메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 10, Issue 3, 2002, Pages 235-263

Prospects for a naturalization of practical reason: Humean instrumentalism and the normative authority of desire

Author keywords

Desire; Hedonism; Hume; Naturalism; Pleasure; Rationality

Indexed keywords


EID: 61249651107     PISSN: 09672559     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/09672550210152104     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (18)

References (45)
  • 1
    • 79953638042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophical Naturalism at the Turn of the Century
    • The notion of naturalism is not altogether clear, but the use made of it in this paper is broad enough to avoid presuppositions that should not be made here. I have indicated various ways it may be construed in 'Philosophical Naturalism at the Turn of the Century', Journal of Philosophical Research, 95 (2000).
    • (2000) Journal of Philosophical Research , pp. 95
  • 2
    • 53249141037 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press, esp. chs 4-6
    • Richard Fumerton, Reason and Morality (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990), esp. chs 4-6
    • (1990) Reason and Morality
    • Fumerton, R.1
  • 4
    • 79953510695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Humean Doubts about the Practical Justification of Morality
    • Peter Railton
    • For a broad characterization of instrumentalism and responses to it, see the introduction by Cullity and Gaut. The papers by James Dreier - 'Humean Doubts about the Practical Justification of Morality' - and Peter Railton - 'On the Hypothetical and Non-Hypothetical in Reasoning about Belief and Action' - defend certain elements of instrumentalism, and Dreier's brings out the limitations of instrumentalism as a route to providing reasons to be moral (or alternatively, 'justifying morality').
    • On the Hypothetical and Non-Hypothetical in Reasoning about Belief and Action
    • Dreier, J.1
  • 5
    • 79953520638 scopus 로고
    • Practical Theory
    • Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Cullity's 'Practical Theory' critically examines Bernard Williams's well-known version tracing to his much-discussed 'Internal and External Reasons', in his Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981);
    • (1981) Internal and External Reasons
  • 6
    • 79953607475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Gaut's "The Structure of Practical Reason' assesses a Kantian constructivist response to instrumentalism (represented in the volume by Christine Korsgaard's paper), and sketches a broadly Aristotelian alternative to both.
    • The Structure of Practical Reason
  • 7
    • 0009205905 scopus 로고
    • Acting for Reasons
    • These five kinds of reasons are introduced and discussed in my 'Acting for Reasons', Philosophical Review, 95 (1986)
    • (1986) Philosophical Review , pp. 95
  • 8
    • 0004281265 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press
    • reprinted in my Action, Intention, and Reason (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1993)
    • (1993) Action, Intention, and Reason
  • 9
    • 0038474856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford and New York
    • and, in a different way, in The Architecture of Reason (Oxford and New York: 2001), esp. ch. 5, on which this paper draws significantly. 1 might add that since motivating reasons as here described operate in producing or sustaining action, one might also call them activating reasons; and since subjective reasons may or may not activate behaviour, but are the appropriate kind to motivate it, one could call them motivational as opposed to motivating. We could also distinguish a sixth variety: inclining reasons, those that produce a tendency to act, and are in that sense (causally) operative, but do not yield action itself. But for our purposes there is no need to complicate the terminology in the text.
    • (2001) The Architecture of Reason
  • 10
    • 79953481483 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1888). The famous claim is on p. 415, the point about strength of mind on p. 418.
    • (1888) A Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 418
    • Selby-Bigge, L.A.1
  • 11
    • 24944472981 scopus 로고
    • Rationalization and Rationality
    • Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Two points of clarification will help. First, I assume for the sake of argument that we may speak of combined desire strengths at least in a way that enables us to make comparative determinations of strength. Second, my focus is the rationality of an action for S, not S's acting rationally; I take the latter to be more complex, requiring that the action be based on the reason(s) in virtue of which it is rational. Supporting argument on the latter point is given in my 'Rationalization and Rationality', in my The Structure of Justification (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) The Structure of Justification
  • 12
    • 4444231038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Groundless Normativity of Instrumental Rationality
    • For a naturalistic defence of a neo-Humean position on practical reason which takes advisability into account, see Donald C. Hubin, 'The Groundless Normativity of Instrumental Rationality', Journal of Philosophy, 98 (9) (2001).
    • (2001) Journal of Philosophy , vol.98 , pp. 9
    • Hubin, D.C.1
  • 13
    • 33746118955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Instrumentalism
    • forthcoming in Elijah Milligram (ed.)
    • For a defence of instrumentalism that stresses the idea of what we intrinsically want as 'dear to our heart', see Christoph Fehige, 'Instrumentalism', forthcoming in Elijah Milligram (ed.) Varieties of Practical Reasoning.
    • Varieties of Practical Reasoning
    • Fehige, C.1
  • 14
    • 0004053964 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • For a plausible attempt to present a detailed naturalistic epistemology see Alvin I. Goldman, Epistemology and Cognition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986).
    • (1986) Epistemology and Cognition
    • Goldman, A.I.1
  • 15
    • 79953388072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Structure of Justification
    • esp. chs 6, 10, and 12, and, forthcoming in Philosophical Topics
    • I have critically appraised the attempt to naturalize epistemology in The Structure of Justification, esp. chs 6, 10, and 12, and in 'An Internalist Theory of Normative Grounds', forthcoming in Philosophical Topics.
    • An Internalist Theory of Normative Grounds
  • 16
    • 84884050171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp. ch. 4
    • An important question that arises here is how, if at all, a self-concept must enter into the object of desire. 1 have discussed this in detail in The Architecture of Reason, esp. ch. 4.
    • The Architecture of Reason
  • 17
    • 79953357150 scopus 로고
    • Self-Notions
    • Questions about how conceptions of the self enter into prepositional attitudes are also treated in detail in the work of John Perry. For a short statement of his position on some of the central issues, see his 'Self-Notions', Logos, 11 (1990).P. 399.
    • (1990) Logos , vol.11 , pp. 399
  • 18
    • 0003743258 scopus 로고
    • e.g., of the reprint of the 1777 edition (La Salle, IL: Open Court)
    • There are also hedonistic passages in An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. See, e.g., p. 134 of the reprint of the 1777 edition (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1960).
    • (1960) An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals , pp. 134
  • 19
    • 79953567025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethical Naturalism and the Explanatory Power of Moral Concepts
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • I have discussed the possibility of naturalizing moral properties, including those which apparently normative content, such as a belief that one ought (morally) to do something, in 'Ethical Naturalism and the Explanatory Power of Moral Concepts', reprinted in my Moral Knowledge and Ethical Character (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
    • (1997) Moral Knowledge and Ethical Character
  • 20
    • 0003672012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • For related discussion of what naturalism requires in the case of mental and physical properties, see, e.g., Jaegwon Kim, Mind in a Physical World (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998)
    • (1998) Mind in A Physical World
    • Kim, J.1
  • 22
    • 79953537665 scopus 로고
    • None but a fool or a madman would ever pretend to dispute the authority of experience or to reject that great guide of human life
    • Indianapolis: Hacket
    • In ch. 2 of Practical Reasoning I have discussed and clarified Hume's position on rational action, which is subtler than this quotation suggests. It is noteworthy that (as one might expect from the hedonistic elements in his work) he seems to think there are some common-sense grounds for criticizing even logically unobjectionable beliefs that go against experience. He says, e.g., that 'none but a fool or a madman would ever pretend to dispute the authority of experience or to reject that great guide of human life'. See An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Eric Steinberg (Indianapolis: Hacket, 1977), p. 23. It appears that Hume has in mind normative authority here, and one might think he might say something similar about experience as a guide to logically and instrumentally unobjectionable intrinsic desires.
    • (1977) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding , pp. 23
    • Steinberg, E.1
  • 23
    • 0003596242 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • The term occurs in G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (Oxford: Blackwell, 1957), but the idea is at least as old as Aquinas's (Aristotelian) view that we want things under the aspect of the good.
    • (1957) Intention
    • Anscombe, G.E.M.1
  • 24
    • 79955265102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The appetitive power is the appetible good, which varies in kind according to its various relations to reason
    • Thomas Aquinas comes to mind here. His overall view is ramified and complex, but it includes many far-reaching points in the vicinity of the view cited in the text; e.g. that 'the object of the appetitive power is the appetible good, which varies in kind according to its various relations to reason' (Summa Theologiae, Q. 60, Art. 1, Reply Obj. 1);
    • Summa Theologiae , pp. 60
    • Aquinas, T.1
  • 26
    • 79955153903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Treatise, p. 414.
    • Treatise , pp. 414
  • 27
    • 79953571774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Concept of Wanting
    • I argue for this in 'The Concept of Wanting', in my Action, Intention, and Reason, cited above.
    • Action, Intention, and Reason
  • 28
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • I am here allowing that an intrinsic good might 'provide' a reason without constituting one. Suppose, e.g., that we adopt T. M. Scanlon's 'buck-passing' view of goodness and value (hence presumably of basic reasons for action as well), on which reasons are constituted by the specific things in virtue of which something is good - say, being enjoyable - not by its goodness as such. See What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), esp. pp. 95-100.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other , pp. 95-100
  • 29
    • 0003794871 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Hume appears to do this, for reasons I have indicated in ch. 2 of Practical Reasoning. Certainly R. B. Brandt does it in A Theory of the Good and the Right (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979).
    • (1979) A Theory of the Good and the Right
    • Brandt, R.B.1
  • 31
    • 79955202595 scopus 로고
    • Weakness of Will and Rational Action
    • Intention, and Reason (originally published)
    • I have defended this kind of view of normative belief in relation to action in, e.g., 'Weakness of Will and Rational Action', in my Action, Intention, and Reason (originally published in Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 68 (1990), pp. 270-81).
    • (1990) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.68 , pp. 270-281
  • 32
    • 23944521540 scopus 로고
    • Memorial Justification
    • Granted there are cases in which we apparently know something from memory even when we have forgotten our grounds; but 1 believe that knowledge and justification are different in this respect, as I argue in 'Memorial Justification', Philosophical Topics, 23 (1995), pp. 31-45. Thus, even if a memory belief meets the defeating condition described in the text, it may still constitute knowledge; but 1 take this to be compatible with failure to be rational or confer rationality on any belief based on it.
    • (1995) Philosophical Topics , vol.23 , pp. 31-45
  • 33
    • 79953553286 scopus 로고
    • sect. 391, London: Hutchinson
    • As Kant put it in one place, 'we should be able to show at the same time [i.e., in a critique of practical reason] the unity of practical and theoretical reason in a common principle, since in the end there can be only one and the same reason, which must be differentiated solely in its application'. See Groundwork of the Metophysic of Morals, sect. 391, trans. H. J. Paton (London: Hutchinson, 1948), p. 59.
    • (1948) Groundwork of the Metophysic of Morals , pp. 59
    • Paton, H.J.1
  • 34
    • 0004221781 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Macmillan)
    • For a good survey of views on the nature of pleasure see William P. Alston's article on pleasure in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967).
    • (1967) The Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Alston, W.P.1
  • 35
    • 79953418025 scopus 로고
    • Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe
    • This point will not seem plausible if one does not distinguish dispositional propositional attitudes from dispositions to form them. For a theory of the difference and a case for positing fewer of the former and more of the latter, see my 'Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe', Nous, 28 (1994).
    • (1994) Nous , pp. 28
  • 36
    • 79953527989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say 'normally' because a belief can be induced by, say, brain manipulation. 1 should add that the relevant experience includes belief formation or contemplation of one's beliefs or their propositional objects: this can be crucial for inferential, as opposed to experiential, belief formation. The suggested discriminative-response theory of belief formation (which I merely sketch here) is introduced and defended in 'Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe'.
    • Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe
  • 37
    • 0004083939 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • For a discussion bearing on this problem (but not, I think, solving it), see Robert Nozick, The Nature of Rationality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), esp. pp. 133-51.
    • (1993) The Nature of Rationality , pp. 133-151
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 38
    • 2942697575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, esp. the essays in Part I
    • For a well-developed pragmatic naturalism with much attention to practical reason, see, e.g., Gilbert Harman, Reasoning, Meaning, and Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), esp. the essays in Part I.
    • (1999) Reasoning, Meaning, and Mind
    • Harman, G.1
  • 39
    • 79955312798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp. ch. 8
    • It is important to note that the failure of naturalization in the domain of practical reason would not entail its failure with respect to the mental, even in the strong sense in which that entails a strong version of physicalism about phenomenal properties. For instance, John Perry's 'antecedent' physicalism might still be maintained. For a recent statement see his Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness, esp. ch. 8.
    • Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness
  • 40
    • 79953456563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethical Naturalism and the Explanatory Power of Moral Properties
    • Moreover, moral properties need not be natu-ralizable in order for moral explanations to be. For an account of how the latter is possible despite the apparent impossibility of the former, see my 'Ethical Naturalism and the Explanatory Power of Moral Properties', in Moral Knowledge.
    • Moral Knowledge
  • 41
    • 0003541293 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • A widely discussed difficulty is the Frege-Geach problem, concerning the (apparently propositional) behaviour of normative sentences in conditionals. For a sophisticated contemporary statement of noncognitivism see Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990).
    • (1990) Wise Choices, Apt Feelings
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 42
    • 26644452454 scopus 로고
    • Some Problems for Gibbard's Norm-Expressivism
    • For criticism of Gibbard's position, see Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, 'Some Problems for Gibbard's Norm-Expressivism', Philosophical Studies, 69 (1993);
    • (1993) Philosophical Studies , pp. 69
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, W.1
  • 43
    • 26644445133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Expressivism and Irrationality
    • Mark van Roojen, 'Expressivism and Irrationality', Philosophical Review, 105 (1996), pp. 311-33 (a critique of Simon Blackburn's noncognitivism more than of Gibbard's);
    • (1996) Philosophical Review , vol.105 , pp. 311-333
    • Van Roojen, M.1
  • 44
    • 34248751358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Transforming Expressivism
    • and James Dreier, 'Transforming Expressivism', Nous, 33 (4) (1999), pp. 558-72.
    • (1999) Nous , vol.33 , Issue.4 , pp. 558-572
    • Dreier, J.1
  • 45
    • 79953617143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This paper was originally written for a conference on practical reason at the University of Munich. A later draft was delivered at the annual meeting of the Italian Society for Analytic Philosophy in 2000, and various versions were read at the following universities: Brown, Georgia State, Indiana, Missouri, Nebraska, Rome, St Andrews, St Louis, and Washington. I am grateful to colleagues and students in these audiences for helpful reactions, and for a number of critical comments 1 thank Roger Crisp, Jamie Dreier, Brad Hooker, and Ernest Sosa.
    • (2000) The Annual Meeting of the Italian Society for Analytic Philosophy


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.