메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 9, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 1-15

Descartes and individual corporeal substance

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61149267783     PISSN: 09608788     EISSN: 14693526     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/09608780010012666     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (18)

References (28)
  • 1
    • 80054125466 scopus 로고
    • P. Clair and F. Girbal, eds, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France
    • G. de Cordemoy, Oeuvres philosophiques. P. Clair and F. Girbal, eds. (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1968), 103-104
    • (1968) Oeuvres philosophiques , pp. 103-104
    • De Cordemoy, G.1
  • 2
    • 80054125333 scopus 로고
    • J. Rohault, A System of Natural Philosophy, vol. 1 (written 1671), trans. J. Clarke and S. Clarke (1723). (New York, Johnson Reprint Corp., 1969), 28
    • (1671) A System of Natural Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 28
    • Rohault, J.1
  • 7
    • 61149467140 scopus 로고
    • 2nd ed, Oxford, Oxford University Press
    • S. V. Keeling, Descartes, 2nd ed. (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1968), 145
    • (1968) Descartes , pp. 145
    • Keeling, S.V.1
  • 11
    • 80054143809 scopus 로고
    • Freiburg, Verlag Karl Alber
    • D. Marshall, jr.. Prinzipien der Descartes: Exegese. (Freiburg, Verlag Karl Alber, 1979), 54-7. Listing all the commentators who accept the monist position, or at least find the notion of individual corporeal substance untenable, would take up nearly the entire length of this essay
    • (1979) Prinzipien der Descartes: Exegese , pp. 54-57
    • Marshall Jr., D.1
  • 12
    • 84869963643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers
    • Translations from the Principles of Philosophy are based on the edition by V. R. Miller and R. P. Miller (Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1983), but are checkedagainst the C. Adam and P. Tannery edition of the Oeuvres de Descartes (Paris, J. Vrin, 1974). I will identify passages according to the standard convention: thus, Article 15, Part II, of the Principles will be labeled 'Pr II 15'. Passages from the French translation of 1647 will be prefaced by 'Fr'. Other translations that are based on the complete Adam and Tannery edition will be marked, 'AT', followed by volume and page number
    • Translations from the Principles of Philosophy
    • Miller, V.R.1    Miller, R.P.2
  • 13
    • 61049147521 scopus 로고
    • Mathematics, Physics, and Corporeal Substance in Descartes
    • As G. Brown has argued, nevertheless, it may not be necessary to read the intimate correlation between extension and matter as a straightforward identity claim; 'Mathematics, Physics, and Corporeal Substance in Descartes', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 70 (1989), 281-302. This issue will be raised briefly below, although the identity of extension and matter, or lack there of, will not affect the main arguments of this essay
    • (1989) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.70 , pp. 281-302
  • 14
    • 0042138146 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Descartes, Space-Time, and Relational Motion
    • For an analysis of some of these problems, see, E. Slowik, 'Descartes, Space-Time, and Relational Motion', Philosophy of Science, vol. 66, no. 1, 1999, 117-39
    • (1999) Philosophy of Science , vol.66 , Issue.1 , pp. 117-139
    • Slowik, E.1
  • 15
    • 0003573115 scopus 로고
    • 2nd ed, Cambridge, MA. Harvard University Press
    • and M. Jammer, Concepts of Space, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, MA. Harvard University Press, 1969), 43-4
    • (1969) Concepts of Space , pp. 43-44
    • Jammer, M.1
  • 16
    • 80054175040 scopus 로고
    • G. W. Leibniz, 'Letter to De Voider, May 13, 1699', in G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters, trans, and ed. by L. E. Loemker. (Dordrecht, D. Reidel, 1970), 519
    • (1699) Letter to De Voider , pp. 519
    • Leibniz, G.W.1
  • 17
    • 0041679310 scopus 로고
    • The Metaphysics and Physics of Force in Descartes
    • S. Gaukroger, ed. (Harvester Press, Sussex)
    • M. Gueroult. 'The Metaphysics and Physics of Force in Descartes', in Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics, S. Gaukroger, ed. (Harvester Press, Sussex, 1980) 199. Gueroult's full presentation of his argument appears in Descartes' Philosophy Interpreted According to the Order of Reasons, Vol. II, trans. By R. Ariew (Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press), 63-74
    • (1980) Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics , pp. 199
    • Gueroult, M.1
  • 18
    • 61449131345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spinoza's Metaphysics
    • ed., D. Garrett. (Cambridge, Cambridge U. Press)
    • J. Bennett, 'Spinoza's Metaphysics', in The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza, ed., D. Garrett. (Cambridge, Cambridge U. Press, 1996), 70-1. Interestingly. Bennett's interpretation, which he dubs a 'field' theory, is much in the spirit of later 'supersubstantivalist' theories of space (i.e. where space is the only predicable substance; and thus objects are merely qualitatively/quantitatively distinct portions of space). Newton toyed with this idea in his early essay, De Gravitatione et aequipondio fluidorum, trans, and eds. A. R. Hall and M. B. Hall, in Unpublished Scientific Papers of Isaac Newton. (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. 1962). 139
    • (1996) The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza , pp. 70-71
    • Bennett, J.1
  • 21
    • 80054125316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rationalists, ed. by D. Pereboom Lanham, Rowman & Littlefield
    • This problem with the modal the sis is raised by P. Hoffman, 'The Unity of Descartes's Man', reprinted in The Rationalists, ed. by D. Pereboom (Lanham, Rowman & Littlefield, 1999), 64
    • (1999) The Unity of Descartes's Man , pp. 64
    • Hoffman, P.1
  • 22
    • 0003855383 scopus 로고
    • Ironically
    • Ironically. Descartes's 'empty vessel' argument can be seen as an early forerunner to the 'hole' problem that plagued Einstein's developmentof General Relativity, as well as recent formulations of substantivalist space-time theories. See, J. Earman, World Enough and Space-Time. (Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1989), chap. 9
    • (1989) World Enough and Space-Time
    • Earman, J.1
  • 23
    • 80054175029 scopus 로고
    • Descartes and the Individuation of Physical Objects
    • Albany, State University of New York Press Also
    • E. Grosholz raises related difficulties, stressing that Descartes's arguments against the vacuum can only work for finite, bounded vacua, and not necessarily against a vacuum that surrounds the material world: 'Descartes and the Individuation of Physical Objects', in Individuation and Identity in Early Modern Philosophy, ed. by K. F. Barber and J. J. E. Gracia (Albany, State University of New York Press, 1994) 48-53. Also, Descartes's term 'indefinite' essentially functions as 'infinite', since it stands for a concept of which no limit can be conceived. Only God. however, is the proper subject of the 'positive'-sounding designation, 'infinite', which lacks any sense of limit (Pr I 26-7)
    • (1994) Individuation and Identity in Early Modern Philosophy , pp. 48-53
    • Barber, K.F.1    Gracia, J.J.E.2
  • 25
    • 0004110955 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Cambridge University Press chap. 7
    • There were many sixteenth and seventeenth century Natural philosophers who did accept a theory with similar implications, such as F. Suarez, P. Fonseca, the Coimbra Jesuits, B. Amicus, and E. Maignan. These thinkers tried to accommodate both the notion of a finite extended world and an infinite (quasi-) non-extended void: i.e. an 'imaginary' space that, while not possessing extension or dimensionality, had the capacity to receive extended bodies. Descartes's theory of space rules out this option, for he interprets vacuum as an extended 'nothing', which is an impossible state-of-affairs (since 'nothing' cannot be the subject of a property). Thus the actual existence of a plenum is impossible since extension must be a property of some thing (but this should not be taken to undermine the argument centered upon conceivability that will be advanced below). (Pr II 16) His substance-property dichotomy is clearly at work, here. (see. Pr I 56) On 'imaginary' space theorists, see, E. Grant, Much Ado About Nothing: Theories of Space and Vacuum from the Middle Ages to the Scientific Revolution. (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981), chap. 7
    • (1981) Much Ado About Nothing: Theories of Space and Vacuum from the Middle Ages to the Scientific Revolution
    • Grant, E.1
  • 26
    • 84869957088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comments on Slowik's "descartes, Monism, and Individual Corporeal Substance"
    • May 8
    • R. Florka has suggested to me that a better interpretation of the consequences of removing all of the space surrounding a body is that it would now fill all of extension: i.e. the body, say, a chair, would now assume the role of the 'indefinitely' extended plenum, which is a better analogue to the case of the empty vessel, as examined above. Of course, the problem that would now arise is whether or not the object retains its identity after it becomes indefinite extension; since, if it is indefinitely extended, and thus has no boundary, in what sense can it still be referred to as a 'chair'? Overall, both versions of individual material substance, i.e. Florka's and my own, face the difficulty of coherently explaining the boundary, or surface, of these substances given their lack of contiguous neighbors, thus both approaches to this problem can be seen as complimentary. R. Florka, 'Comments on Slowik's "Descartes, Monism, and Individual Corporeal Substance"', presented at the American Philosophical Association Central Division Meeting, May 8, 1999
    • (1999) American Philosophical Association Central Division Meeting
    • Florka, R.1
  • 27
    • 0042031917 scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press
    • M. Grene, Descartes. (Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1985) 100-1
    • (1985) Descartes , pp. 100-101
    • Grene, M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.