메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 34, Issue 3, 2002, Pages

Sensualism and unconscious representations in Nietzsche's account of knowledge

(1)  Anderson, R Lanier a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60950698179     PISSN: 02705664     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/intstudphil200234310     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (20)

References (42)
  • 1
    • 0004212168 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press is a notable contribution to the literature on the doctrine
    • Nietzsche's "falsification thesis" claims that subjective features of cognitive agents inevitably influence their beliefs so as to falsify them. The term was brought to prominence by Maudemarie Clark, whose Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1990) is a notable contribution to the literature on the doctrine.
    • (1990) Whose Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy
    • Clark, M.1
  • 2
    • 0003804733 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press
    • See also Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 1985), pp. 42-73.
    • (1985) Nietzsche: Life As Literature , pp. 42-73
    • Nehamas, A.1
  • 3
    • 33748159118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Overcoming Charity: The Case of Maudemarie Clark's Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy
    • I discuss Clark's views and their importance in R. Lanier Anderson, "Overcoming Charity: The Case of Maudemarie Clark's Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy," Nietzsche-Studien 25 (1996): 307-41.
    • (1996) Nietzsche-Studien , vol.25 , pp. 307-341
    • Anderson, R.L.1
  • 5
    • 79955278370 scopus 로고
    • 7th, following the 2nd, ed. , ed. H. Cohen (Leipzig: J. Baedeker [1876]) 107 ff
    • "Sensualismus" was a standard term for empiricism in nineteenth-century German discussions. For examples of the usage, see F. A. Lange, Geschichte des Materialismus und Kritik seiner Bedeutung in der Gegenwart, 7th, following the 2nd, ed. , ed. H. Cohen (Leipzig: J. Baedeker, 1902 [1876]), vol. II, pp. 107 ff.
    • (1902) Geschichte des Materialismus und Kritik Seiner Bedeutung in der Gegenwart , vol.2
    • Lange, F.A.1
  • 7
    • 79955321580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elsewhere in Nietzsche, e. g. , GS 370, 372;
    • Elsewhere in Nietzsche, see, e. g. , GS 370, 372
  • 8
    • 79955264917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BGE 11,14
    • BGE 11,14
  • 9
    • 60950496084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WP 516
    • WP 516.
  • 11
    • 0039745449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press
    • For two quite different approaches to the will to power doctrine, which both emphasize the importance of unconscious drives and affects see John Richardson, Nietzsche's System (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1996), pp. 21, 35-39
    • (1996) Nietzsche's System
    • Richardson, J.1
  • 12
    • 0003968611 scopus 로고
    • trans. H. Tomlinson New York: Columbia Univ. Press
    • and Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. H. Tomlinson (New York: Columbia Univ. Press, 1983), pp. 39-72.
    • (1983) Nietzsche and Philosophy , pp. 39-72
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 13
    • 50249182239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Urbana: Univ. of Illinois Press), chs. 6-7
    • Relevant discussions include Stephen Hales and Rex Welshon, Nietzsche's Perspectivism (Urbana: Univ. of Illinois Press, 2000), chs. 6-7
    • (2000) Nietzsche's Perspectivism
    • Hales, S.1    Welshon, R.2
  • 15
    • 0004159339 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge, ch. 5;
    • Richard Schacht, Nietzsche (London: Routledge, 1983), ch. 5
    • (1983) Nietzsche
    • Schacht, R.1
  • 19
    • 0040040260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. D. Smith (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 34 ff
    • Pierre Klossowski, Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle, trans. D. Smith (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1997), pp. 26, 34 ff.
    • (1997) Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle , pp. 26
    • Klossowski, P.1
  • 20
    • 79955242264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. M. Gendre Albany: SUNY Press, ch. 5, esp
    • and Michel Haar, Nietzsche and Metaphysics, trans. M. Gendre (Albany: SUNY Press, 1996), ch. 5, esp. pp. 88-93.
    • (1996) Nietzsche and Metaphysics , pp. 88-93
    • Haar, M.1
  • 21
    • 79955348821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BGE 3, 5-6, 19, 20, 23, 32, 34, 54, 191, 192, 230, 231;
    • BGE 3, 5-6, 19, 20, 23, 32, 34, 54, 191, 192, 230, 231
  • 22
    • 79955168729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GM II, esp. 1, 16
    • GM II, esp. 1, 16
  • 23
    • 79955340534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TI "Reason" 5, and "World" 3-6
    • TI "Reason" 5, and "World" 3-6.
  • 24
    • 79955243273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G. W. Leibniz, New Essays on Human Understanding, trans. P. Remnant and J. Bennett (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1981), p. 53. Citations use the abbreviation NE.
    • G. W. Leibniz, New Essays on Human Understanding, trans. P. Remnant and J. Bennett (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1981), p. 53. Citations use the abbreviation NE.
  • 25
    • 60950544138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Changing the Cartesian Mind
    • See Alison Simmons, "Changing the Cartesian Mind," The Philosophical Review 110 (2001): 31-75.
    • (2001) The Philosophical Review , vol.110 , pp. 31-75
    • Simmons, A.1
  • 26
    • 79955235642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Poellner, Nietzsche and Metaphysics, p. 219; more generally pp. 218-22.
    • Poellner, Nietzsche and Metaphysics, p. 219; see more generally pp. 218-22.
  • 27
    • 79955276236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Poellner does consider Leibniz's view (Nietzsche and Metaphysics, pp. 222-23), and concludes that (on at least one construal) it is unproblematic.
    • Poellner does consider Leibniz's view (Nietzsche and Metaphysics, pp. 222-23), and concludes that (on at least one construal) it is unproblematic.
  • 28
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. P. Guyer and A. Wood Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press B 95-109
    • Once a logical subject is treated as a condition of its predicates in this way, it is a short step to equate it with a substance, which serves as the condition for its accidents. The association was definitively established in nineteenth-century German philosophy by Kant's argument in the "metaphysical deduction" of the categories, which traced the category of substance to the categorical ("S is P") form of judgment (see Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. P. Guyer and A. Wood [Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1998], A 70-83/B 95-109).
    • (1998) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Kant, I.1
  • 29
    • 79955360123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and similar remarks at GM I:13
    • and similar remarks at GM I:13
  • 30
    • 79955180085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TI "Reason" 5 and "World" 3
    • TI "Reason" 5 and "World" 3.
  • 31
    • 0007554995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Knowledge, Truth, and Value: Nietzsche's Debt to Schopenhauer and the Development of his Empiricism
    • Christopher Janaway, ed, Oxford: Clarendon
    • See, e. g. , Maudemarie Clark, "On Knowledge, Truth, and Value: Nietzsche's Debt to Schopenhauer and the Development of his Empiricism," in Christopher Janaway, ed. , Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche's Educator (Oxford: Clarendon, 1998), pp. 37-78
    • (1998) Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer As Nietzsche's Educator , pp. 37-78
    • Clark, M.1
  • 32
    • 0040866607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche
    • Janaway, ed. esp. 239, 237-51
    • and to some extent also Brian Leiter, "The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche," in Janaway, ed. , Willing and Nothingness, pp. 217-57, esp. 239, 237-51.
    • Willing and Nothingness , pp. 217-257
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 33
    • 79955352633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lange (N. B. : Translations from Lange are mine. )
    • Lange, Geschichte des Materialismus, vol. II, p. 31. (N. B. : Translations from Lange are mine. )
    • Geschichte des Materialismus , vol.2 , pp. 31
  • 34
    • 79955292866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stanford Univ. : unpublished manuscript
    • For discussion, see Nadeem Hussain "Nietzsche's Positivism" (Stanford Univ. : unpublished manuscript).
    • Nietzsche's Positivism
    • Hussain, N.1
  • 35
    • 79955208044 scopus 로고
    • trans. T. J. McCormack Chicago: Open Court, but all translations here are mine
    • This work was originally published in English as Popular Scientific Lectures, trans. T. J. McCormack (Chicago: Open Court, 1894), but all translations here are mine.
    • (1894) English As Popular Scientific Lectures
  • 36
    • 79955199562 scopus 로고
    • The Economical Nature of Physical Research
    • Mach from the early, reprinted in
    • See also Mach, "The Economical Nature of Physical Research" (from the early 1880s, reprinted in Populär-wissenschaftliche Vorlesungen, pp. 215-42).
    • (1880) Populär-wissenschaftliche Vorlesungen , pp. 215-242
  • 37
    • 79955340532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E. Mach, Contributions to the Analysis of the Sensations, trans. C. M. Williams (Chicago: Open Court, 1910 [1886])
    • He developed the ideas in more detail in E. Mach, Contributions to the Analysis of the Sensations, trans. C. M. Williams (Chicago: Open Court, 1910 [1886]), which first appeared the same year as BGE, and was part of Nietzsche's library.
  • 39
    • 21244434433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Truth and Objectivity in Perspectivism
    • esp. pp. 10-12
    • I have argued elsewhere (R. Lanier Anderson, "Truth and Objectivity in Perspectivism," Synthese 115 [1998]: 1-32, esp. pp. 10-12) that in this passage, Nietzsche means to follow Kant's arguments against the possibility of our possessing a power of intellectual intuition, which would deliver direct knowledge of the essences of independent substances, or "things in themselves. " Without such a capacity, our knowledge is subject to strict limits, which Nietzsche characterizes through the notion of perspectival conditions on knowledge (and Kant through his idea of formal conditions of experience, which limit our knowledge to appearances).
    • (1998) Synthese , vol.115 , pp. 1-32
    • Anderson, R.L.1
  • 40
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • B 71-2, A 51/B 75, B 135, B 138-9, B 145, et passim
    • For Kant's treatment of the issue, see Critique of Pure Reason, B 68, B 71-2, A 51/B 75, B 135, B 138-9, B 145, et passim.
    • Critique of Pure Reason
  • 41
    • 79955284403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an interesting discussion of this problem of the " selectiveness" of our representations, and its relation to Nietzsche's falsification thesis, see Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature, pp. 47-62. Contrary to the view advocated here, Nehamas suggests that there is a route from the partial or selective character of our representations of the world to Nietzsche's conclusion that they are all false in some sense. (Nehamas emphasizes the thought that our commitments tend to be accompanied by a false higher-order belief that they offer complete accounts of the relevant subject matter, when in fact they are always only partial. ) While some passages do suggest the picture Nehamas paints, it seems to me that the balance of the texts favors attribution of the stronger thesis that even our first-order accounts themselves betray the "falsifying" influence of perspective. I therefore prefer the account I have offered, which takes perspectivism to arise from the systematic transformation of experience by our cognitive activity, not just from its selective character.
    • Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life As Literature , pp. 47-62


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.