메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 4, Issue 2, 1996, Pages 367-380

Mill on virtue as a part of happiness

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61249339287     PISSN: 09608788     EISSN: 14693526     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/09608789608570946     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (5)

References (12)
  • 1
    • 0004247732 scopus 로고
    • J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism, ed. Mary Warnock (London: Fontana, 1962), chap. IV. References to this text are to chapters and paragraphs
    • (1962) Utilitarianism
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 2
    • 0009266910 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press
    • F. Berger, Happiness, Justice, and Freedom (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1984)
    • (1984) Happiness, Justice, and Freedom
    • Berger, F.1
  • 3
    • 0009304994 scopus 로고
    • Remarks on Bentham's philosophy
    • J. S. Mill, 'Remarks on Bentham's philosophy', in Collected Works, ed. J. Robson (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), vol. X, 12-13
    • (1969) Collected Works , vol.10 , pp. 12-13
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 4
    • 79956675027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Bentham', Collected Works X, 95-6. It should be noted that Mill says of this desire that it is 'without hope of good . . . from other source than [the agent's] own inward consciousness'
    • Collected Works , vol.10 , pp. 95-96
    • Bentham1
  • 5
    • 84885739661 scopus 로고
    • Non-hedonist interpretation of Mill in 'Mill's deliberative utilitarianism
    • David O. Brink, in his non-hedonist interpretation of Mill in 'Mill's deliberative utilitarianism', Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (1992) 67-103 (see esp. 72-9), neither distinguishes activity pleasures from experience pleasures, nor discusses Mill's view of pain as the opposite of pleasure. I assume, incidentally, that Mill understands happiness to consist in any kind of pleasurable experience, that is, any experience which is enjoyed. Likewise, any distressing experience will count as painful
    • (1992) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.21 , pp. 67-103
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 6
    • 79956613666 scopus 로고
    • Reply to Professor Skorupski
    • In his conclusion on Mill's conception of the 'essential elements of human happiness' (Berger, 41-2), Berger indiscriminately runs together instrumental and non-instrumental goods. It cannot be that what are merely 'requirements' or 'requisites' for human happiness - such as the following by others of the rules of justice - can themselves be elements of human happiness. It should be noted that in his response to John Skorupski's review of his book, Berger speaks of 'whatever is requisite to "a sense of dignity" ' as one of the 'things in which we take pleasure by our natures' ('Reply to Professor Skorupski', Philosophical Books 26 (1985), 206). But Mill must surely be taken to be speaking of the (pleasurable) sense of dignity as the pleasurable component of happiness, not any pleasure we take in what is necessary for it
    • (1985) Philosophical Books , vol.26 , pp. 206
  • 8
    • 0003986649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The use of 'genuine' is to mark the distinction between Mill's view and that of, say, Aristotle, in which apparent self-sacrifice always turns out in fact to be in the agent's best interests; see Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, IX.8, 1168b23-31
    • Nicomachean Ethics
    • Aristotle1
  • 9
    • 79956674997 scopus 로고
    • See H. R. West, 'Mill's "proof of the principle of utility', in The Limits of Utilitarianism, ed. H. B. Miller and W. H. Williams (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), 28. West says that the ultimate ends of desires can be seen as 'experiences . . . with a pleasure component'. Unfortunately, he goes on to allow that virtue can be said to be desired as an end, apparently because he sees this as the sole interpretative alternative to the view that what is desired ultimately is only the 'pleasure component' of the state of consciousness of being virtuous. There is, of course, a third option, that it is the pleasurable experience of being virtuous that is desired. (II.2 might be taken to suggest that West's rejected alternative is anyway correct. But Mill is too unclear about the distinction between pleasure and a pleasurable experience for this interpretation to be accepted.)
    • (1982) Mill's proof of the principle of utility, in The Limits of Utilitarianism , pp. 28
    • West, H.R.1
  • 10
    • 0004264902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge; Cambridge University Press
    • G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge; Cambridge University Press, 1903), 72. I was pleased to find that Moore was similarly blunt about his own earlier views, in his later preface recently published in a Revised Edition of Principia Ethica, ed. T. Baldwin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1993), 2-27
    • (1903) Principia Ethica , pp. 72
    • Moore, G.E.1
  • 12
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고
    • Cf. H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London: Macmillan, 7th edn, 1907), note 1, Sidgwick's interpretation in this note is I think close to mine
    • (1907) The Methods of Ethics
    • Sidgwick, C.H.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.