-
1
-
-
61049530812
-
The logical status of fictional discourse
-
Expression and Meaning Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 58-75, 75
-
P. 73 of John Searle, "The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse", first published in New Literary History vol. VI, 1974-75, pp. 319-332, and included in Expression and Meaning (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 58-75. Page references are to the latter.
-
(1974)
New Literary History
, vol.6
, pp. 319-332
-
-
Searle, J.1
-
2
-
-
0007262361
-
Language-created language-independent entities
-
P. 157 of Spring
-
P. 157 of Stephen Schiffer, "Language-Created Language-Independent Entities", Philosophical Topics vol. 24, no. 1, Spring, 1996, pp. 149-167, emphasis his.
-
(1996)
Philosophical Topics
, vol.24
, Issue.1
, pp. 149-167
-
-
Schiffer, S.1
-
3
-
-
34250231529
-
The problem of non-existents, I. Internalism
-
On page 130 of "The Problem of Non-Existents, I. Internalism", Topoi 1(1982), pp. 97-140
-
(1982)
Topoi
, vol.1
, pp. 97-140
-
-
-
5
-
-
0011087972
-
Nonexistence
-
Nathan Salmon would say that Coyle did create an individual. Such a view severs the tie between creation and pretense, and therefore is not a version of pretensetheoretical creationism. See his "Nonexistence", Noûs 32:3(1998), pp. 277-319.
-
(1998)
Noûs
, vol.32
, Issue.3
, pp. 277-319
-
-
-
6
-
-
34248749117
-
Commitment
-
James E. Tomberlin Boston & Oxford: Blackwell
-
Mark Richard expresses reservations about Salmon's view, in "Commitment", Philosophical Perspectives 12, language, Mind, and Ontology, 1998 (ed.) James E. Tomberlin (Boston & Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 255-281.
-
(1998)
Philosophical Perspectives 12, Language, Mind, and Ontology
, pp. 255-281
-
-
Richard, M.1
-
7
-
-
52649164553
-
Creatures of fiction
-
P. 305 of his "Creatures of Fiction", American Philosophical Quarterly, 14:4, 1977, pp. 299-308, emphasis his.
-
(1977)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.14
, Issue.4
, pp. 299-308
-
-
-
8
-
-
0040310755
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Gregory Curry makes a similar point while defending the notion of truth in fiction. See his The Nature of Fiction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), pp. 4-9.
-
(1990)
The Nature of Fiction
, pp. 4-9
-
-
Curry, G.1
-
9
-
-
9444269588
-
Fiction and metaphysics
-
See his "Fiction and metaphysics", Philosophy and Literature 7:1, 1983, pp. 67-77.
-
(1983)
Philosophy and Literature
, vol.7
, Issue.1
, pp. 67-77
-
-
-
10
-
-
0039718815
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Amie L. Thomasson, Fiction and Metaphysics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999) pp. 144-145.
-
(1999)
Fiction and Metaphysics
, pp. 144-145
-
-
Thomasson, A.L.1
-
11
-
-
79953665706
-
Pierre menard, author of the quixote
-
New York: New Directions, I find their reasoning highly unpersuasive
-
This allows the possibility for someone to write the story independently of Doyle. Some people think that such a story would not be the same story as A Study in Scarlet. Cf. Jorge Luis Borges, "Pierre Menard, Author of the Quixote", Ficciones (New York: New Directions, 1964). I find their reasoning highly unpersuasive.
-
(1964)
Ficciones
-
-
Borges, J.L.1
-
12
-
-
84870838988
-
People who know only the rules of pronunciation can read a spanish text aloud well enough that spaniards can understand it, even though the readers have no idea what they are saying
-
New York: Scientific American Library, A Division of HPHLP
-
Even when instantiations of sentences are produced by someone intentionally, his/her mental states need not determine the interpretation. As George A. Miller observes, "People who know only the rules of pronunciation can read a Spanish text aloud well enough that Spaniards can understand it, even though the readers have no idea what they are saying." See his The Science of Words (New York: Scientific American Library, A Division of HPHLP, 1991), p. 56.
-
(1991)
The Science of Words
, pp. 56
-
-
Miller, G.A.1
-
13
-
-
33748187786
-
Intentions in words
-
March
-
Also see Herman Cappelen, "Intentions in Words", Noûs 33:1, March 1999, pp. 92-102.
-
(1999)
Noûs
, vol.33
, Issue.1
, pp. 92-102
-
-
Cappelen, H.1
|