메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 105, Issue 7, 2008, Pages 371-388

Bringing moral responsibility down to earth

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049218434     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2008105737     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (90)

References (49)
  • 3
    • 0033211718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recent Work on Moral Responsibility
    • it is possible that determinism is consistent with responsibility but not with free will. Thus, it is often important to distinguish between moral-responsibility compatibilism and free will compatibilism, and we will keep the views distinct here
    • As John Fischer has emphasized in "Recent Work on Moral Responsibility" Ethics, CX (1999): 93-139, it is possible that determinism is consistent with responsibility but not with free will. Thus, it is often important to distinguish between moral-responsibility compatibilism and free will compatibilism, and we will keep the views distinct here
    • (1999) Ethics , vol.110 , pp. 93-139
    • Fischer, J.1
  • 4
    • 27344441057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Responsibility, Luck, and Chance: Reflections on Free Will and Indeterminism
    • May, on p. 217
    • Kane, "Responsibility, Luck, and Chance: Reflections on Free Will and Indeterminism" this JOURNAL, XCVI, 5 (May 1999): 217-40, on p. 217
    • (1999) JOURNAL , vol.96 , pp. 217-240
    • Kane1
  • 7
    • 27344460599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Surveying Freedom: Folk Intuitions about Free Will and Responsibility
    • Nahmias, S. Morris, T. Nadelhoffer, and J. Turner, "Surveying Freedom: Folk Intuitions about Free Will and Responsibility," Philosophical Psychology, XVIII, 5 (2005): 561-84
    • (2005) Philosophical Psychology , vol.18 , pp. 561-584
    • Nahmias1    Morris, S.2    Nadelhoffer, T.3    Turner, J.4
  • 8
    • 58649090384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions
    • Nichols and Knobe, "Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions," Noûs, XLI, 4 (2007): 663-85
    • (2007) Noûs , vol.41 , pp. 663-685
    • And Knobe, N.1
  • 9
    • 85039129249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We hope to explore whether these results extend to other populations. (We hope even more that others will explore whether our results extend to other populations!) However, it is important to note that we are primarily looking at whether subjects from the same population give different answers in the different conditions.
    • We hope to explore whether these results extend to other populations. (We hope even more that others will explore whether our results extend to other populations!) However, it is important to note that we are primarily looking at whether subjects from the same population give different answers in the different conditions
  • 10
    • 85039108732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The mean response in Actual was 3.58, and the mean response in Alternate was 5.06 (4 is the midline). The difference between the conditions was significant (t (74) = 3.611, p = .001).
    • The mean response in Actual was 3.58, and the mean response in Alternate was 5.06 (4 is the midline). The difference between the conditions was significant (t (74) = 3.611, p = .001)
  • 11
    • 0004295505 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • Interestingly, these responses parallel Peter van Inwagen's claim that he thinks that moral responsibility is incompatible with determinism but that if he came to believe determinism was true, he would be a compatibilist (see An Essay on Free Will (New York: Oxford, 1983))
    • (1983) An Essay on Free Will
  • 12
    • 0003992974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Metaphysical flipflopping in Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility
    • New York: Cambridge
    • Fisher and Mark Ravizza label this view "metaphysical flipflopping" in Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility (New York: Cambridge, 1998)
    • (1998)
    • Fisher1    Ravizza, M.2
  • 13
    • 85039105644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The mean response in Actual was 5.35, and the mean response in Alternate was 3.67. The difference between the conditions was significant (t (65) = -4.426, p < .001). Note that the question was positively framed, while the other two were framed negatively, so we in fact would expect this sort of inversion in the agreement values. These values are consistent with what would be expected if judgments of moral responsibility and blame-worthiness were correlated.
    • The mean response in Actual was 5.35, and the mean response in Alternate was 3.67. The difference between the conditions was significant (t (65) = -4.426, p < .001). Note that the question was positively framed, while the other two were framed negatively, so we in fact would expect this sort of inversion in the agreement values. These values are consistent with what would be expected if judgments of moral responsibility and blame-worthiness were correlated
  • 14
    • 85039118145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While the difference is significant (t (74, 2.362, p < .05, in both conditions, the mean response was above the midline. In the Actual condition, the mean response was 4.3, and in the Alternate condition, the mean response was 5.3. Overall, these results suggest that there was stronger agreement to the statement that people (in a determinist universe) lacked freedom of choice than that they lacked moral responsibility. Interestingly, we found that this difference was statistically significant in the Actual condition (t (39, 2.456, p < .05, but not in the Alternate condition (t 35, 843, p, 405, n.s
    • While the difference is significant (t (74) = 2.362, p < .05), in both conditions, the mean response was above the midline. In the Actual condition, the mean response was 4.3, and in the Alternate condition, the mean response was 5.3. Overall, these results suggest that there was stronger agreement to the statement that people (in a determinist universe) lacked freedom of choice than that they lacked moral responsibility. Interestingly, we found that this difference was statistically significant in the Actual condition (t (39) = -2.456, p < .05), but not in the Alternate condition (t (35) = -.843, p = .405, n.s.)
  • 16
    • 33747873670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neuroscientific Challenges to Free Will and Responsibility
    • For a discussion of why such a conclusion is not warranted on the basis of neuroscientific research, see Adina L. Roskies, "Neuroscientific Challenges to Free Will and Responsibility," Trends in Cognitive Sciences, X (2006): 419-23
    • (2006) Trends in Cognitive Sciences , vol.10 , pp. 419-423
    • Roskies, A.L.1
  • 18
    • 85039128099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Question of the Will
    • October 15
    • C. Goldberg, "A Question of the Will," The Boston Globe (October 15, 2002), p. C1
    • (2002) The Boston Globe
    • Goldberg, C.1
  • 19
    • 3543091729 scopus 로고
    • Free Will Is a Verifiable Assumption: A Reply to Garrett and Viney
    • R.J. Rychlak and J.F. Rychlak, "Free Will Is a Verifiable Assumption: A Reply to Garrett and Viney," New Ideas in Psychology, VIII (1990): 43-51
    • (1990) New Ideas in Psychology , vol.8 , pp. 43-51
    • Rychlak, R.J.1    Rychlak, J.F.2
  • 20
    • 17544382953 scopus 로고
    • Sorry, but Your Soul Just Died
    • There are a variety of deterministic accounts of decision and action. Most work in neuroethics does not clearly distinguish between neurological determinism and metaphysical determinism. For some purposes it matters whether the deterministic thesis is neurological, but for our purposes it does not. For ease of exposition we talk about determinism generically.
    • and T. Wolfe, "Sorry, But Your Soul Just Died," Forbes, CLVIII (1990): 210. There are a variety of deterministic accounts of decision and action. Most work in neuroethics does not clearly distinguish between neurological determinism and metaphysical determinism. For some purposes it matters whether the deterministic thesis is neurological, but for our purposes it does not. For ease of exposition we talk about determinism generically
    • (1990) Forbes , vol.48 , pp. 210
    • Wolfe, T.1
  • 21
    • 61049353555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Folk Intuitions, Slippery Slopes, and Necessary Fictions: An Essay on Saul Smilansky's Illusionism
    • For arguments to a similar conclusion, see T. Nadelhoffer and A. Feltz, "Folk Intuitions, Slippery Slopes, and Necessary Fictions: An Essay on Saul Smilansky's Illusionism," Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXXI (2007): 202-13
    • (2007) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.31 , pp. 202-213
    • Nadelhoffer, T.1    Feltz, A.2
  • 22
    • 85039083226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to say that neuroscientific advances pose no threat to the social order; only that this particular focus for worry is overblown
    • This is not to say that neuroscientific advances pose no threat to the social order; only that this particular focus for worry is overblown
  • 24
    • 0003011116 scopus 로고
    • Automatic and Conscious Processing of Social Information
    • R.S.J. Wyer and T.K. Srull, eds, Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
    • See, for example, J.A. Bargh "Automatic and Conscious Processing of Social Information, " in R.S.J. Wyer and T.K. Srull, eds., Handbook of Social Cognition, Volume III (Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1984), pp. 1-44
    • (1984) Handbook of Social Cognition , vol.3 , pp. 1-44
    • Bargh, J.A.1
  • 25
    • 85047681068 scopus 로고
    • Heuristic versus Systematic Information Processing and the Use of Source versus Message Cues in Persuasion
    • See also S. Chaiken, "Heuristic versus Systematic Information Processing and the Use of Source versus Message Cues in Persuasion," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, XXXIX (1980): 752-66
    • (1980) Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , vol.39 , pp. 752-766
    • Chaiken, S.1
  • 26
    • 0002016719 scopus 로고
    • Heuristic and Systematic Information Processing within and beyond the Persuasion Context
    • J.S. Uleman and J.A. Bargh, eds, New York: Guilford
    • and S. Chaiken, A. Liberman, and A. Eagly, "Heuristic and Systematic Information Processing within and beyond the Persuasion Context," in J.S. Uleman and J.A. Bargh, eds., Unintended Thought (New York: Guilford,1989), pp. 212-52
    • (1989) Unintended Thought , pp. 212-252
    • Chaiken, S.1    Liberman, A.2    Eagly, A.3
  • 27
    • 58149372982 scopus 로고
    • The Effects of Involvement on Responses to Argument Quantity and Quality: Central and Peripheral Routes to Persuasion
    • and R. Petty and J. Cacioppo, "The Effects of Involvement on Responses to Argument Quantity and Quality: Central and Peripheral Routes to Persuasion," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, XLVI (1984): 69-81
    • (1984) Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , vol.46 , pp. 69-81
    • Petty, R.1    Cacioppo, J.2
  • 28
    • 85047682342 scopus 로고
    • Issue Involvement Can Increase or Decrease Persuasion by Enhancing Message-Relevant Cognitive Responses
    • R. Petty and J. Cacioppo, "Issue Involvement Can Increase or Decrease Persuasion by Enhancing Message-Relevant Cognitive Responses," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, XXXVII (1979): 1915-26
    • (1979) Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , vol.37 , pp. 1915-1926
    • Petty, R.1    Cacioppo, J.2
  • 30
    • 21844513016 scopus 로고
    • When Bad Isn't All Bad: Strategic Use of Sample Information in Generalization and Stereotyping
    • B. Doosje, R. Spears, and W. Koomen, "When Bad Isn't All Bad: Strategic Use of Sample Information in Generalization and Stereotyping," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, LXIX (1995): 642-55
    • (1995) Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , vol.69 , pp. 642-655
    • Doosje, B.1    Spears, R.2    Koomen, W.3
  • 33
    • 85039129133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We thank Richard Holton for suggesting the cognitive dissonance explanation to us
    • We thank Richard Holton for suggesting the cognitive dissonance explanation to us
  • 34
    • 0007227553 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • Jackson, Conditionals (New York: Oxford, 1991)
    • (1991) Conditionals
    • Jackson1
  • 35
    • 84963002103 scopus 로고
    • Dogmatism, Junk Knowledge, and Conditionals
    • A nonmotivational interpretation of the results may also be closely related to the nonrobust conditional story. Just this pattern holds in cases in which one's credence in the conditional is less strong than one's credence in the consequent in some contexts. Forced to give up something in those contexts, one will give up the conditional. On this view, the explanation would not be motivational, but rather cognitive. We thank Andy Egan for pointing this out
    • Sorensen, "Dogmatism, Junk Knowledge, and Conditionals," Philosophical Quarterly, XXXVIII (1988): 433-54. A nonmotivational interpretation of the results may also be closely related to the nonrobust conditional story. Just this pattern holds in cases in which one's credence in the conditional is less strong than one's credence in the consequent in some contexts. Forced to give up something in those contexts, one will give up the conditional. On this view, the explanation would not be motivational, but rather cognitive. We thank Andy Egan for pointing this out
    • (1988) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.38 , pp. 433-454
    • Sorensen1
  • 36
  • 40
    • 27744443511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hypnotically Induced Disgust Makes Moral Judgments More Severe
    • T. Wheatley and J. Haidt, "Hypnotically Induced Disgust Makes Moral Judgments More Severe," Psychological Science, XVI (2005): 780-84
    • (2005) Psychological Science , vol.16 , pp. 780-784
    • Wheatley, T.1    Haidt, J.2
  • 41
    • 0002636819 scopus 로고
    • In-group Favoritism and Statistical Reasoning in Social Inference
    • M. Schaller, "In-group Favoritism and Statistical Reasoning in Social Inference," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, LXIII (1992): 61-74
    • (1992) Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , vol.63 , pp. 61-74
    • Schaller, M.1
  • 42
    • 33746169424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Qualia and Analytic Conditionals
    • March
    • Braddon-Mitchell, "Qualia and Analytic Conditionals," this JOURNAL, C, 3 (March 2003): 111-35
    • (2003) JOURNAL , vol.100 , Issue.3 , pp. 111-135
    • Braddon-Mitchell1
  • 43
    • 85039081343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Braddon-Mitchell goes on to refine this view taking account of the importance of centered possible worlds; this is a refinement that does not matter much for our purposes, since our judgments about moral responsibility are not made on the basis of first-person experiences
    • Braddon-Mitchell goes on to refine this view taking account of the importance of centered possible worlds; this is a refinement that does not matter much for our purposes, since our judgments about moral responsibility are not made on the basis of first-person experiences
  • 46
    • 45349083543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • Other two-dimensionalist accounts vary on a number of dimensions; for a state-of-the-art anthology see M. Garcia-Carpintero and J. Macia, eds., Two-Dimensional Semantics (New York: Oxford, 2006)
    • (2006) Two-Dimensional Semantics
    • Garcia-Carpintero, M.1    MacIa, J.2
  • 47
    • 34547903877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intuitions and Individual Differences: The Knobe Effect Revisited
    • But in the present case, we do not have enough information to know whether the individual differences in intuitions about moral responsibility are stable or random, and so we are unable to begin to evaluate whether the minority respondents should be regarded as mistaken in their responses.
    • Of course, our data do not show anything approaching complete unanimity in intuitions, and Derk Pereboom has suggested (personal communication) that this raises important questions about the status of the 2-D explanation of our findings. On the 2-D account, how do we evaluate the minority of responses in the Actual condition that are incompatibilist? Are such judgments mistaken? This implicates delicate issues about how to interpret individual differences. Ideally, one would like to know whether the variation tracks stable features of the individual, or whether the variation is just noise. In the case of some philosophically-relevant intuitions, the individual differences do seem to be stable. See Nichols and J. Ulatowski, "Intuitions and Individual Differences: The Knobe Effect Revisited," Mind and Language, XXII (2007): 346-65. But in the present case, we do not have enough information to know whether the individual differences in intuitions about moral responsibility are stable or random, and so we are unable to begin to evaluate whether the minority respondents should be regarded as mistaken in their responses
    • (2007) Mind and Language , vol.22 , pp. 346-365
    • Ulatowski, Nichols9J.1
  • 48
    • 0004178922 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard
    • We do see a varied pattern of judgments about natural kinds across worlds (see, for example, Saul Kripke's Naming and Necessity (Cambridge: Harvard, 1972)
    • (1972) Naming and Necessity
    • Kripke, S.1
  • 49
    • 0000692309 scopus 로고
    • The Meaning of 'Meaning'
    • New York: Cambridge, However, there is no obvious reason to expect these judgments to be driven by emotional responses to the possible worlds scenarios. This suggests that the emotion-based model is not sufficient for explaining the pattern of judgments for all our modal intuitions. There may be other factors that also lead to differences in cross-world judgments
    • and Hilary Putnam's "The Meaning of 'Meaning'," in Mind, Language and Reality (New York: Cambridge, 1975), p. 215-71). However, there is no obvious reason to expect these judgments to be driven by emotional responses to the possible worlds scenarios. This suggests that the emotion-based model is not sufficient for explaining the pattern of judgments for all our modal intuitions. There may be other factors that also lead to differences in cross-world judgments
    • (1975) Mind, Language and Reality , pp. 215-271
    • Putnam, H.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.