메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 11, Issue 1, 2003, Pages 121-127

On Reid's 'Inconsistent Triad': A Reply to McDermid

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61249729402     PISSN: 09608788     EISSN: 14693526     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/0960878032000058491     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (5)

References (16)
  • 2
    • 40449121167 scopus 로고
    • sixth edn. (Edinburgh)
    • Reid gives his three arguments in the fourth of his Essays on the Active Powers of the Human Mind, which is entitled 'Of the Liberty of Moral Agents'. Unless otherwise indicated, all quotations will be from this essay, and the edition I shall use is Sir William Hamilton (ed.), The Works of Thomas Reid, sixth edn. (Edinburgh. 1868). Page numbers will be given in the main body of the text, with an 'a' or a 'b' to indicate, respectively, the left and right-hand columns of Hamilton's text.
    • (1868) The Works of Thomas Reid
    • Hamilton, W.1
  • 6
    • 60949546441 scopus 로고
    • Causality and Agency in the Philosophy of Thomas Reid
    • M. Dalgarno and E. Matthews (eds), (Dordrecht)
    • On agent causation and common sense, see Richard Stalley, 'Causality and Agency in the Philosophy of Thomas Reid', in M. Dalgarno and E. Matthews (eds), The Philosophy of Thomas Reid (Dordrecht, 1989);
    • (1989) The Philosophy of Thomas Reid
    • Stalley, R.1
  • 7
    • 33746122860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford, ch. 5
    • and on agent causation and reasons explanations, see Timothy O'Connor, Persons and Causes (Oxford, 2000), ch. 5.
    • (2000) Persons and Causes
    • O'Connor, T.1
  • 8
    • 80054239234 scopus 로고
    • Reid's Definition of Freedom
    • Stephen F. Barker and Tom L. Beauchamp eds, Philadelphia
    • For one reply to the infinite regress objection, see Jerome Weinstock, 'Reid's Definition of Freedom', in Stephen F. Barker and Tom L. Beauchamp (eds), Thomas Reid: Critical Interpretations (Philadelphia, 1976).
    • (1976) Thomas Reid: Critical Interpretations
    • Weinstock, J.1
  • 11
    • 0009280822 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca
    • William Rowe also believes that Reid's argument is meant as a direct proof of the reality of moral liberty. Like McDermid, he suggests that the arguments be supplemented with an additional premise to the effect that fundamental principles of our constitution are true: see Thomas Reid on Freedom and Morality (Ithaca, 1991), 103-111.
    • (1991) Thomas Reid on Freedom and Morality , pp. 103-111
  • 12
    • 80054224110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Active Power and the Liberty of Moral Agents
    • This is the interpretation I believe to be the correct one, so long as the inconsistency is understood to be between the necessitarian's theoretical beliefs and the beliefs implicit in his practice. Timothy Duggan seems to me exactly right when he says that 'Reid's first argument . is not, in fact, an argument in support of the thesis that man is endowed with moral liberty. It is. rather, an argument in support of the claim that this thesis is a first principle of contingent truth': see 'Active Power and the Liberty of Moral Agents', in Barker and Beauchamp (eds), Thomas Reid: Critical Interpretations, 107.
    • Thomas Reid: Critical Interpretations , pp. 107
    • Barker1    Beauchamp2
  • 13
    • 0008407848 scopus 로고
    • (Edinburgh)
    • For Karnes's argument, see his Essays on the Principles of Morality and Natural Religion (Edinburgh, 1751), 151-218. He retracts the hypothesis of a deceitful sense in the second edition of 1758, adopting there a straightforwardly compatibilist view of moral responsibility.
    • (1751) Principles of Morality and Natural Religion , pp. 151-218
  • 14
    • 80054239225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It could alternatively be construed as an ad hominem argument, as is noted by Duggan: that is, as 'directed against those who wish to maintain both that man lacks power over the determinations of his will and is, nonetheless, accountable for his actions' ('Active Power and Moral Agents', 108).
    • Active Power and Moral Agents , pp. 108
  • 15
    • 42149103476 scopus 로고
    • 2nd edn, Birmingham
    • However, Reid shows himself aware that at least some necessitarians were willing to accept that their doctrine is at odds with accountability as normally construed: see 618a, where he quotes Priestley to the effect that, on the doctrine of necessity, men 'cannot accuse themselves as having done anything wrong, in the ultimate sense of the word'. (This passage is from Priestley's The Doctrine of Philosophical Necessity Illustrated, 2nd edn, Birmingham, 1782, 147.) Reid regards Priestley's views on this matter as plainly absurd.
    • (1782) The Doctrine of Philosophical Necessity Illustrated , pp. 147
    • Priestley1
  • 16
    • 80054239225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I think Reid would allow that the evidence of liberty of will in purposive action is only prima facie evidence: it remains possible that, despite appearances, the agent is in the grip of some compulsion or neurosis, such that, in fact, his will is not in his power (see Duggan, 'Active Power and Moral Agents', 108)
    • Active Power and Moral Agents , pp. 108
    • Duggan1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.