-
4
-
-
80054534593
-
Politic Society
-
Studies in the Reformation: Luther to Hooker, C. W. Dugmore (ed. ), London , 153
-
'The Philosopher of the "Politic Society": Richard Hooker as a Political Thinker', in W. D. J. Cargill Thompson, Studies in the Reformation: Luther to Hooker, C. W. Dugmore (ed. ), London 1980, pp. 149, 153.
-
(1980)
Richard Hooker As A Political Thinker
, pp. 149
-
-
Thompson, W.D.J.C.1
-
7
-
-
80054568556
-
The Place of Hooker in the History of Thought. Paul Forte finds similar usage between Aquinas and Hooker in dealing with law in 'Richard Hooker's Theory of Law
-
Peter Munz provides a survey of Hooker's indebtedness to Thomistic sources in Appendix A, The Place of Hooker in the History of Thought. Paul Forte finds similar usage between Aquinas and Hooker in dealing with law in 'Richard Hooker's Theory of Law', Journal of Medieval and Renaissance Studies, Vol. 12, 1982, p. 139.
-
(1982)
Journal of Medieval and Renaissance Studies
, vol.12
, pp. 139
-
-
Munz, P.1
-
10
-
-
80054600426
-
-
ST, 1a2ae. 90, 1, 3
-
ST, 1a2ae. 90, 1, 3.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
80054505695
-
-
ST, 1a2ae, 91, 2
-
ST, 1a2ae, 91, 2: 'The end of divine government is God himself, and his law is none other than himself. '
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
80054568626
-
-
ST, 1a2ae. 93, 4
-
St Thomas has it that 'his will is better spoken of as intelligence itself. ST, 1a2ae. 93, 4.
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
80054568622
-
-
ST, 1a2ae. 93, 3
-
ST, 1a2ae. 93, 3;
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
80054528904
-
-
Laws, 1, 3
-
Laws, 1, 3.
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
22944475914
-
-
Peter Lake remarks that, 'compared to the views of other protestants, Hooker's vision of sin as a species of ignorance, a sort of intellectual laziness, seemed almost benign'. Anglicans and Puritans?, p. 150.
-
Anglicans and Puritans?
, pp. 150
-
-
-
17
-
-
80054568565
-
-
Faulkner, pp. 86-7
-
Faulkner, pp. 86-7.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
80054505664
-
-
Faulkner, p. 62
-
Faulkner, p. 62.
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
80054568572
-
-
ST, 1a2ae, 93, 6
-
ST, 1a2ae, 93, 6.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
80054521434
-
-
ST, 1a2ae, 91, 4, 1
-
ST, 1a2ae, 91, 4, 1.
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
80054568517
-
-
Laws, 1. 6. 3
-
Laws, 1. 6. 3;
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
80054568570
-
-
cf. St Thomas at ST 1a2ae, 91, 3
-
cf. St Thomas at ST 1a2ae, 91, 3: 'The practical reason is concerned with things to be done, which are individual and contingent, not with necessary things that are the concern of theoretic reason. That is why human laws cannot have inerrancy that marks conclusions of demonstrative science'.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
80054568566
-
-
Laws, 1. 12. 2; 1. 8. 7; 1. 8. 9
-
Laws, 1. 12. 2; 1. 8. 7; 1. 8. 9.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
80054534637
-
-
Cf. ST, 1a2ae, 94, 4
-
Cf. ST, 1a2ae, 94, 4: 'as for its first common principles, here natural law is the same for all . . . Nevertheless in fewer cases where the desire or the information may be wanting . . . The knowledge . . . of what is right may be distorted by passion of bad custom. '
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
80054528852
-
-
De Legibus, C. W. Keyes (trans. ), London and Cambridge, Mass. 1928, II,4,10
-
De Legibus, C. W. Keyes (trans. ), London and Cambridge, Mass. 1928, II,4,10.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
80054521426
-
-
ST, 1a2ae, 91, 3
-
ST, 1a2ae, 91, 3.
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
80054568519
-
-
ST, 1a2ae, 94, 2
-
ST, 1a2ae, 94, 2.
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
80054534613
-
-
ST, a12ae, 94, 4
-
Aquinas distinguishes between primary and secondary precepts of natural law, the first being self-evident to theoretical reason and the second being the deductions from first principles applied to particular cases. ST, a12ae, 94, 4.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
80054568521
-
-
See e. g. , Laws, 1. 12. 2; 8. 9; 11. 8. 6; 111. 7. 2; 9. 3
-
See e. g. , Laws, 1. 12. 2; 8. 9; 11. 8. 6; 111. 7. 2; 9. 3.
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
80054528855
-
Locke and Hooker on the Finding of the law
-
E. De Jonghe, 'Locke and Hooker on the Finding of the law', Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 42, 1988, p. 316.
-
(1988)
Review of Metaphysics
, vol.42
, pp. 316
-
-
De Jonghe, E.1
-
36
-
-
0004276775
-
-
2nd edn, New York
-
Utilitarians might find Finnis' emphasis on satisfactions too strong: see e. g. , J. Rachels, The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 2nd edn, New York 1993, pp. 104-5.
-
(1993)
The Elements of Moral Philosophy
, pp. 104-105
-
-
Rachels, J.1
-
39
-
-
80054528815
-
-
Crowe, pp. 139-40
-
Crowe, pp. 139-40.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
80054528813
-
-
Munz, p. 64
-
Munz, p. 64.
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
0040541846
-
Rights, Natural Rights, and the Philosophy of Law
-
N. Kretzmann, A. Kenny, J. Pinborg and E. Stump eds, Cambridge
-
A. S. McGrade, 'Rights, Natural Rights, and the Philosophy of Law', in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, N. Kretzmann, A. Kenny, J. Pinborg and E. Stump (eds), Cambridge 1982, p. 752.
-
(1982)
The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
, pp. 752
-
-
McGrade, A.S.1
-
44
-
-
0004264902
-
-
Cambridge
-
The whole point of Moore's doctrine of intuitionism was to put a stop to questions about reasons, not to invite reason giving as Hooker does. For Moore, one just intuits certain simple properties, and they cannot be analysed further: 'If I am asked "What is good?", my answer is that good is good and that is the end of the matter. ' Principia Ethica, Cambridge 1903, p. 6.
-
(1903)
Principia Ethica
, pp. 6
-
-
-
45
-
-
80054521379
-
-
Brian Copenhaver's comments in, B. Copenhaver and Schmitt eds, pp
-
For a survey of the 'forgotten' philosophy of the Renaissance and the tendency of histories of philosophy to be proleptic, see Brian Copenhaver's comments in Renaissance Philosophy, B. Copenhaver and Schmitt (eds), pp. 339-46.
-
Renaissance Philosophy
, pp. 339-346
-
-
-
46
-
-
80054528808
-
The First Principle of Practical Reason
-
A. Kenny ed, London and Melbourne
-
G. Grisez, 'The First Principle of Practical Reason', in Aquinas, A. Kenny (ed. ), London and Melbourne 1969, pp. 340-82.
-
(1969)
Aquinas
, pp. 340-382
-
-
Grisez, G.1
-
47
-
-
0040171008
-
-
Washington
-
For concise criticism of the interpretation of Grisez and Finnis (above), see Ralph McInerny, Ethica Thomistica, Washington 1982, pp. 44-59.
-
(1982)
Ethica Thomistica
, pp. 44-59
-
-
McInerny, R.1
-
49
-
-
80054534529
-
-
See Grisez, pp. 372-82
-
See Grisez, pp. 372-82.
-
-
-
|