메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 60, Issue 1, 2002, Pages 27-35

Depiction, perception, and imagination: Responses to Richard Wollheim

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049160986     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1540-6245.00049     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (33)

References (51)
  • 4
    • 34548526913 scopus 로고
    • Seeing-In and Seeing Fictionally
    • James Hopkins and Anthony Savile, Oxford: Blackwell
    • Walton, "Seeing-In and Seeing Fictionally," in James Hopkins and Anthony Savile, Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Art: Essays for Richard Wollheim (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992), pp. 281-291
    • (1992) Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Art: Essays for Richard Wollheim , pp. 281-291
    • Walton1
  • 5
    • 61049522795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pictures and Photographs: Objections Answered
    • ed. Richard Allen and Murray Smith Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • and Walton, "Pictures and Photographs: Objections Answered," in Film Theory and Philosophy, ed. Richard Allen and Murray Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), pp. 60-75
    • (1997) Film Theory and Philosophy , pp. 60-75
    • Walton1
  • 8
    • 0009194003 scopus 로고
    • Explaining Depiction
    • There is room for skepticism about this. Perhaps such things can be depicted, misrepresented, as being visible. Robert Hopkins has interesting things to say about this in "Explaining Depiction," The Philosophical Review 104 (1995): 429-431
    • (1995) The Philosophical Review , vol.104 , pp. 429-431
    • Hopkins, R.1
  • 12
    • 61049249148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perhaps he means to be avoiding this commitment when he says, "Representations that are of things merely of some particular kind" cannot "sustain answers to the question, Which object? Which event? or, Which woman? Which battle?" ("On Pictorial Representation," p. 223.) But the sense in which they cannot is very unclear. These questions invite any number of reasonable answers: "That one," "The one in the picture," "The one so-and-so is now looking at," "The one wearing the fancy hat," "The one looking over her shoulder." Which if any of these answers is informative will of course depend on the context
    • On Pictorial Representation , pp. 223
  • 13
    • 79953921627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whether they are true when taken literally depends on one's theory of fiction. In Painting as an Art, Wollheim notes that "of course, "This is a picture of Venus' does not admit of existential generalization" (Painting as an Art, p. 361, n.16)
    • Painting As An Art , Issue.16 , pp. 361
  • 14
    • 61049274585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Formalism and Pictorial Organization
    • The representational content of a painting is "often, and totally misleadingly, referred to as its 'illusionistic' content," Wollheim remarks. And he speaks of "the unjustified assimilation of the representational to the illusionistic or the imitative" (Richard Wollheim, "On Formalism and Pictorial Organization," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 59[2001]: 131-132)
    • (2001) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.59 , pp. 131-132
    • Wollheim, R.1
  • 16
    • 79954360757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On my theory, it is fictional in the world of the picture that there are peasants but not that I see them. Both statements express fictional truths in the spectator's game world. Cf. my Mimesis as Make-Believe, pp. 293-304
    • My Mimesis As Make-Believe , pp. 293-304
  • 17
    • 79954225465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Those who think that there really is something (the woman in the picture) that I imagine seeing still have the problem of saying what sort of thing this is, although they needn't say that it is something that can actually be seen.
    • Those who think that there really is something (the woman in the picture) that I imagine seeing still have the problem of saying what sort of thing this is, although they needn't say that it is something that can actually be seen
  • 18
    • 79954222901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There may be no specific mode of cognitive access such that readers imagine knowing about a person in that manner. Nevertheless, they probably imagine that their cognitive access to the person is in some ordinary manner or other
    • There may be no specific mode of cognitive access such that readers imagine knowing about a person in that manner. Nevertheless, they probably imagine that their cognitive access to the person is in some ordinary manner or other
  • 19
    • 60949910304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 215, 218, 223, and 234-235
    • Wollheim, Painting as an Art, pp. 210, 215, 218, 223, and 234-235
    • Painting As An Art , pp. 210
    • Wollheim1
  • 22
    • 61149605158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Hopkins (among others) has argued for the plausible thesis that depiction is necessarily from a point of view ("Explaining Depiction," p. 428
    • Explaining Depiction , pp. 428
    • Hopkins, R.1
  • 23
    • 79954322949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Picture, Image and Experience, p. 36), while noting that there can be significant indeterminacies in a picture's perspective
    • Picture, Image and Experience , pp. 36
  • 24
    • 84922024375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • (Ambiguities also, I would add.) Dominic Lopes observes rightly that a picture need not represent things from a single point of view (Lopes, Understanding Pictures [New York: Oxford University Press, 1996], p. 120). I think a picture might conceivably lack a point of view entirely but that this virtually never happens
    • (1996) Understanding Pictures , pp. 120
    • Lopes1
  • 25
    • 85050909609 scopus 로고
    • Make-Believe, and Its Role in Pictorial Representation and the Acquisition of Knowledge
    • My point here is essentially the same as that of an example I introduced in another place of two circular films or videos of a roller coaster ride, one made with a camera fixed to the roller coaster and gyrating with it, the other made with a camera remaining rigidly upright. What is portrayed, what the viewer sees in the (moving) picture, is the same in the two cases, but they are sure to affect viewers very differently. Picture perception is not just a matter of ascertaining what is true in the world of the picture, as I put it there, or of what we see in the picture surface, even what we see to be included in the "represented space." The difference between the two films cannot be explained in terms of what we see in them. Cf. Kendall Walton, "Make-Believe, and Its Role in Pictorial Representation and the Acquisition of Knowledge," Philosophic Exchange 23 (1993): 81-95
    • (1993) Philosophic Exchange , vol.23 , pp. 81-95
    • Walton, K.1
  • 26
    • 1342325192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press
    • Reprinted in Aesthetics, ed. Susan Feagin and Patrick Maynard (Oxford University Press, 1997)
    • (1997) Aesthetics
    • Feagin, S.1    Maynard, P.2
  • 28
  • 29
    • 0033249184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From Thought to Action: Effects of Process- Versus Outcome-Based Mental Simulations on Performance
    • Cf., for example, the studies described by Lien B. Pham and Shelley E. Taylor, "From Thought to Action: Effects of Process- Versus Outcome-Based Mental Simulations on Performance," Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin 25 (1999): 250-260
    • (1999) Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin , vol.25 , pp. 250-260
    • Pham, L.B.1    Taylor, S.E.2
  • 31
    • 0032043620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harnessing the Imagination: Mental Simulation, Self-Regulation, and Coping
    • and Shelley E. Taylor, Lien B. Pham, Inna D. Rivkin, and David A. Armor, "Harnessing the Imagination: Mental Simulation, Self-Regulation, and Coping," American Psychologist 53 (1998):429-439
    • (1998) American Psychologist , vol.53 , pp. 429-439
    • Taylor, S.E.1    Pham, L.B.2    Rivkin, I.D.3    Armor, D.A.4
  • 32
    • 79954042052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wollheim claimed that the make-believe theory has "grave difficulties" in accounting for this phenomenon (Paintings as an Art, p. 360, n.8)
    • Paintings As An Art , Issue.8 , pp. 360
  • 34
    • 79954243295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will not examine the most obvious difference between Levinson and Wollheim: Levinson rejects the necessity of twofoldness, which Wollheim has always taken to be at the very heart of his conception of seeing-in.
    • I will not examine the most obvious difference between Levinson and Wollheim: Levinson rejects the necessity of "twofoldness," which Wollheim has always taken to be at the very heart of his conception of seeing-in
  • 35
    • 61049436323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wollheim on Pictorial Representation
    • emphasis in original
    • "Wollheim on Pictorial Representation," p. 229, emphasis in original
  • 36
    • 84921299359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Making Believe
    • Cornell University Press
    • Jerrold Levinson, "Making Believe," in The Pleasures of Aesthetics (Cornell University Press, 1996), p. 294
    • (1996) The Pleasures of Aesthetics , pp. 294
    • Levinson, J.1
  • 37
    • 79954056407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Wollheim on Pictorial Representation," p. 232, n.3, emphasis in original. Wollheim expressly allows for imaginings being involuntary or passive rather than active, and so does not share Levinson's conception of imagining
    • Wollheim on Pictorial Representation , Issue.3 , pp. 232
  • 38
    • 34250798943 scopus 로고
    • Imagination and Identification
    • 69 ff, Harvard University Press
    • Cf. Wollheim, "Imagination and Identification," in On Art and the Mind (Harvard University Press, 1974), pp. 69 ff
    • (1974) On Art and the Mind
    • Wollheim, C.1
  • 39
    • 79954222133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mimesis as Make-Believe, pp. 293-352.
    • See Mimesis as Make-Believe, pp. 293-352
  • 40
    • 0033474058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Internal and External Pictures
    • Catherine Abell and Gregory Currie, "Internal and External Pictures," Philosophical Psychology 12 (1999): 440-441
    • (1999) Philosophical Psychology , vol.12 , pp. 440-441
    • Abell, C.1    Currie, G.2
  • 41
    • 0009258630 scopus 로고
    • I do not know how Currie will square this suggestion with his skeptical remarks in, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • I do not know how Currie will square this suggestion with his skeptical remarks in Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy and Cognitive Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)
    • (1995) Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy and Cognitive Science
  • 42
    • 61049522795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Pictures and Photographs: Objections Answered
    • ed. Richard Allen and Murray Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • which I discuss in "On Pictures and Photographs: Objections Answered," in Film Theory and Philosophy, ed. Richard Allen and Murray Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), pp. 60-75
    • (1997) Film Theory and Philosophy , pp. 60-75
  • 43
    • 79954042047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I responded to this objection in Mimesis as Make-Believe, pp. 301-30 2.
    • I responded to this objection in Mimesis as Make-Believe, pp. 301-30 2
  • 44
    • 79954229525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. my exchange with Wollheim in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1991)
    • Cf. my exchange with Wollheim in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1991)
  • 47
    • 79954219589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Passionate Sightseer, review of Michael Podro, Depiction
    • More recently, Wollheim described me as "the major contemporary advocate of the theory that we relate to the content of pictures through the imagination rather than perceptually" ("A Passionate Sightseer," review of Michael Podro, Depiction, in The Times Literary Supplement 23 [April 1999], p. 20). I decline the honor, having designed my theory to establish and explain the fundamentally perceptual nature of pictorial representation
    • (1999) The Times Literary Supplement , vol.23 , pp. 20
  • 49
    • 84900774512 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Richard Wollheim, Art and Its Objects, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980), p. 207. My principles are not tied essentially to artists' intentions, as his standards of correctness are
    • (1980) Art and Its Objects. 2nd Ed. , pp. 207
    • Wollheim, R.1
  • 50
    • 0009118249 scopus 로고
    • My Transparent Pictures
    • If the recording is of an actual concert performance (as many of Gould's recordings are not), in hearing (directly) the sounds from the speakers, I am hearing, indirectly, the actual performance. I imagine my experience to be one of hearing the performance directly. (Cf. my "Transparent Pictures," in Critical Inquiry 11 [1984]: 246-277.)
    • (1984) Critical Inquiry , vol.11 , pp. 246-277
  • 51
    • 79954125412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am indebted to Malcolm Budd, David Hills, Jerrold Levinson, Patrick Maynard, and Richard Wollheim for discussions of the ideas in this essay
    • I am indebted to Malcolm Budd, David Hills, Jerrold Levinson, Patrick Maynard, and Richard Wollheim for discussions of the ideas in this essay


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.