메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 66, Issue 3, 2008, Pages 237-251

Kant's justified dismissal of artistic sublimity

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049323077     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1540-6245.2008.00306.x     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (27)

References (20)
  • 3
    • 22144483868 scopus 로고
    • Kant on Fine Art: Artistic Sublimity Shaped by Beauty
    • Robert Wicks, "Kant on Fine Art: Artistic Sublimity Shaped by Beauty," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1995): 189-193
    • (1995) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.53 , pp. 189-193
    • Wicks, R.1
  • 5
    • 0037996775 scopus 로고
    • Taste, Sublimity, and Genius: The Aesthetics of Nature and Art
    • ed. Paul Guyer Cambridge University Press
    • Eva Schaper, "Taste, Sublimity, and Genius: The Aesthetics of Nature and Art," in The Cambridge Companion to Kant, ed. Paul Guyer (Cambridge University Press, 1992)
    • (1992) The Cambridge Companion to Kant
    • Schaper, E.1
  • 9
    • 61049479269 scopus 로고
    • The Kantian Sublime: Aesthetic Judgment and Religious Feeling
    • See Allan Lazaroff "The Kantian Sublime: Aesthetic Judgment and Religious Feeling," Kant Studien 71 (1980): 202-220, quote from p. 206
    • (1980) Kant Studien , vol.71 , pp. 202-220
    • Lazaroff, A.1
  • 10
    • 61049136800 scopus 로고
    • Gracyk, Sublimity, Ugliness, and Formlessness in Kant's Aesthetic Theory
    • So Kant must have in mind the phenomenological peculiarity of the experience of the mathematically sublime in which the magnitude of the object makes its form incomprehensible as a unified whole. I discuss this below. For a slightly different but generally similar line of interpretation of the "formlessness" of sublime objects, see Theodore A. Gracyk, "Sublimity, Ugliness, and Formlessness in Kant's Aesthetic Theory," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 45 (1986): 49-56
    • (1986) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.45 , pp. 49-56
    • Theodore, A.1
  • 11
    • 33748890830 scopus 로고
    • The Kantian Sublime and the Nostalgia for Violence
    • Moving from this extra cautiousness of Kant about the objective subreption in the sublime, Huhn, interestingly, argues that the sublime is more central and constitutive than the beautiful in Kant's aesthetics; see Thomas Huhn, "The Kantian Sublime and the Nostalgia for Violence," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1995): 269-275
    • (1995) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.53 , pp. 269-275
    • Huhn, T.1
  • 13
    • 0003520282 scopus 로고
    • hereafter Observations, trans. John T. Goldwait University of California Press
    • Kant gives the same examples also in his precritical aesthetic treatise; see Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime (hereafter Observations), trans. John T. Goldwait (University of California Press, 1960), p. 49
    • (1960) Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime , pp. 49
  • 15
    • 79953917567 scopus 로고
    • trans, Southern Illinois University Press, §68
    • Immanuel Kant, Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, trans. Victor Lyle Dowdell (Southern Illinois University Press, 1978), §68, 7:243, p. 146
    • (1978) Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View , vol.7 , Issue.243 , pp. 146
    • Kant, I.1
  • 16
    • 33748543708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Allison follows a similar line of interpretation and concludes that "judgments of the sublime in art are inherently adherent"; see Allison, Kant's Theory of Taste, p. 339
    • Kant's Theory of Taste , pp. 339
    • Allison1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.