메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 61, Issue 2, 2003, Pages 149-157

The Croce-Collingwood theory as theory

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049313802     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1540-6245.00104     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (23)

References (59)
  • 1
    • 79954372555 scopus 로고
    • I refer to the works of Collingwood and Croce according to abbreviated titles. For Collingwood's works: Speculum Mentis (Oxford University Press, 1924) is noted as SM
    • (1924) For Collingwood's works: Speculum Mentis
  • 2
    • 0004238031 scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press
    • The Principles of Art (Oxford University Press, 1938) is noted as PA
    • (1938) The Principles of Art
  • 7
  • 10
    • 79954039024 scopus 로고
    • The Totality of Artistic Expression
    • Oxford University Press
    • "The Totality of Artistic Expression," in Philosophy, Poetry, History (Oxford University Press, 1966)
    • (1966) Philosophy, Poetry, History
  • 11
    • 79954184089 scopus 로고
    • Milan: Riccardo Ricciardi is noted as TAE
    • trans. C. Sprigge from Filosofia, Poesia, Storia (Milan: Riccardo Ricciardi, 1951), is noted as TAE
    • (1951) Filosofia, Poesia, Storia
    • Sprigge, C.1
  • 13
    • 0004261997 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
    • Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1968)
    • (1968) Languages of Art
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 14
    • 0004175786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2nd ed, Cambridge University Press
    • Richard Wollheim, Art and Its Objects, 2nd ed. (Cambridge University Press, 1980)
    • (1980) Art and Its Objects
    • Wollheim, R.1
  • 15
    • 84971124348 scopus 로고
    • The Croce-Collingwood Theory of Art
    • John Hospers, "The Croce-Collingwood Theory of Art," Philosophy 31 (1956): 291-308
    • (1956) Philosophy , vol.31 , pp. 291-308
    • Hospers, J.1
  • 16
    • 61049150552 scopus 로고
    • Does Traditional Aesthetics Rest on a Mistake?
    • William Kennick, "Does Traditional Aesthetics Rest on a Mistake?" Mind 67 (1958): 317-334
    • (1958) Mind , vol.67 , pp. 317-334
    • Kennick, W.1
  • 17
    • 79958514210 scopus 로고
    • The Dreariness of Aesthetics
    • ed. W. Elton Basil Blackwell
    • John Passmore, "The Dreariness of Aesthetics," in Aesthetics and Language, ed. W. Elton (Basil Blackwell, 1959), pp. 36-55
    • (1959) Aesthetics and Language , pp. 36-55
    • Passmore, J.1
  • 20
    • 0007178604 scopus 로고
    • The Artistic Enfranchisement of Real Objects: The Artworld
    • Arthur Danto, "The Artistic Enfranchisement of Real Objects: The Artworld," The Journal of Philosophy 61 (1964): 571-584
    • (1964) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.61 , pp. 571-584
    • Danto, A.1
  • 23
    • 79954010775 scopus 로고
    • In The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (Harvard University Press, 1981), Danto offers an alternative explanation: our concern with art just is, or has become, partly reflexive, a concern with the nature of the interest we take in works of art
    • (1981) The Transfiguration of the Commonplace Harvard
  • 24
    • 24944485098 scopus 로고
    • Art, Emotion and Expression
    • See, for example, R. Wilkinson, "Art, Emotion and Expression," in Philosophical Aesthetics, ed. O. Hanfling (London: Blackwell, 1992), pp. 186-194
    • (1992) Philosophical Aesthetics , pp. 186-194
    • Wilkinson, R.1
  • 25
    • 79954181672 scopus 로고
    • On Reading Collingwood's Principles of Art
    • True, Collingwood says that Book 1 of the Principles of Art is an exercise in conceptual analysis. And that theoretical elements figure prominently there does not prove that he was wrong to say so; analysis is almost always idealization, and in practice must be informed by theoretical considerations. However, the plausibility, and indeed the content, as Collingwood points out, of the claim that Art is Expression is derived almost wholly from the theories propounded in Book 2. It was, I think, a needless and bad strategic maneuver on Collingwood's part to have pretended that he could first, by strictly analytical means, mark out the logical space to be filled by a theory. For a more detailed discussion of this issue with respect to Collingwood, see J. Grant, "On Reading Collingwood's Principles of Art," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 46 (1987): 239-248
    • (1987) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.46 , pp. 239-248
    • Grant, J.1
  • 26
    • 79954265078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Croce and Collingwood
    • For a recent, unsympathetic account of what below I call the Expression Thesis in Croce and Collingwood, see Gordon Graham, "Croce and Collingwood," in The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, ed. B. Gaut and D. Lopes (London: Routledge, 2000), pp.75-85
    • (2000) The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics , pp. 75-85
    • Graham, G.1
  • 27
    • 1642277569 scopus 로고
    • A Study of the Irrefutability of Two Aesthetic Theories
    • For pungent criticism of what I call the Ideality Thesis, see Beryl Lake, "A Study of the Irrefutability of Two Aesthetic Theories," in Aesthetics and Language, ed. W. Elton (London: Blackwell, 1959), pp. 100-113
    • (1959) Aesthetics and Language , pp. 100-113
    • Lake, B.1
  • 29
    • 79954350248 scopus 로고
    • Collingwood and Art Media: a Reply
    • John Hospers, in "Collingwood and Art Media: a Reply," Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 2 (1971): 43-46, stresses the importance of this bit of Kantianism in both Croce and Collingwood
    • (1971) Southwestern Journal of Philosophy , vol.2 , pp. 43-46
    • Hospers, J.1
  • 30
    • 79954396712 scopus 로고
    • A Critical Outline of Collingwood's Philosophy of Art
    • For detailed analysis and criticisms of Collingwood's theory specifically, see P. Jones, "A Critical Outline of Collingwood's Philosophy of Art," ed. M. Krausz, Critical Essays on the Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood (Oxford University Press, 1972), pp. 42-67
    • (1972) Critical Essays on the Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood , pp. 42-67
    • Jones, P.1
  • 31
    • 61049554156 scopus 로고
    • A Reconsideration of the Croce-Dewey Exchange
    • For problems internal to Croce's theory of art, see G. Douglas, "A Reconsideration of the Croce-Dewey Exchange," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 28 (1970): 497-504
    • (1970) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.28 , pp. 497-504
    • Douglas, G.1
  • 35
    • 79954035178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the earlier account in Speculum Mentis (pp. 80-91), Collingwood holds that since intuition, in itself, is not assertoric, it cannot be meaningful, hence, it cannot be expressive
    • the earlier account in Speculum Mentis , pp. 80-91
  • 38
    • 79954220404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Collingwood seems to struggle with this issue on p. 239, top; in answering the question he sets for himself, he really only answers the question with respect to the psychical emotions
    • Collingwood seems to struggle with this issue , pp. 239
  • 39
    • 79953919259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might think that Croce's later emphasis on the "lyrical intuition" (see especially The Essence of Aesthetic, pp. 28-33) represents such a distinction, but it is clear, on close reading, that what Croce has in mind is a difference of degree rather than principle
    • especially The Essence of Aesthetic , pp. 28-33
  • 40
    • 79956992766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For its appearance in Croce, see "Aesthetics," pp. 229-231
    • Aesthetics , pp. 229-231
    • Croce1    see2
  • 42
    • 84893094837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aesthetic, pp. 104-110
    • Aesthetic , pp. 104-110
  • 44
    • 61149298689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Collingwood's Commitments: A Reply to Hausman and Dilworth
    • and "Collingwood's Commitments: A Reply to Hausman and Dilworth," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56 (1998): 396-398
    • (1998) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.56 , pp. 396-398
  • 48
    • 0039276827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the remarks about the experience of being understood, The Principles of Art, pp. 317-318. I discuss this passage below
    • The Principles of Art , pp. 317-318
  • 49
    • 79954407513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Reading Collingwood's
    • On this issue, see also Grant, "On Reading Collingwood's Principles of Art."
    • Principles of Art
    • Grant1
  • 53
    • 79954067967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see "Aesthetics," p. 567. The argument to follow is very near the surface here of Croce's distinction between the physical object and the work of art
    • Aesthetics , pp. 567
  • 54
    • 79954192628 scopus 로고
    • the excellent article by Don Taylor
    • For criticism of Collingwood on this point, see the excellent article by Don Taylor, "Art, Craft and History," Clio 2 (1973): 239-278. Taylor argues that Collingwood's attempt to distinguish art ontologically from amusement-craft must fail; for some amusements achieve their end precisely by exercising the imagination. But according to Taylor, that does not mean that the distinction cannot be made, and made as sharply as we think it ought to be: Art can be distinguished, if not by its exercising the imagination, then by the sorts of things it is concerned to imagine. The distinction is moral, axiological, perhaps epistemological, but not ontological
    • (1973) Art, Craft and History, Clio , vol.2 , pp. 239-278
  • 55
    • 0010940827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is most interesting that at the time of Speculum Mentis, when Collingwood had yet to accept Croce's emphasis on feeling as the key to expression, he was much closer to the idea that beauty is somehow connected with truth; indeed, his attempt to make this out in terms of his logic of question and answer (Speculum Mentis, pp. 76-80), is impressive, and one wishes he had done more with it in the later work
    • Speculum Mentis , pp. 76-80
  • 56
    • 79954128154 scopus 로고
    • Readers familiar with it may wonder why I concentrate on the discussion in Art and Its Objects, omitting the more sustained criticism Wollheim offers in his later article, "On an Alleged Inconsistency in Collingwood's Aesthetics," in Critical Essays on the Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood, ed. M. Krausz (Oxford University Press, 1972), pp. 68-78. The reason is that the former makes a more fundamental and decisive point. Very briefly, Wollheim's point in the 1972 essay is that the divorce of the artwork from the bodily work is plausible only with respect to those arts that admit of notation, and that are most suitably identified with types rather than tokens (e.g., music, poetry). Unlike those cases, it is just not true that we can credit someone with having made a sculpture in advance of her or his having sculpted it. This point is not decisive, however: one might think it accidental that the plastic arts are not notated (although, of course, there are well-known difficulties here). Further, as stressed, that the imaginative experience should, as a matter of psychological fact, depend upon actual perception, is consistent with the Ideality Thesis. Thus, the fact that we do not credit merely imagined sculptures might be perfectly intelligible even if the Ideality Thesis were true, indeed, even if we actually subscribed to it. What is needed is to show that something in the very notion of art - in our conception of its purpose or value - rules this out. That is what the argument from Art and Its Objects succeeds in doing
    • (1972) Critical Essays on the Philosophy , pp. 68-78
    • Collingwood1    ed. M. Krausz, R.G.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.