메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 3, 2001, Pages 235-256

The moral self and the perfect self in Aristotle and Mencius

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049399105     PISSN: 03018121     EISSN: 15406253     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/0301-8121.00045     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (75)
  • 2
    • 80054210009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (hereafter cited as NE), 1094a23-25, 1095a18-20
    • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (hereafter cited as NE), 1094a23-25, 1095a18-20
  • 3
    • 61049569822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 7B:16
    • Mencius 7B:16
  • 4
    • 80054206430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1097B33-1098a4
    • NE, 1097B33-1098a4
  • 5
    • 80054189862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1097a33-1098a3
    • NE, 1097a33-1098a3
  • 6
    • 80054261837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle does not believe that animals have reason (De Anima, 428a8-23, 432a5-11). Since eudaimonia means exercising rationality well, and animals do not share rationality, he denies that animals are capable of eudaimonia (NE, 1178b24-28)
    • Aristotle does not believe that animals have reason (De Anima, 428a8-23, 432a5-11). Since eudaimonia means exercising rationality well, and animals do not share rationality, he denies that animals are capable of eudaimonia (NE, 1178b24-28)
  • 7
    • 80054209924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Chinese term is duan, also translated as roots, sprouts, beginnings, stirrings, germs, and so forth. For the sake of consistency, I use seed throughout
    • The Chinese term is duan, also translated as "roots," "sprouts," "beginnings," "stirrings," "germs," and so forth. For the sake of consistency, I use "seed" throughout
  • 8
    • 80054206427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 2A:6
    • Mencius 2A:6
  • 9
    • 0004060178 scopus 로고
    • Hong Kong: Chinese University Press
    • Unless otherwise indicated, the translation of the Book of Mencius is based on D. C. Lau, Mencius (Hong Kong: Chinese University Press, 1984)
    • (1984) Mencius
    • Lau, D.C.1
  • 10
    • 80054209916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1144b4-6
    • NE, 1144b4-6
  • 11
    • 80054209912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 6A:15
    • Mencius 6A:15
  • 12
    • 80054259123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Generation of Anima, 736b3-4
    • Generation of Anima, 736b3-4
  • 13
    • 80054259000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De Anima II.1., 412a10-11, a22-26
    • De Anima II.1., 412a10-11, a22-26
  • 14
    • 80054259004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1098b33-34; cf. 1175b34-35
    • NE, 1098b33-34; cf. 1175b34-35
  • 15
    • 80054206259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is in this latter sense of actuality that the soul is called the first actuality (De Anima II.1, a27-28, b5)
    • It is in this latter sense of actuality that the soul is called the "first actuality" (De Anima II.1, a27-28, b5)
  • 16
    • 80054209850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 3B:9
    • Mencius 3B:9
  • 17
    • 80054176801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., Mencius 7B:24
    • E.g., Mencius 7B:24
  • 18
    • 60950729591 scopus 로고
    • The Background of the Mencian Theory of Human Nature
    • Albany: State University of New York Press
    • A. C. Graham, "The Background of the Mencian Theory of Human Nature," in his Studies in Chinese Philosophy and Philosophical Literature (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990) pp. 27-28
    • (1990) Studies in Chinese Philosophy and Philosophical Literature , pp. 27-28
    • Graham, A.C.1
  • 19
    • 78651053122 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • There has been much debate regarding Mencius's conception of xing when he talks about the goodness of xing. Mencius is clearly not talking about the whole of human nature. Fung Yulan believes that xing in Mencius is only limited to moral inclinations (A History of Chinese Philosophy, vol. 1 [Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1952], pp. 124-5)
    • (1952) A History of Chinese Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 124-125
  • 20
    • 80054209934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Graham suggests that the term refers to "the maturation of a continuing growth" ("Background of Mencian Theory," p. 8)
    • Background of Mencian Theory , pp. 8
  • 21
    • 61449452820 scopus 로고
    • The Mencian Conception of Ren xing: Does it Mean 'Human Nature?
    • edited by Henry Rosemont, Jr. [La Salle, IL: Open Court,]
    • Roger Ames argues that the xing of a human being in Mencius is viewed more as a cultural achievement or construction than what is unlearned, so he proposes that "For the human being at least, xing seems to come closer to 'character,' 'personality' or 'constitution' than what we generally understand by 'nature'" ("The Mencian Conception of Ren xing: Does it Mean 'Human Nature"?," in Chinese Texts and Philosophical Contexts edited by Henry Rosemont, Jr. [La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1991], p. 150)
    • (1991) Chinese Texts and Philosophical Contexts , pp. 150
    • Ames, R.1
  • 22
    • 80054176746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It seems that different views emphasize different aspects of the complicated notion of xing in our classification. Fung holds onto sense (2), Graham underscores sense (3), and Ames emphasizes the result of sense (3). These senses can be unified if we consider the four seeds in the process from potentiality to actuality. It is the same good xing that is potentially owned by every human being, and that can only be developed by some. Once it is developed, a gentleman is made. Since the gentlemen represents the development of these four seeds, the four seeds are also said to be xing of the gentleman (Mencius 7A;21)
    • It seems that different views emphasize different aspects of the complicated notion of xing in our classification. Fung holds onto sense (2), Graham underscores sense (3), and Ames emphasizes the result of sense (3). These senses can be unified if we consider the four seeds in the process from potentiality to actuality. It is the same good xing that is potentially owned by every human being, and that can only be developed by some. Once it is developed, a gentleman is made. Since the gentlemen represents the development of these four seeds, the four seeds are also said to be "xing of the gentleman" (Mencius 7A;21)
  • 23
    • 0003986649 scopus 로고
    • Indiana: Hackett
    • For the definitions of these two senses in Aristotle's ethics, see the glossary in T. H. Irwin, trans., Nicomachean Ethics (Indiana: Hackett, 1985)
    • (1985) Nicomachean Ethics
    • Irwin, T.H.1
  • 24
    • 80054258948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1050a21. Unless otherwise indicated, all quotations are based on the Revised Oxford Translation of the Complete Works of Aristotle, edited by J. Barnes
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1050a21. Unless otherwise indicated, all quotations are based on the Revised Oxford Translation of the Complete Works of Aristotle, edited by J. Barnes
  • 25
    • 80054209748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A further point might be worth making. Many critics of Mencius question how his roots could be innate. Mencius indeed painstakingly argues that these roots are given. His main strategy is to show that they are unlearned, spontaneous, unreflective, and uncalculating. He illustrates the existence of the innate seed of benevolence by pointing out our spontaneous and disinterested concern at the sight of a child about to fall into a well (Mencius 2A:6); he also underscores the infants' pre-socially conditioned love of and respect for his parents and siblings (Mencius 7A:15)
    • A further point might be worth making. Many critics of Mencius question how his roots could be innate. Mencius indeed painstakingly argues that these roots are given. His main strategy is to show that they are unlearned, spontaneous, unreflective, and uncalculating. He illustrates the existence of the innate seed of benevolence by pointing out our spontaneous and disinterested concern at the sight of a child about to fall into a well (Mencius 2A:6); he also underscores the infants' pre-socially conditioned love of and respect for his parents and siblings (Mencius 7A:15)
  • 26
    • 34247355606 scopus 로고
    • Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press
    • For a detailed discussion of Mencius's arguments on the innateness of the four roots, see P. J. Ivanhoe, Ethics in the Confucian Tradition (Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press, 1990), pp. 29-36
    • (1990) Ethics in the Confucian Tradition , pp. 29-36
    • Ivanhoe, P.J.1
  • 27
    • 80054176722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nevertheless, Mencius's arguments are not taken to be convincing. For instance, in Background of Mencian Theory, Graham comments: ... we are now almost morbidly aware of the difficulty of proving that apparently disinterested actions do not have egoistic motives and that apparently instinctive reactions are not socially conditioned (p. 29)
    • Nevertheless, Mencius's arguments are not taken to be convincing. For instance, in "Background of Mencian Theory," Graham comments: "... we are now almost morbidly aware of the difficulty of proving that apparently disinterested actions do not have egoistic motives and that apparently instinctive reactions are not socially conditioned" (p. 29)
  • 28
    • 0003457446 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, This issue is too complicated to be solved by philosophical arguments alone. I would like to mention, however, that Aristotle believes that rationality is innate and does not argue why. Yet he is rarely questioned in this regard
    • Graham's view is widely shared. As Chad Hansen aptly observes: "Typically, western treatments of Mencius' psychological theory, drawing on traditional Western cynicism about human nature, regard Mencius' view as lacking any empirical support" (A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992], p. 167). This issue is too complicated to be solved by philosophical arguments alone. I would like to mention, however, that Aristotle believes that rationality is innate and does not argue why. Yet he is rarely questioned in this regard
    • (1992) A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought , pp. 167
  • 29
    • 80054206223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1095b19-20.
    • NE, 1095b19-20
  • 30
    • 0141757688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, pp. 210ff
    • There are two related debates; First, does Mencius mean that xing is originally good, or that it is directed toward goodness? Second, does Mencius mean that human beings are moral agents, and that shan is a formal term, referring to whatever conforms to the direction of xing, without having substantial content? For a helpful discussion of this debate, see Kwong-Loi Shun, Mencius and Early Chinese Thought (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997), pp. 210ff
    • (1997) Mencius and Early Chinese Thought
    • Shun, K.1
  • 31
    • 80054258925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 6A:6
    • Mencius 6A:6
  • 33
    • 80054258852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 3A:1, 6A:6, 6A:2
    • Mencius 3A:1, 6A:6, 6A:2
  • 34
    • 80054258922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. NE, 1144a21-36, 1140a29, 1141b13
    • Cf. NE, 1144a21-36, 1140a29, 1141b13
  • 35
    • 80054258855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They are fused in such a way that they constitute a direct sensitivity. A moral self can immediately judge what is right and has the practical perception of just seeing what the right thing to do is (NE, 1142a27-30, 1143b14, 1144a29, 114b1-17; cf. 1109b23)
    • They are fused in such a way that they constitute a direct sensitivity. A moral self can immediately judge what is right and has the practical perception of "just seeing" what the right thing to do is (NE, 1142a27-30, 1143b14, 1144a29, 114b1-17; cf. 1109b23)
  • 36
    • 80054209836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Analects 12:1
    • Analects 12:1
  • 37
    • 80054209789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., Mencius 3A:1.
    • E.g., Mencius 3A:1
  • 38
    • 80054176682 scopus 로고
    • By the time of Mencius however jen [ren] is directly translatable by 'benevolence
    • La Salle, IL: Open Court
    • For instance, Graham says: "By the time of Mencius however jen [ren] is directly translatable by 'benevolence'" (Disputers of the Tao [La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1989], p. 113)
    • (1989) Disputers of the Tao , pp. 113
  • 40
    • 80054176644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is supported by Chad Hansen, who holds that yi should be "an idealised social practice" (Daoist Theory, p. 165)
    • Daoist Theory , pp. 165
  • 41
    • 0141757688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and also by Shun, in whose analysis, yi, whether as an attribute of a person or as a quality of action, is related to certain ethical standards (Mencius and Early Chinese Thought, pp. 62-63)
    • Mencius and Early Chinese Thought , pp. 62-63
  • 42
    • 80054258842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 3A:4, 7B:24
    • Mencius 3A:4, 7B:24
  • 43
    • 80054258847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is no explicit remark, so far as I am aware, in the Book of Mencius that yi should be grouped with zhi, or that yi involves adjusting universal principles according to the particular circumstances. Mencius indeed recognizes the need for a person to depart from the established li under certain circumstances. However, such a decision not to hold li too rigidly is called discretion (chuan). For instance, li prescribes that man and woman should not touch each other. But Mencius proposes that one should use discretion to help save a sister-in-law who is drowning (Mencius 4A:17, cf. 7A:26)
    • There is no explicit remark, so far as I am aware, in the Book of Mencius that yi should be grouped with zhi, or that yi involves adjusting universal principles according to the particular circumstances. Mencius indeed recognizes the need for a person to depart from the established li under certain circumstances. However, such a decision not to hold li too rigidly is called "discretion" (chuan). For instance, li prescribes that man and woman should not touch each other. But Mencius proposes that one should use discretion to help save a sister-in-law who is drowning (Mencius 4A:17, cf. 7A:26)
  • 44
    • 80054209758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Further, if yi is the evaluation function, what is its difference from zhi (wisdom)? Munro's answer is that whereas a person of yi is involved in the activities he is evaluating, a person of zhi does not have to get involved (Concept of Man in Early China, p. 76)
    • Concept of Man in Early China , pp. 76
    • Further1
  • 45
    • 80054176654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This distinction is rejected by Shun Mencius and Early Chinese Thought, p. 71
    • This distinction is rejected by Shun (Mencius and Early Chinese Thought, p. 71)
  • 46
    • 80054206151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 4A:10, 6A:11
    • Mencius 4A:10, 6A:11
  • 47
    • 80054209744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Analects 12:22
    • Analects 12:22
  • 48
    • 80054209749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius, 4A:4, 4B:28, 7A:45, 7A:46, 7B:1
    • Mencius, 4A:4, 4B:28, 7A:45, 7A:46, 7B:1
  • 49
    • 0003409985 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, Since the feelings of pleasure and pain operate in the cultivation of disposition, I do not take them to form a separate aspect of Aristotle's virtue. More important, the feelings of pleasure and pain in Aristotle involve no altruistic or benevolent love for others
    • In Julia Annas's analysis, Aristotle's virtue, in addition to the dispositional and intellectual aspects, also has an affective aspect. This means that virtues "involve our feelings, especially our feelings of pleasure and pain, and developing a virtue involves habituating our feelings in certain ways" (The Morality of Happiness [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993], p. 49). Since the feelings of pleasure and pain operate in the cultivation of disposition, I do not take them to form a separate aspect of Aristotle's virtue. More important, the feelings of pleasure and pain in Aristotle involve no altruistic or benevolent love for others
    • (1993) The Morality of Happiness , pp. 49
  • 50
    • 0001825773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue: Confucius and Aristotle
    • 335ff
    • Jiyuan Yu, "Virtue: Confucius and Aristotle," Philosophy East and West 48, no. 2 (1998): 335ff
    • (1998) Philosophy East and West , vol.48 , Issue.2
    • Yu, J.1
  • 51
    • 80054206150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1103a25
    • NE, 1103a25
  • 52
    • 80054206159 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1103al4-17; a25; a34-b4; b14-25; 1104a33-b2; 1105al4-16
    • NE, 1103al4-17; a25; a34-b4; b14-25; 1104a33-b2; 1105al4-16
  • 53
    • 80054209745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1114a12-14
    • NE, 1114a12-14
  • 54
    • 80054176651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1140b11-20, 1144a8-9, 1144a30-31, 1145a5-6; 1151a15-19
    • NE, 1140b11-20, 1144a8-9, 1144a30-31, 1145a5-6; 1151a15-19
  • 55
    • 80054206113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius 7B:3
    • Mencius 7B:3
  • 56
    • 80054258825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1103b23-25
    • NE, 1103b23-25
  • 57
    • 80054258826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sometimes Aristotle suggests that we have a natural ground for habituation. We have a natural part in the human soul that obeys reason, and we have natural virtues. Without these natural factors, one cannot acquire virtues through habituation. As a stone cannot be habituated to go up no matter how hard you try NE, 1103a21-23
    • Sometimes Aristotle suggests that we have a natural ground for habituation. We have a natural part in the human soul that obeys reason, and we have natural virtues. Without these natural factors, one cannot acquire virtues through habituation. As a stone cannot be habituated to go up no matter how hard you try (NE, 1103a21-23)
  • 58
    • 80054240961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle even claims that what habituation achieves is to perfect our nature (NE, 1103a25). But it is not clear how this line of thought can be reconciled with the importance of habituation that he underscores, and it is also not an idea on which he spends much time
    • Aristotle even claims that what habituation achieves is to perfect our nature (NE, 1103a25). But it is not clear how this line of thought can be reconciled with the importance of habituation that he underscores, and it is also not an idea on which he spends much time
  • 59
    • 80054176640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius, 1A:3, 3A:3
    • Mencius, 1A:3, 3A:3
  • 60
    • 80054206118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1178a9-10
    • NE, 1178a9-10
  • 61
    • 0009282255 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley, CA: University of California Press
    • This point is also made by Thomas Nagel when he says: "Aristotle believes, in short, that human life is not important enough for humans to spend their lives on. A person should seek to transcend not only his individual practical concerns but also those of society or humanity as a whole" ("Aristotle on Eudalmonia," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, edited by A. O. Rorty [Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1980], p. 12)
    • (1980) Essays on Aristotle's Ethics , pp. 12
    • Rorty, A.O.1
  • 62
    • 80054209737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1178b22-23
    • NE, 1178b22-23
  • 63
    • 80054206101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Metaphysics, 1072b15, 23-24
    • Metaphysics, 1072b15, 23-24
  • 65
    • 33745208169 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • For instance, Anthony Kenny says, "Aristotle's belief that the pursuit of happiness must be the pursuit of a single dominant aim, and his account of the nature of philosophy, seem to be both so seriously mistaken as to make unprofitable a discussion of his arguments that happiness consists in theoria" (The Aristotelian Ethics [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978], p. 58)
    • (1978) The Aristotelian Ethics , pp. 58
  • 66
    • 80054176614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius, 7A:1
    • Mencius, 7A:1
  • 67
    • 80054241381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1177a21-22, 1177a24, 1177a26-34
    • NE, 1177a21-22, 1177a24, 1177a26-34
  • 68
    • 80054209718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius, 6A:7
    • Mencius, 6A:7
  • 69
    • 80054209725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius, 4B:28
    • Mencius, 4B:28
  • 70
    • 80054176625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1177b27-28
    • NE, 1177b27-28
  • 71
    • 80054258804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is also what Plato means in the Phaedo by saying that to do philosophy is to practice death
    • This is also what Plato means in the Phaedo by saying that to do philosophy is to practice death
  • 72
    • 80054176612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1177b32-1178a2
    • NE, 1177b32-1178a2
  • 73
    • 80054241367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE, 1142a26
    • NE, 1142a26
  • 74
    • 80054209061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mencius's sages, because of their developed sense of right and wrong, are usually very critical of moral requirements themselves. When they feel it suitable, they would violate the requirement. For instance, the sage King Shun married without telling his father, because he was afraid his father would reject his love (Mencius 4A26)
    • Mencius's sages, because of their developed sense of right and wrong, are usually very critical of moral requirements themselves. When they feel it suitable, they would violate the requirement. For instance, the sage King Shun married without telling his father, because he was afraid his father would reject his love (Mencius 4A26)
  • 75
    • 80054241096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at the University of Oxford, November 6. I wish to thank Nick Bunnin for editing that version and for including it in Chinese Philosophy Working Papers no. 8, I am also grateful for all the helpful comments from the participants at that conference, and for comments from Pablo DeGreiff, Peter Hare, Xinyan Jiang, and Roger Worthington
    • An earlier version of this article was presented at a symposium "Chinese Accounts of Finitude and the Self: Beyond Comparative Philosophy," at the University of Oxford, November 6, 1999. I wish to thank Nick Bunnin for editing that version and for including it in Chinese Philosophy Working Papers (no. 8). I am also grateful for all the helpful comments from the participants at that conference, and for comments from Pablo DeGreiff, Peter Hare, Xinyan Jiang, and Roger Worthington
    • (1999) Chinese Accounts of Finitude and the Self: Beyond Comparative Philosophy


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.