-
1
-
-
61149257171
-
-
I want to thank Colin MacLeod, David Reidy, Dennis Klimchuk, and two anonymous referees, who were very generous with their comments, which helped me to improve the paper a lot
-
I want to thank Colin MacLeod, David Reidy, Dennis Klimchuk, and two anonymous referees, who were very generous with their comments, which helped me to improve the paper a lot.
-
-
-
-
2
-
-
17344372772
-
Intersectional Identity and the Authentic Self?: Opposites Attract!
-
Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, eds, New York: Oxford University Press
-
Diana Meyers, 'Intersectional Identity and the Authentic Self?: Opposites Attract!' in Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, eds. (New York: Oxford University Press 2000), 151
-
(2000)
Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self
, pp. 151
-
-
Meyers, D.1
-
3
-
-
61149522113
-
Integrity and Rational Change
-
Claudia Card, ed, Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas
-
Victoria Davion, 'Integrity and Rational Change,' in Feminist Ethics, Claudia Card, ed. (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas 1991), 190
-
(1991)
Feminist Ethics
, pp. 190
-
-
Davion, V.1
-
5
-
-
0001764986
-
Standing for Something
-
Cheshire Calhoun, 'Standing for Something,' Journal of Philosophy 92 (1995), 248
-
(1995)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.92
, pp. 248
-
-
Calhoun, C.1
-
7
-
-
0002211902
-
Persons, Character and Morality
-
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
-
and 'Persons, Character and Morality,' in Williams's Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973-1980 (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press 1981).
-
(1981)
Williams's Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973-1980
-
-
-
8
-
-
79956624308
-
-
Lynne McFall has this view of integrity as well. See her 'Integrity,' Ethics 98 (1987) 5-20.
-
(1987)
Integrity
, vol.98
, pp. 5-20
-
-
-
9
-
-
79956624380
-
-
Diana Meyers agrees and discusses the issue in 'Intersectional Identity,' 151.
-
Intersectional Identity
, pp. 151
-
-
-
10
-
-
61149131959
-
-
None has written anything comprehensive about how the two differ from one another
-
None has written anything comprehensive about how the two differ from one another.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
0346275693
-
Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Most philosophers writing on autonomy, especially Frankfurt, say that critical self-reflection is a key element of autonomy, while philosophers writing on integrity do not say the same thing about it. See Frankfurt's 'Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,' in his The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1988).
-
(1988)
The Importance of What We Care about
-
-
Frankfurt1
-
12
-
-
79956608345
-
-
Many philosophers, including Williams and McFall, explicitly associate having integrity with acting on values that are 'core,' or central to one's identity, but philosophers writing on autonomy in the Frankfurtian tradition do not do the same with it, not explicitly
-
Many philosophers, including Williams and McFall, explicitly associate having integrity with acting on values that are 'core,' or central to one's identity, but philosophers writing on autonomy in the Frankfurtian tradition do not do the same with it, not explicitly.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
0009332647
-
-
Cambridge: The MIT Press, . I refer throughout to a prototypical sense of integrity in Western culture. As with autonomy, I do not pretend to capture all of the ways in which we use 'integrity,' including non-prototypical ways (e. g. , the 'integrity' of objects)
-
along with Mind and Morals: Essays on Ethics and Cognitive Science, Larry May, Marilyn Friedman, and Andy Clark, eds. (Cambridge: The MIT Press 1996). I refer throughout to a prototypical sense of integrity in Western culture. As with autonomy, I do not pretend to capture all of the ways in which we use 'integrity,' including non-prototypical ways (e. g. , the 'integrity' of objects).
-
(1996)
Mind and Morals: Essays on Ethics and Cognitive Science
-
-
May, L.1
Friedman, M.2
Clark, A.3
-
15
-
-
15844403177
-
-
Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press
-
Here it is subjective, because I am taking as my starting point the dominant view of autonomy (i. e. , Frankfurt's), according to which the content of autonomous reflection is subjective. Elsewhere, I defend a more controversial view, according to which some objective (or substantive) limits exist on the mental contents of autonomous agents. Among these limits are justified self-trust, and self-respect. See my Self-Trust and Reproductive Autonomy (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press 2002).
-
(2002)
Self-Trust and Reproductive Autonomy
-
-
-
16
-
-
1642495088
-
Autonomy
-
John Christman, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press, One's capacity for autonomy allows one to shape an identity for oneself, but one is not fully autonomous until one has an identity that informs one's choices (i. e. , that makes them one's own)
-
Autonomy can do the first task because it is not simply a condition but also a capacity. See Joel Feinberg's 'Autonomy,' in The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy, John Christman, ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1989). One's capacity for autonomy allows one to shape an identity for oneself, but one is not fully autonomous until one has an identity that informs one's choices (i. e. , that makes them one's own).
-
(1989)
The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
18
-
-
79956673385
-
-
The important respect has to do with the content of what a person with integrity stands for: it concerns how everyone should act, not just how the agent himself should act, which is the case for personal autonomy. I do not deny, and in fact argue in Self-Trust and Reproductive Autonomy that autonomy is a social phenomenon in the sense that it is exercised and developed only in certain kinds of social environments. See also Mackenzie's and Stoljar's Relational Autonomy volume (2000)
-
(2000)
Mackenzie's and Stoljar's Relational Autonomy
-
-
-
19
-
-
79956642456
-
-
Burlington, VT: Ashgate, ch. 6. Integrity, I would argue, is similarly 'relational' (i. e. , socially constituted)
-
and Stefaan Cuypers's Self-Identity and Personal Autonomy (Burlington, VT: Ashgate 2001), ch. 6. Integrity, I would argue, is similarly 'relational' (i. e. , socially constituted).
-
(2001)
Stefaan Cuypers's Self-Identity and Personal Autonomy
-
-
-
20
-
-
79956642457
-
Integrity: Political, not Psychological
-
New York: Routledge
-
Philosophers who strongly associate resistance and struggle with integrity include Calhoun (see above), and Amelie Rorty. See the letter's 'Integrity: Political, not Psychological,' in Integrity in the Public and Private Domain, Alan Montefiore and David Vines, eds. (New York: Routledge 1999).
-
(1999)
Integrity in the Public and Private Domain
-
-
Montefiore, A.1
Vines, D.2
-
21
-
-
34548311096
-
Two Types of Autonomy Accounts
-
Richard Double, 'Two Types of Autonomy Accounts,' Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1992), 70.
-
(1992)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.22
, pp. 70
-
-
Double, R.1
-
22
-
-
84875891967
-
The Public Conception of Autonomy and Critical Self-Reflection
-
See as well Robert Noggle's 'The Public Conception of Autonomy and Critical Self-Reflection,' The Southern Journal of Philosophy 35 (1997) 495-515.
-
(1997)
The Southern Journal of Philosophy
, vol.35
, pp. 495-515
-
-
Noggle, R.1
-
28
-
-
14544280884
-
-
& 172
-
As Frankfurt puts it, one 'constitutes' oneself by reflecting upon and deciding what one wants (and presumably, the more one reflects and decides, the more one constitutes oneself): see 'Identification and Wholeheartedness,' 170 & 172.
-
Identification and Wholeheartedness
, pp. 170
-
-
-
29
-
-
79956673790
-
-
Double assumes that reflection of this sort is necessary according to the dominant view of autonomy: see 'Two Types,' 70.
-
Two Types
, pp. 70
-
-
-
30
-
-
33644681362
-
The Faintest Passion
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, He discusses the need to be self-reflective so that one can replace 'unsatisfying' (i. e. , inconsistent or ambivalent) truths about oneself, and ultimately be a whole, autonomous self
-
Frankfurt says as much in 'The Faintest Passion,' in his Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1999), 99, 100, 106. He discusses the need to be self-reflective so that one can replace 'unsatisfying' (i. e. , inconsistent or ambivalent) truths about oneself, and ultimately be a whole, autonomous self.
-
(1999)
Necessity, Volition, and Love
, vol.99
, Issue.100
, pp. 106
-
-
-
31
-
-
79956642772
-
On the Necessity of Ideals
-
See Frankfurt's 'On the Necessity of Ideals,' in Necessity, Volition, 115.
-
Necessity, Volition
, pp. 115
-
-
Frankfurt1
-
33
-
-
79956624279
-
-
That is not to say that they discover it on their own necessarily. Self-reflection may only be useful if it involves feedback from others
-
That is not to say that they discover it on their own necessarily. Self-reflection may only be useful if it involves feedback from others.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
78649649676
-
Integrity and Self-Protection
-
& 222
-
See my 'Integrity and Self-Protection,' Journal of Social Philosophy 35 (2004), 221 & 222.
-
(2004)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.35
, pp. 221
-
-
-
35
-
-
79956624278
-
-
It is Calhoun's ('Standing for Something'). She refers to the evaluative communities in Mill and Kant (256). Both the unrestricted flow of ideas in Mill and the community of co-legislators in Kant require that people stand for what they believe to be true or for principles that they think should legislate everyone, respectively. In other words, they must have integrity. For otherwise the communities would not function in the way Mill and Kant intended
-
It is Calhoun's ('Standing for Something'). She refers to the evaluative communities in Mill and Kant (256). Both the unrestricted flow of ideas in Mill and the community of co-legislators in Kant require that people stand for what they believe to be true or for principles that they think should legislate everyone, respectively. In other words, they must have integrity. For otherwise the communities would not function in the way Mill and Kant intended.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
0003593197
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For example, a reason for acting courageously could simply be 'it's worth the risk'; see Rosalind Hursthouse's On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1999), 128
-
(1999)
On Virtue Ethics
, pp. 128
-
-
Hursthouse, R.1
-
37
-
-
79956673648
-
-
G. Himmelfarb, ed, Harmondsworth: Penguin, ch. 2
-
See John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, G. Himmelfarb, ed. (Harmondsworth: Penguin 1982), ch. 2.
-
(1982)
On Liberty
-
-
Stuart Mill, J.1
-
39
-
-
79956624171
-
-
his 'Identification and Wholeheartedness. '
-
See his 'Identification and Wholeheartedness. '
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
79956642738
-
-
Many feminists oppose the idea that an autonomous self must be completely unified, or wholehearted in its deliberations. The reason why is that many women's selves are made up of 'intersectional identities' (e. g. , mother/professional; Hispanic/lesbian) that do not admit of wholehearted integration, but may be autonomous nonetheless. See Meyers, 'Intersectional Identity,' 168-72.
-
Intersectional Identity
, pp. 168-172
-
-
Meyers1
-
41
-
-
79956642662
-
Integrity and Radical Change, and Margaret Walker's 'Picking Up Pieces: Lives, Stories, and Integrity
-
New York: Routledge, Still, I do not think most feminists would deny that some integration is essential for both autonomy and integrity; without being somewhat integrated, one would have nothing either to govern one's self with or to stand for
-
Feminists writing on integrity make a similar claim about wholehearted integration and intersectional identities. See, for example, Davion's 'Integrity and Radical Change,' and Margaret Walker's 'Picking Up Pieces: Lives, Stories, and Integrity,' in her Moral Understandings: A Feminist Study in Ethics (New York: Routledge 1998). Still, I do not think most feminists would deny that some integration is essential for both autonomy and integrity; without being somewhat integrated, one would have nothing either to govern one's self with or to stand for.
-
(1998)
Moral Understandings: A Feminist Study in Ethics
-
-
Davion1
-
43
-
-
33644683482
-
Autonomy, Necessity, and Love
-
Frankfurt, 'Autonomy, Necessity, and Love,' in Necessity, Volition, 132
-
Necessity, Volition
, vol.132
-
-
Frankfurt1
-
45
-
-
79956673591
-
-
The judgment is more specifically that people in general, not just the agent herself, should be willing to die for fine wine
-
The judgment is more specifically that people in general, not just the agent herself, should be willing to die for fine wine.
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
79956639742
-
-
One might object that acting such that one furthers one's own conception of the good may not improve one's autonomy because one's good, subjectively defined, could lie in 'abnegating one's autonomy' (as one referee for this journal suggested to me). What if one's good, subjectively defined, is to be the slave of another? I think we would, or at least should, question whether such a conception of the good is subjectively defined. More than likely, it is the product of oppression or some other alien, negative force
-
One might object that acting such that one furthers one's own conception of the good may not improve one's autonomy because one's good, subjectively defined, could lie in 'abnegating one's autonomy' (as one referee for this journal suggested to me). What if one's good, subjectively defined, is to be the slave of another? I think we would, or at least should, question whether such a conception of the good is subjectively defined. More than likely, it is the product of oppression or some other alien, negative force.
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
79956673589
-
-
One might ask whether aside from my theory, we have any reason to deny that she would exercise personal autonomy if she went against public opinion. After all, she might do so after having made an informed and voluntary decision. However, 'personal autonomy' does not refer simply to making informed and voluntary decisions. If it did, it would be indistinguishable from other forms of autonomy, including moral autonomy (i. e. , integrity). The 'personal' in personal autonomy refers to individual goals or preferences that one thinks should motivate the self, but not others inevitably (hence the term 'personal'). 'Personal autonomy' involves satisfying personal preferences. 'Moral autonomy,' by contrast, involves adhering to one's own moral 'preferences,' if you will
-
One might ask whether aside from my theory, we have any reason to deny that she would exercise personal autonomy if she went against public opinion. After all, she might do so after having made an informed and voluntary decision. However, 'personal autonomy' does not refer simply to making informed and voluntary decisions. If it did, it would be indistinguishable from other forms of autonomy, including moral autonomy (i. e. , integrity). The 'personal' in personal autonomy refers to individual goals or preferences that one thinks should motivate the self, but not others inevitably (hence the term 'personal'). 'Personal autonomy' involves satisfying personal preferences. 'Moral autonomy,' by contrast, involves adhering to one's own moral 'preferences,' if you will.
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
79956639733
-
-
Assuming that what we perceive to be good for ourselves and what we perceive to be right together exhaust the sorts of values that could be the product of autonomous self-reflection, my view does not place substantive restrictions on what an agent who is autonomous (personally or morally) can endorse. Thus my view is faithful to its Frankfurtian starting point, which is a non-substantive, or purely procedural view of autonomy
-
Assuming that what we perceive to be good for ourselves and what we perceive to be right together exhaust the sorts of values that could be the product of autonomous self-reflection, my view does not place substantive restrictions on what an agent who is autonomous (personally or morally) can endorse. Thus my view is faithful to its Frankfurtian starting point, which is a non-substantive, or purely procedural view of autonomy.
-
-
-
-
50
-
-
79956639739
-
-
However, if we cannot simply prioritize the right over the good in our current situation, we may feel uncertain about our decision and hence not as integrated as an autonomous person perhaps should be
-
However, if we cannot simply prioritize the right over the good in our current situation, we may feel uncertain about our decision and hence not as integrated as an autonomous person perhaps should be.
-
-
-
-
51
-
-
79956673577
-
-
One might think it is odd to say that integrity involves 'being in a proper relation to others. ' Does it not sometimes require that we stand apart from society, even alienate ourselves from it, in order to remain true to what we think is right? Yes, but that is consistent with saying that we should be in the sort of relation to others that integrity demands on Calhoun's theory. The proper relation is not physical but moral. The agent must resist pressure to conform not simply for his own sake, but for others' sakes. Authentic moral concern for others should be evident from the content of his beliefs
-
'Standing for Something,' 252. One might think it is odd to say that integrity involves 'being in a proper relation to others. ' Does it not sometimes require that we stand apart from society, even alienate ourselves from it, in order to remain true to what we think is right? Yes, but that is consistent with saying that we should be in the sort of relation to others that integrity demands on Calhoun's theory. The proper relation is not physical but moral. The agent must resist pressure to conform not simply for his own sake, but for others' sakes. Authentic moral concern for others should be evident from the content of his beliefs.
-
Standing for Something
, pp. 252
-
-
-
52
-
-
79956639659
-
-
Note that there are four categories here: 1) standing for something, 2) the social nature Calhoun describes, 3) honoring one's own principles of right, and 4) having integrity. My aim is to establish connections between 1) and 2), 2) and 3), and finally, 3) and 4). Along with Calhoun, I simply assume that 1) and 4 are linked: integrity involves standing for something. I also assume that the converse could be false: standing for something may not always involve maintaining integrity. Further, it may not always involve honouring authentic principles of right
-
Note that there are four categories here: 1) standing for something, 2) the social nature Calhoun describes, 3) honoring one's own principles of right, and 4) having integrity. My aim is to establish connections between 1) and 2), 2) and 3), and finally, 3) and 4). Along with Calhoun, I simply assume that 1) and 4) are linked: integrity involves standing for something. I also assume that the converse could be false: standing for something may not always involve maintaining integrity. Further, it may not always involve honouring authentic principles of right.
-
-
-
-
53
-
-
79956623995
-
-
I use a very similar example in my paper, 'Integrity and Self-Protection' (forthcoming). I quote from it below
-
I use a very similar example in my paper, 'Integrity and Self-Protection' (forthcoming). I quote from it below.
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
79956639732
-
-
It is true that in this example, the person could be standing up for what is right primarily for his own sake. Alternatively, people can do what is right primarily for others' sake, or for their own sake and others' sake. If my theory of integrity is accurate, people can act with integrity in each of these ways. A similar claim can be made about personal autonomy. People can do what is good for themselves, for people close to them, or for themselves and those people, and act with personal autonomy, though not necessarily with integrity, in each case. When a person promotes someone else's good or his own good while violating his own principles of right, he acts autonomously but without integrity
-
It is true that in this example, the person could be standing up for what is right primarily for his own sake. Alternatively, people can do what is right primarily for others' sake, or for their own sake and others' sake. If my theory of integrity is accurate, people can act with integrity in each of these ways. A similar claim can be made about personal autonomy. People can do what is good for themselves, for people close to them, or for themselves and those people, and act with personal autonomy, though not necessarily with integrity, in each case. When a person promotes someone else's good or his own good while violating his own principles of right, he acts autonomously but without integrity.
-
-
-
-
56
-
-
79956623977
-
-
Rosalind Hursthouse's On Virtue Ethics
-
See Rosalind Hursthouse's On Virtue Ethics
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
0000322565
-
Virtue and Reason
-
and John McDowell's 'Virtue and Reason,' Monist 62 (1979) 331-50
-
(1979)
Monist
, vol.62
, pp. 331-350
-
-
McDowell, J.1
-
60
-
-
0004207980
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press 1986)
-
(1986)
The View from Nowhere
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
61
-
-
0039153014
-
Identity, Ostension, and Hypostasis
-
New York: Harper & Row
-
W. V. O. Quine, 'Identity, Ostension, and Hypostasis,' in From a Logical Point of View (New York: Harper & Row 1963), 78
-
(1963)
From A Logical Point of View
, pp. 78
-
-
Quine, W.V.O.1
-
62
-
-
79956673451
-
-
Note that for me, this restriction about importance is ultimately procedural. I have said that when someone's principles of right concern trivial matters, they are 'barely believable as anyone's best judgment' about what is right (16). The implication here is that the person has not adequately reflected on what is right
-
Note that for me, this restriction about importance is ultimately procedural. I have said that when someone's principles of right concern trivial matters, they are 'barely believable as anyone's best judgment' about what is right (16). The implication here is that the person has not adequately reflected on what is right.
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
79956673460
-
-
Calhoun, 257
-
Calhoun, 257
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
79956673167
-
-
But most contemporary philosophers assume, unlike Kant, that one can be morally autonomous even if one's moral views are objectively wrong. I think that the same is true about integrity
-
But most contemporary philosophers assume, unlike Kant, that one can be morally autonomous even if one's moral views are objectively wrong. I think that the same is true about integrity.
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
0004305896
-
-
H. J. Paton, trans., New York: Harper and Row
-
See Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, H. J. Paton, trans. (New York: Harper and Row 1964), 114
-
(1964)
Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals
, pp. 114
-
-
Kant1
-
66
-
-
5744229285
-
The Kantian Conception of Autonom
-
Christman
-
quoted in Thomas Hill's 'The Kantian Conception of Autonomy,' in Christman, The Inner Citadel, 97.
-
The Inner Citadel
, pp. 97
-
-
Hill, T.1
-
69
-
-
79956639423
-
Hursthouse Virtues and Reasons and a similar Virtue Ethics
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For the ancients as well as for medieval Christian philosophers, the good life was one of virtue. Today, we are seeing a resurgence of such theories of the good (i. e. , objectivist theories) in ethics with the current revival of virtue ethics. See, for example, Hursthouse's Virtues and Reasons volume, and a similar volume, Virtue Ethics, Roger Crisp and Michael Slote, eds. (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1997).
-
(1997)
-
-
Crisp, R.1
Slote, M.2
-
70
-
-
79956642431
-
-
Note that it is not a Kantian notion: while happiness may be defined subjectively, in terms of individual preferences in Kant, the good is not. For Kant, '[it] is impossible to conceive anything at all in the world, or even out of it, which can be taken as good without qualification, except a good will' (his emphasis, Groundwork, 61)
-
Note that it is not a Kantian notion: while happiness may be defined subjectively, in terms of individual preferences in Kant, the good is not. For Kant, '[it] is impossible to conceive anything at all in the world, or even out of it, which can be taken as good without qualification, except a good will' (his emphasis, Groundwork, 61).
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
79956639445
-
-
One might argue that the opposite is true with respect to autonomy and emancipation: some emancipation, in the form of freedom from restrictions or from external coercion, is necessary before one can exercise of autonomy. I agree. However, freedom of that form is not complete emancipation; one might still lack the capacity to form and act upon one's own desires. Hence, autonomy, or the development of it, allows for complete emancipation
-
One might argue that the opposite is true with respect to autonomy and emancipation: some emancipation, in the form of freedom from restrictions or from external coercion, is necessary before one can exercise of autonomy. I agree. However, freedom of that form is not complete emancipation; one might still lack the capacity to form and act upon one's own desires. Hence, autonomy, or the development of it, allows for complete emancipation.
-
-
-
|