L. 7, 142-3).
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
79958673894
-
-
475, 313 (Plutarch's critique, vide infra, 314-315; 320 (Plotinus, vide infra, 323 (Galen, 326 (corporeal matter, 336; 340 (cause is body, 343; 394; 467; 469, everything' is corporeal, 533 (corporeal matter, 793; 1028 1029; 1032; 1034 in which, curiously enough, Plato is aligned with the Stoics, 1046; 1051-3
-
At the heart of the controversy lies the fragment of Diogenes Laertius which I quote below as (1) (7, 134; SVF 2, 299; 300): the mss. tell us the principles are corporeal, the parallel Suda version says they are incorporeal. The following are fragments which call the principles corporeal: SVF 1, 90 (ambiguous, however); 98 (vide infra); 153; 2, 305 (corporeal matter); 310 (see also 475); 313 (Plutarch's critique, vide infra); 314-315; 320 (Plotinus, vide infra); 323 (Galen); 326 (corporeal matter); 336; 340 (cause is body); 343; 394; 467; 469 ('everything' is corporeal); 533 (corporeal matter); 793; 1028 1029; 1032; 1034 (in which, curiously enough, Plato is aligned with the Stoics); 1046; 1051-3.
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
84966083594
-
Archai and Stoicheia: A Problem in Stoic Cosmology
-
For a review see M. Lapidge, 'Archai and Stoicheia: A Problem in Stoic Cosmology', Phronesis 18 (1973), 240-78.
-
(1973)
Phronesis
, vol.18
, pp. 240-278
-
-
Lapidge, M.1
-
20
-
-
85163488604
-
Monism and Immanence: Foundations of Stoic Principles
-
ed. J. Rist Berkeley
-
R. Todd, 'Monism and Immanence: Foundations of Stoic Principles', in The Stoics, ed. J. Rist (Berkeley, 1978), pp. 137-60;
-
(1978)
The Stoics
, pp. 137-160
-
-
Todd, R.1
-
21
-
-
61249429870
-
Zeno of Citium
-
167ff
-
J. Mansfeld, 'Zeno of Citium', Mnemosyne 31 (1978), 162, 167ff.;
-
(1978)
Mnemosyne
, vol.31
, pp. 162
-
-
Mansfeld, J.1
-
22
-
-
0004065729
-
-
Ithaca, New York, ch. 6, esp. pp. 93-8
-
R. Sorabji, Matter, Space and Motion. Theories in Antiquity and their Sequel (Ithaca, New York, 1988), ch. 6, esp. pp. 93-8.
-
(1988)
Matter, Space and Motion. Theories in Antiquity and Their Sequel
-
-
Sorabji, R.1
-
23
-
-
79958640175
-
-
Plut. De Cominunibus Notitiis 1085b-c
-
Plut. De Cominunibus Notitiis 1085b-c.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
79958644346
-
-
Plotinus Enn. 6, 1, 26, 12ff.
-
Plotinus Enn. 6, 1, 26, 12ff.;
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
79958542853
-
-
SVF 2, 323
-
see also SVF 2, 323 on the problem of a corporeal matter.
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
79958486228
-
-
SVF 2, 467; 471
-
cf. SVF 2, 467; 471 (which presents Chrysippus' attempt at solving the problem).
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
0011705051
-
Alexander of Aphrodisias on Stoic Physics. A Study of the de Mixtione . . .
-
See also R. Todd, 'Alexander of Aphrodisias on Stoic Physics. A Study of the De Mixtione . . .', Phil Ant 28 (1976).
-
(1976)
Phil Ant
, vol.28
-
-
Todd, R.1
-
28
-
-
79958618513
-
-
See SVF 1, 90; 2, 343; 363
-
See SVF 1, 90; 2, 343; 363.
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
79958530264
-
-
Long and Sedley, pp. 273-4 commentary on the fragments; 45A = SVF 1, 90
-
Cf. Long and Sedley, pp. 273-4 (commentary on the fragments; 45A = SVF 1, 90;
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
79958533041
-
-
45B = SVF 2, 363
-
45B = SVF 2, 363).
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
79958500643
-
-
SVF 1, 171; 2, 1027; 1037 (which contrasts with); 1054; 1133; 1134
-
See, for instance, SVF 1, 171; 2, 1027; 1037 (which contrasts with); 1054; 1133; 1134.
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
79958667245
-
-
SVF 2, 311; 604; 605; 1064
-
See, for instance, SVF 2, 311; 604; 605; 1064;
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
84979434283
-
The Stoics on World-conflagration and Everlasting Recurrence
-
see also A. Long, 'The Stoics on World-conflagration and Everlasting Recurrence', Southern Journal of Philosophy Suppl. 23 (1985), 22-3.
-
(1985)
Southern Journal of Philosophy Suppl
, vol.23
, pp. 22-23
-
-
Long, A.1
-
34
-
-
79958545113
-
-
SVF 1, 134ff
-
See, for instance, SVF 1, 134ff;
-
-
-
-
35
-
-
79958647497
-
-
Kidd in his commentary on F92, 368-74
-
For a full discussion, see Kidd in his commentary on F92, 368-74.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
79958605449
-
-
(SVF 1, 85)
-
(SVF 1, 85)
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
79958612487
-
-
(SVF 1, 493)
-
(SVF 1, 493)
-
-
-
-
38
-
-
79958581814
-
-
(SVF 2, 300)
-
(SVF 2, 300)
-
-
-
-
39
-
-
79958562417
-
-
(SVF 3, Arch. 12)
-
(SVF 3, Arch. 12). I use Kidd's translations as a starting point, in order to have some common ground for the discussion. Only when I disagree on the points relevant for my discussion have I indicated alternatives between brackets.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
79958477067
-
-
SVF 1, 86-87
-
SVF 1, 86-87;
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
79958592841
-
-
Galen Meth. Med. 14; 10, 974, 15
-
Hicks in his Loeb translation takes (i) as the subject and not as the predicate and (ii) as two coinciding notions, i.e. as which is. I adhere to a different interpretation. I am gratefully indebted to J. van Winden for having engaged himself in a discussion about the issue and having strongly defended the Hicks - Waszink hypothesis, the one I am arguing against. The following are my motivations for preferring the alternative reading: (i) the no article-predicate rule, (ii) 'first matter', not matter tout court, is called 'being' here, and (iii) precisely because there is no article (cf. in contrast the Posidonius passage 2) it is hard to tell whether the two designations are coinciding or not; I take this to be anticipating the distinction made immediately following. Note that my hypothesis as a whole does not stand or fall with this reading: minimally there are two kinds of matter being distinguished. For a parallel to reading as 'something is called by two names', see Galen Meth. Med. 14; 10, 974, 15 (where it is used as an equivalent of).
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
79958640174
-
-
Long and Sedley, pp. 172-3
-
This does not have to impinge on the so-called 'Growing Argument' (cf. Long and Sedley, pp. 172-3): growth and diminishment in the case of particulars require an identity of a subject, something remaining the same throughout the process, and that identity would be due entirely to the active principle, not to the substrate. The question is whether the notion of 'becoming more or less', on the other hand, does ask for such a strong identity requirement, and whether it is to be put on the same level as 'growing and diminishing', see Posidonius F96 = Long and Sedley 28D, (5): 'The substance neither grows nor diminishes through addition or subtraction, but simply alters, just as in the case of numbers and measures.' (As with 'stuff', one can add to or subtract from numbers and measures; amounts and sizes can become more or less, but they cannot grow or diminish in the strict sense used here.)
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
79958683115
-
-
Long and Sedley 28q = SVF 1, 87 = part F92 Posidonius
-
See also Long and Sedley 28q = SVF 1, 87 = part F92 Posidonius, my passage 2, where Zeno, Chrysippus, and Posidonius are mentioned, with the claim that for Zeno the sum total of matter does not become more or less, and that for Chrysippus it does not grow and diminish (both of these being true). The latter passage is not so helpful with regard to particulars, because they are described in terms of division and fusion, which are due to the active principle, in the lines devoted to Zeno.
-
-
-
-
44
-
-
79958547979
-
-
Alcinous, Didaskalikos 162.29-39
-
See also Alcinous, Didaskalikos 162.29-39.
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
79958665272
-
-
Waszink (1962), p. xxxiv
-
and Waszink (1962), p. xxxiv, has used it for a subdivision in his outline of the structure of the text.
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
79958577293
-
-
SVF 2, 300 (D.L. 7, 134; quoted here as 2.1)
-
As Kidd himself points out, 370, 'without quality' appears in SVF 2, 300 (D.L. 7, 134; quoted here as 2.1);
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
79958606323
-
-
SVF 2, 299 (again D.L. 7, 134)
-
'without shape' (Kidd's translation,) we find in SVF 2, 299 (again D.L. 7, 134);
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
79958558329
-
-
SVF 2, 311 (Stoics in general)
-
'without shape' cf. SVF 2, 311 (Stoics in general);
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
79958680514
-
-
Cf. Baltes' commentary, PhilAnt 21 (1972), 41.
-
(1972)
PhilAnt
, vol.21
, pp. 41
-
-
Baltes1
-
51
-
-
79958529035
-
-
Seneca Ep. 65, 2ff.; 89, 16
-
Seneca Ep. 65, 2ff.; 89, 16;
-
-
-
-
52
-
-
79958534222
-
-
Stob. Ecl. 1, 13, 1
-
Stob. Ecl. 1, 13, 1;
-
-
-
-
53
-
-
79958512860
-
-
SVF 1, 89; 2, 336
-
SVF 1, 89; 2, 336;
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
79958692036
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd F95
-
Edelstein and Kidd F95;
-
-
-
-
55
-
-
79958531870
-
-
Theophrastus fr. 230 (ed. Fortenbaugh et al.)
-
Theophrastus fr. 230 (ed. Fortenbaugh et al.).
-
-
-
-
56
-
-
79958687785
-
-
Kidd 368-9
-
See Kidd 368-9;
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
79958599100
-
-
Stob. Ecl. 1.11.5
-
Stob. Ecl. 1.11.5;
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
0039578263
-
-
Berlin/Leipzig
-
H. Diels, Doxographi Graeci (Berlin/Leipzig, 1929), pp. 457-8.
-
(1929)
Doxographi Graeci
, pp. 457-458
-
-
Diels, H.1
-
62
-
-
79958605448
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd F16; D.L. 7, 135
-
Cf. Edelstein and Kidd F16; D.L. 7, 135.
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
79958642831
-
-
Kidd (commentary) F16, 126
-
Kidd (commentary) F16, 126 connects this with Plato Timaeus 53Cff.
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
79958515202
-
-
Meno 76A
-
and Meno 76A.
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
79958609172
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd F100, 101, 139
-
See Edelstein and Kidd F100, 101, 139.
-
-
-
-
66
-
-
79958518429
-
-
Note that Plutarch, 1012Dff
-
Note that Plutarch, 1012Dff., includes Xenocrates as equating 'divisible being' with the dyad (matter).
-
-
-
-
67
-
-
79958584169
-
-
D.L. 7,150
-
See also D.L. 7,150, where prime matter/substance is called 'limited'.
-
-
-
-
68
-
-
67649862854
-
La théorie stoïcienne du genre suprême et l'ontologie platonicienne
-
ed. J. Barnes and M. Mignucci, Naples
-
See J. Brunschwig, 'La théorie stoïcienne du genre suprême et l'ontologie platonicienne', Matter and Metaphysics, Fourth Symposium Hellenisticum, Elenchos 14 (ed. J. Barnes and M. Mignucci, Naples 1988), pp. 19-127.
-
(1988)
Matter and Metaphysics, Fourth Symposium Hellenisticum, Elenchos
, vol.14
, pp. 19-127
-
-
Brunschwig, J.1
-
69
-
-
79958502958
-
-
Brunschwig, pp. 42-60
-
In the Stoic view of the world two kinds of things have reality value and fall under the general heading of 'something': bodies and the incorporeal space, void, time, and the ('meaning', 'sayable'). On the one hand, the combination of both 'in thought' and 'in reality' seems particularly suited to describe the admittedly awkward category of incorporeals that, unlike mere constructs of the mind such as universals, do have objective reality value, but not in the strong sense of bodies. On the other hand, the 'limits' are granted 'being' in Plutarch's passage, as Posidonius' interpretation of Plato's 'divisible Being'. Strictly speaking the Stoics consider only bodies and not the incorporeals as entitled to being. (Brunschwig, pp. 42-60, discusses and dismisses apparent exceptions, including Seneca's claim, Epistulae 58, 22, that the void and time are quasi being - quae quasi sunt). All of this evidence once again points towards a corporeal matter, as is also indicated by the context of Plutarch's passage about Posidonius and his followers, 1022F.
-
-
-
-
70
-
-
79958628371
-
-
(1013C, 1014F, Plutarch's corporeal matter bears the 'traces' of the elements (1016D-E; Timaeus 52D-53B)
-
At first glance Plutarch himself appears to be oscillating between a corporeal matter (cf. Cherniss' list of passages, in his Loeb edition, 185 n.c), and one that is strictly qualityless and hence derives its sensible features from a participation in the intelligible (1013C, 1014F). Plutarch's corporeal matter bears the 'traces' of the elements (1016D-E; Timaeus 52D-53B);
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
79958620853
-
-
(Doxographi Graeci 308 A4 9, B5 9)
-
matter in its basic sense is qualityless (51 A; 52A), but the matter the Demiurge structures does already have some features (see also 30A). This tension is present in Plato's own text, though Plutarch takes it further. Cherniss notes that Plutarch borrows Stoic terminology to talk about matter, as in 1014B, 180 n.b., and 1014C, 183 n.d.; the Stoics are mentioned at 1015B as using. On p. 185 n.c. Cherniss also draws attention to a passage from the Placila (Doxographi Graeci 308 A4 9, B5 9)in which the Platonic receptacle is called, in the Stoic vein.
-
-
-
-
72
-
-
84868727713
-
-
definition to Speusippus (Tarán F54a-b; Lang fr. 40). Tarán (365-71; contra Merlan et al.) defends the hypothesis that Speusippus used this definition as an interpretation of the Timaeus (35A7, where 'does not mean idea at all'; 36E2)
-
The intriguing point is that Iamblichus ascribes this definition to Speusippus (Tarán F54a-b; Lang fr. 40). Tarán (365-71; contra Merlan et al.) defends the hypothesis that Speusippus used this definition as an interpretation of the Timaeus (35A7, where 'does not mean "idea" at all'; 36E2) and as a defence of Plato against Aristotle, without necessarily adhering to it himself.
-
-
-
-
73
-
-
79958678744
-
-
Ciceronis Somnium Scipionis 1, 14, 19
-
Although I do not consider as sufficient evidence the fact that Macrobius attributes the term to Posidonius, in his Commentarii in Ciceronis Somnium Scipionis 1, 14, 19;
-
-
-
-
74
-
-
79958517252
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd F140
-
Edelstein and Kidd F140.
-
-
-
-
75
-
-
79958551146
-
-
Merlan (1934) and Kidd in his commentary on F141, 533-5
-
For the entire mathematical definition and its Old Academy heritage, see Merlan (1934) and Kidd in his commentary on F141, 533-5.
-
-
-
-
76
-
-
79958685119
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd (commentary 150-1) F 28a, b
-
A physical variant of this tenet for the human soul makes it extend even through the bones of the human body and connects this with the Timaeus 73B, where it is said that the soul's bonds are in the roots of the bone. Cf. Edelstein and Kidd (commentary 150-1) F 28a, b;
-
-
-
-
77
-
-
79958618512
-
-
Scholia in Homerum; Eust. Il. 12, 386
-
Scholia in Homerum; Eust. Il. 12, 386.
-
-
-
-
78
-
-
79958561211
-
-
4, 1, 2 (Berlin, 1978)
-
De Placitis, mainly books 3-5 (up to 336.15) in the edition of Ph. De Lacey, Corpus Medicorum Graecorum 5, 4, 1, 2 (Berlin, 1978).
-
Corpus Medicorum Graecorum
, pp. 5
-
-
De Lacey, Ph.1
-
80
-
-
79958634950
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd F147
-
Edelstein and Kidd F147.
-
-
-
-
81
-
-
79958571376
-
-
Galen De Placitis 5, 312.29-34
-
Galen De Placitis 5, 312.29-34.
-
-
-
-
82
-
-
60950439733
-
Poetry and the Passions: Two Stoic Views, Passions and Perceptions. Studies in Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind
-
ed. J. Brunschwig and M. Nussbaum, Cambridge
-
I am gratefully indebted to David Blank for drawing my attention to the debate about the Stoic Diogenes of Babylon; see M. Nussbaum, 'Poetry and the Passions: Two Stoic Views', Passions and Perceptions. Studies in Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind; Proceedings of the Fifth Symposium Hellenisticum (ed. J. Brunschwig and M. Nussbaum) (Cambridge, 1993), pp. 97-149.
-
(1993)
Proceedings of the Fifth Symposium Hellenisticum
, pp. 97-149
-
-
Nussbaum, M.1
-
83
-
-
79958520835
-
The Harmonics of Stoic Virtue
-
If, as Nussbaum claims, Diogenes' interest in music and poetry foreshadows Posidonius' doctrine, and if, indeed, Diogenes prepares the ground for Posidonius' revision of Stoic psychology, then we have yet another reason for breaking through Galen's ideological marshalling of Posidonius as a radical reformer. Two remarks are appropriate here: (a) I believe that Posidonius' position of allocating three faculties to one and the same soul substance is considerably weaker than a full-fledged return to Plato's doctrine of a tripartite soul; (b.1) Diogenes' musical theory might be 'non-cognitive' or irrational in the sense that it focuses on the senses, which are instrumental to the, but this position is still essentially different from a non-cognitive approach which assigns irrational faculties to the soul's ruling component itself, and it also has to be noted that perception is cognitive for the Stoics; (b.2) this point is related to the question whether any model of the impact of musical harmony on the soul necessarily presupposes this soul to be composite, in Plato's or Posidonius' sense. For a theory of musical harmony which is compatible with a unitary soul, see A. Long, 'The Harmonics of Stoic Virtue', Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Suppl. (1991), 97-116.
-
(1991)
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Suppl.
, pp. 97-116
-
-
Long, A.1
-
84
-
-
84868769545
-
Le De Ira de Sénèque et la théorie stoïcienne des passions
-
Paris
-
For a more extended argument concerning the points of similarity between Chrysippus and Posidonius, see J. Fillion-Lahille, 'Le De Ira de Sénèque et la théorie stoïcienne des passions'. Etudes et Commentates 94 (Paris 1984), 119-62.
-
(1984)
Etudes et Commentates
, vol.94
, pp. 119-162
-
-
Fillion-Lahille, J.1
-
85
-
-
34548739373
-
The Idea of the Will in Chrysippus, Posidonius and Galen
-
(ed. J. Cleary, published Lanham
-
Cf. J. Mansfeld, 'The Idea of the Will in Chrysippus, Posidonius and Galen', Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 7 (ed. J. Cleary, 1991, published Lanham, 1993), 124.
-
(1991)
Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy
, vol.7
, pp. 124
-
-
Mansfeld, J.1
-
86
-
-
79958511108
-
-
De Placitis 5, 318.13-14
-
Galen himself makes this slip, see for instance De Placitis 5, 318.13-14.
-
-
-
-
87
-
-
79958474294
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd F186
-
See also, for instance, infra, Edelstein and Kidd F186;
-
-
-
-
88
-
-
79958512228
-
-
Ciem. Al. Strom. 2, 21, 129.1-5 (text 9)
-
Ciem. Al. Strom. 2, 21, 129.1-5 (text 9).
-
-
-
-
89
-
-
79958683114
-
-
Op. cit., pp. 33-4
-
Op. cit., pp. 33-4.
-
-
-
-
90
-
-
79958501816
-
-
Simpl., SVF 3, 203
-
Simpl., SVF 3, 203;
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
79958522382
-
-
Philo, SVF 2, 844
-
Philo, SVF 2, 844;
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
79958558328
-
-
Arius Didymus, SVF 3, 112
-
Arius Didymus, SVF 3, 112.
-
-
-
-
93
-
-
79958505553
-
-
De Placitis 5, 305.18-27
-
De Placitis 5, 305.18-27.
-
-
-
-
94
-
-
79958603099
-
Posidonian Polemic and Academic Dialectic: The Impact of Carneades upon Posidonius
-
In a recent article, 'Posidonian Polemic and Academic Dialectic: The Impact of Carneades upon Posidonius', Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 34 (1993), 229-323, John A. Stevens goes an important step further. He claims (p. 322) that Posidonius himself 'attributes to Chrysippus subtly altered representations of Carneades' views'. But this apparent concession to the skeptics' criticisms is in fact motivated by Posidonius' attempt to salvage core Stoic doctrine by drawing on common sense experience about the nature of the soul and irrational behaviour. If Stevens is right, we have yet another, deeper-level manipulation of Chrysippus' views, one by Posidonius, that is embedded within Galen's own purposes.
-
(1993)
Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies
, vol.34
, pp. 229-323
-
-
-
95
-
-
79958638785
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd F31
-
See Edelstein and Kidd F31;
-
-
-
-
96
-
-
79958655823
-
-
Galen De Placitis 5, 322.28-326.8
-
Galen De Placitis 5, 322.28-326.8;
-
-
-
-
97
-
-
79958680513
-
-
F33, Galen De Placitis 5, 332.31-334.10
-
F33, Galen De Placitis 5, 332.31-334.10.
-
-
-
-
98
-
-
79958582938
-
-
Ti 77B
-
Posidonius uses for his description of the lowest category of animals a terminology which is reminiscent of Plato's account of plants (cf. Ti 77B).
-
-
-
-
99
-
-
79958511107
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd (commentary) F31, 155.162
-
In the Timaeus (44B), too, reason, in connection with its cognitive circular motions, is said to start out weak in children; cf. Edelstein and Kidd (commentary) F31, 155.162.
-
-
-
-
100
-
-
0003437293
-
Animal Minds and Human Morals
-
Ithaca, NY
-
For the case of animals, see the excellent analysis by R. Sorabji, 'Animal Minds and Human Morals', Cornell Studies in Classical Philology 54 (Ithaca, NY, 1993).
-
(1993)
Cornell Studies in Classical Philology
, pp. 54
-
-
Sorabji, R.1
-
101
-
-
79958649647
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd (commentary) F 31, 156; 158-160
-
See Edelstein and Kidd (commentary) F 31, 156; 158-160, which also indicates that even in his use of the Phaedrus image, Posidonius borrowed terminology from the Timaeus.
-
-
-
-
102
-
-
79958562416
-
-
De Placitis 5, 460-3
-
De Placitis 5, 460-3.
-
-
-
-
103
-
-
79958534220
-
-
Rist (1969), p. 212
-
See Rist (1969), p. 212; I do disagree with Rist, however, that this needs to lead to a strong dualistic view of the human soul. See also part iv of this paper.
-
-
-
-
105
-
-
67649833053
-
Posidonius' "hierarchy" between God, Fate and Nature and Cicero's de Divinatione'
-
and M. Dragona-Monachou, 'Posidonius' "hierarchy" between God, Fate and Nature and Cicero's De Divinatione', Philosophia 4 (1974), 286-301.
-
(1974)
Philosophia
, vol.4
, pp. 286-301
-
-
Dragona-Monachou, M.1
-
106
-
-
79958610336
-
-
Kidd (commentary) thinks that Posidonius' (F108; Cic. Div. 1, 64)
-
Kidd (commentary) thinks that Posidonius' (F108; Cic. Div. 1, 64) view of our minds being capable of divination because of reason, i.e. our kinship with the divine, stands in conscious opposition to the Timaeus 71D-72B, where divination is an essentially irrational process.
-
-
-
-
108
-
-
77949367251
-
The Philosophical System of Posidonius
-
292f, 301-5
-
L. Edelstein, 'The Philosophical System of Posidonius', AJP 57 (1936), 292f, 301-5.
-
(1936)
AJP
, vol.57
-
-
Edelstein, L.1
-
109
-
-
79958633783
-
-
SVF 1, 85; 2, 299 (not 229 as in Kidd 104)
-
F5; SVF 1, 85; 2, 299 (not 229 as in Kidd 104);
-
-
-
-
110
-
-
79958660959
-
-
D.L. 7, 134
-
D.L. 7, 134.
-
-
-
-
111
-
-
79958614866
-
-
Rist 1969, p. 211
-
Rist (1969), p. 211.
-
-
-
-
112
-
-
79958608748
-
-
Op. cit., pp. 340, 351
-
Op. cit., pp. 340, 351.
-
-
-
-
113
-
-
79958642830
-
-
Op. cit., p. 292, and throughout her argumentation
-
Op. cit., p. 292, and throughout her argumentation.
-
-
-
-
114
-
-
79958502956
-
-
Cic. Div. 1, 131
-
See Cic. Div. 1, 131:'. . ., cum domus sit omnium una, eaque communis,...'
-
-
-
-
117
-
-
79958525869
-
-
Op.cit., pp.300-1
-
Op.cit., pp.300-1.
-
-
-
-
118
-
-
79958511106
-
-
SVF 1, 179ff
-
cf. SVF 1, 179ff.
-
-
-
-
119
-
-
79958628368
-
-
SVF 3, 4 - D. L. 7. 87-8 = Long and Sedley 63C
-
SVF 3, 4 - D. L. 7. 87-8 = Long and Sedley 63C.
-
-
-
-
120
-
-
79958488638
-
-
Kidd (commentary on F187; 677), against for instance Edelstein (1936, 314) and Rist (1969, 212)
-
and Kidd (commentary on F187; 677), against for instance Edelstein (1936, 314) and Rist (1969, 212), that this passage does not necessarily imply we also have an evil demon, in the irrational part of our soul, a theory which would turn Posidonius into more of a dualist.
-
-
-
-
121
-
-
79958520834
-
-
Edelstein and Kidd F85
-
See also Edelstein and Kidd F85.
-
-
-
-
122
-
-
79958618511
-
-
Tht. 176B
-
See also Tht. 176B, for the theme of.
-
-
-
-
123
-
-
79958597953
-
-
Kidd commentary 669-78
-
Kidd (commentary 669-78).
-
-
-
-
124
-
-
79958671178
-
-
Compare and contrast also Xenocrates fr. 81 (ed. Heinze; Aristotle Topics 2, 6, 112a32)
-
Compare and contrast also Xenocrates fr. 81 (ed. Heinze; Aristotle Topics 2, 6, 112a32): 'as Xenocrates says, happy is the man who has his soul in good condition. For that (the soul) is each man's daimon.' Notice that here, however, the soul in its entirety is our daimon.
-
-
-
-
125
-
-
79958605445
-
-
Kidd, pp. 672-3
-
instead of. See Kidd, pp. 672-3, for a discussion of the problems with this reading.
-
-
-
-
126
-
-
79958626221
-
-
Rist 1969, pp. 214-15
-
Rist (1969), pp. 214-15.
-
-
-
-
127
-
-
79958663741
-
-
(62C = SVF 2.974) in connection with Alexander of Aphrodisias On Fate 181.13-182.20 (62G = SVF 2.979)
-
For a discussion of the Cicero passage (62C = SVF 2.974) in connection with Alexander of Aphrodisias On Fate 181.13-182.20 (62G = SVF 2.979),
-
-
-
-
128
-
-
79958557139
-
-
Long and Sedley, commentary, pp. 392-1
-
see Long and Sedley, commentary, pp. 392-1.
-
-
-
-
129
-
-
79958586746
-
-
University of Leiden, The Netherlands, in June of 1994, and at Cornell University, on February 2, 1996
-
I presented a version of this paper at the University of Leiden, The Netherlands, in June of 1994, and at Cornell University, on February 2, 1996. The paper has greatly benefited from both audiences, and from the comments of the people I thanked in the footnotes, among whom Anthony Long and John Dillon, who saw me through the entire process and let the disagreements stand. Many essential final touches were added during my stay at the 'Fondation Hardt' in Geneva, May 20-June 8, 1996, made possible by a grant from the University of Notre Dame Institute for Scholarship in the Liberal Arts. I also would like to thank Kenneth Sayre and the reader of the journal.
-
-
-
|